mirror of
https://github.com/opsxcq/mirror-textfiles.com.git
synced 2025-09-01 00:51:52 +02:00
477 lines
28 KiB
Plaintext
477 lines
28 KiB
Plaintext
350 BC
|
|
|
|
ON MEMORY AND REMINISCENCE
|
|
|
|
by Aristotle
|
|
|
|
translated by J. I. Beare
|
|
|
|
1
|
|
|
|
WE have, in the next place, to treat of Memory and Remembering,
|
|
considering its nature, its cause, and the part of the soul to which
|
|
this experience, as well as that of Recollecting, belongs. For the
|
|
persons who possess a retentive memory are not identical with those
|
|
who excel in power of recollection; indeed, as a rule, slow people
|
|
have a good memory, whereas those who are quick-witted and clever
|
|
are better at recollecting.
|
|
|
|
We must first form a true conception of these objects of memory, a
|
|
point on which mistakes are often made. Now to remember the future
|
|
is not possible, but this is an object of opinion or expectation
|
|
(and indeed there might be actually a science of expectation, like
|
|
that of divination, in which some believe); nor is there memory of the
|
|
present, but only sense-perception. For by the latter we know not
|
|
the future, nor the past, but the present only. But memory relates
|
|
to the past. No one would say that he remembers the present, when it
|
|
is present, e.g. a given white object at the moment when he sees it;
|
|
nor would one say that he remembers an object of scientific
|
|
contemplation at the moment when he is actually contemplating it,
|
|
and has it full before his mind;-of the former he would say only
|
|
that he perceives it, of the latter only that he knows it. But when
|
|
one has scientific knowledge, or perception, apart from the
|
|
actualizations of the faculty concerned, he thus 'remembers' (that the
|
|
angles of a triangle are together equal to two right angles); as to
|
|
the former, that he learned it, or thought it out for himself, as to
|
|
the latter, that he heard, or saw, it, or had some such sensible
|
|
experience of it. For whenever one exercises the faculty of
|
|
remembering, he must say within himself, 'I formerly heard (or
|
|
otherwise perceived) this,' or 'I formerly had this thought'.
|
|
|
|
Memory is, therefore, neither Perception nor Conception, but a state
|
|
or affection of one of these, conditioned by lapse of time. As already
|
|
observed, there is no such thing as memory of the present while
|
|
present, for the present is object only of perception, and the future,
|
|
of expectation, but the object of memory is the past. All memory,
|
|
therefore, implies a time elapsed; consequently only those animals
|
|
which perceive time remember, and the organ whereby they perceive time
|
|
is also that whereby they remember.
|
|
|
|
The subject of 'presentation' has been already considered in our
|
|
work On the Soul. Without a presentation intellectual activity is
|
|
impossible. For there is in such activity an incidental affection
|
|
identical with one also incidental in geometrical demonstrations.
|
|
For in the latter case, though we do not for the purpose of the
|
|
proof make any use of the fact that the quantity in the triangle
|
|
(for example, which we have drawn) is determinate, we nevertheless
|
|
draw it determinate in quantity. So likewise when one exerts the
|
|
intellect (e.g. on the subject of first principles), although the
|
|
object may not be quantitative, one envisages it as quantitative,
|
|
though he thinks it in abstraction from quantity; while, on the
|
|
other hand, if the object of the intellect is essentially of the class
|
|
of things that are quantitative, but indeterminate, one envisages it
|
|
as if it had determinate quantity, though subsequently, in thinking
|
|
it, he abstracts from its determinateness. Why we cannot exercise
|
|
the intellect on any object absolutely apart from the continuous, or
|
|
apply it even to non-temporal things unless in connexion with time, is
|
|
another question. Now, one must cognize magnitude and motion by
|
|
means of the same faculty by which one cognizes time (i.e. by that
|
|
which is also the faculty of memory), and the presentation (involved
|
|
in such cognition) is an affection of the sensus communis; whence this
|
|
follows, viz. that the cognition of these objects (magnitude, motion
|
|
time) is effected by the (said sensus communis, i.e. the) primary
|
|
faculty of perception. Accordingly, memory (not merely of sensible,
|
|
but) even of intellectual objects involves a presentation: hence we
|
|
may conclude that it belongs to the faculty of intelligence only
|
|
incidentally, while directly and essentially it belongs to the primary
|
|
faculty of sense-perception.
|
|
|
|
Hence not only human beings and the beings which possess opinion
|
|
or intelligence, but also certain other animals, possess memory. If
|
|
memory were a function of (pure) intellect, it would not have been
|
|
as it is an attribute of many of the lower animals, but probably, in
|
|
that case, no mortal beings would have had memory; since, even as
|
|
the case stands, it is not an attribute of them all, just because
|
|
all have not the faculty of perceiving time. Whenever one actually
|
|
remembers having seen or heard, or learned, something, he includes
|
|
in this act (as we have already observed) the consciousness of
|
|
'formerly'; and the distinction of 'former' and 'latter' is a
|
|
distinction in time.
|
|
|
|
Accordingly if asked, of which among the parts of the soul memory is
|
|
a function, we reply: manifestly of that part to which
|
|
'presentation' appertains; and all objects capable of being
|
|
presented (viz. aistheta) are immediately and properly objects of
|
|
memory, while those (viz. noeta) which necessarily involve (but only
|
|
involve) presentation are objects of memory incidentally.
|
|
|
|
One might ask how it is possible that though the affection (the
|
|
presentation) alone is present, and the (related) fact absent, the
|
|
latter-that which is not present-is remembered. (The question arises),
|
|
because it is clear that we must conceive that which is generated
|
|
through sense-perception in the sentient soul, and in the part of
|
|
the body which is its seat-viz. that affection the state whereof we
|
|
call memory-to be some such thing as a picture. The process of
|
|
movement (sensory stimulation) involved the act of perception stamps
|
|
in, as it were, a sort of impression of the percept, just as persons
|
|
do who make an impression with a seal. This explains why, in those who
|
|
are strongly moved owing to passion, or time of life, no mnemonic
|
|
impression is formed; just as no impression would be formed if the
|
|
movement of the seal were to impinge on running water; while there are
|
|
others in whom, owing to the receiving surface being frayed, as
|
|
happens to (the stucco on) old (chamber) walls, or owing to the
|
|
hardness of the receiving surface, the requisite impression is not
|
|
implanted at all. Hence both very young and very old persons are
|
|
defective in memory; they are in a state of flux, the former because
|
|
of their growth, the latter, owing to their decay. In like manner,
|
|
also, both those who are too quick and those who are too slow have bad
|
|
memories. The former are too soft, the latter too hard (in the texture
|
|
of their receiving organs), so that in the case of the former the
|
|
presented image (though imprinted) does not remain in the soul,
|
|
while on the latter it is not imprinted at all.
|
|
|
|
But then, if this truly describes what happens in the genesis of
|
|
memory, (the question stated above arises:) when one remembers, is
|
|
it this impressed affection that he remembers, or is it the
|
|
objective thing from which this was derived? If the former, it would
|
|
follow that we remember nothing which is absent; if the latter, how is
|
|
it possible that, though perceiving directly only the impression, we
|
|
remember that absent thing which we do not perceive? Granted that
|
|
there is in us something like an impression or picture, why should the
|
|
perception of the mere impression be memory of something else, instead
|
|
of being related to this impression alone? For when one actually
|
|
remembers, this impression is what he contemplates, and this is what
|
|
he perceives. How then does he remember what is not present? One might
|
|
as well suppose it possible also to see or hear that which is not
|
|
present. In reply, we suggest that this very thing is quite
|
|
conceivable, nay, actually occurs in experience. A picture painted
|
|
on a panel is at once a picture and a likeness: that is, while one and
|
|
the same, it is both of these, although the 'being' of both is not the
|
|
same, and one may contemplate it either as a picture, or as a
|
|
likeness. Just in the same way we have to conceive that the mnemonic
|
|
presentation within us is something which by itself is merely an
|
|
object of contemplation, while, in-relation to something else, it is
|
|
also a presentation of that other thing. In so far as it is regarded
|
|
in itself, it is only an object of contemplation, or a presentation;
|
|
but when considered as relative to something else, e.g. as its
|
|
likeness, it is also a mnemonic token. Hence, whenever the residual
|
|
sensory process implied by it is actualized in consciousness, if the
|
|
soul perceives this in so far as it is something absolute, it
|
|
appears to occur as a mere thought or presentation; but if the soul
|
|
perceives it qua related to something else, then,-just as when one
|
|
contemplates the painting in the picture as being a likeness, and
|
|
without having (at the moment) seen the actual Koriskos,
|
|
contemplates it as a likeness of Koriskos, and in that case the
|
|
experience involved in this contemplation of it (as relative) is
|
|
different from what one has when he contemplates it simply as a
|
|
painted figure-(so in the case of memory we have the analogous
|
|
difference for), of the objects in the soul, the one (the unrelated
|
|
object) presents itself simply as a thought, but the other (the
|
|
related object) just because, as in the painting, it is a likeness,
|
|
presents itself as a mnemonic token.
|
|
|
|
We can now understand why it is that sometimes, when we have such
|
|
processes, based on some former act of perception, occurring in the
|
|
soul, we do not know whether this really implies our having had
|
|
perceptions corresponding to them, and we doubt whether the case is or
|
|
is not one of memory. But occasionally it happens that (while thus
|
|
doubting) we get a sudden idea and recollect that we heard or saw
|
|
something formerly. This (occurrence of the 'sudden idea') happens
|
|
whenever, from contemplating a mental object as absolute, one
|
|
changes his point of view, and regards it as relative to something
|
|
else.
|
|
|
|
The opposite (sc. to the case of those who at first do not recognize
|
|
their phantasms as mnemonic) also occurs, as happened in the cases
|
|
of Antipheron of Oreus and others suffering from mental derangement;
|
|
for they were accustomed to speak of their mere phantasms as facts
|
|
of their past experience, and as if remembering them. This takes place
|
|
whenever one contemplates what is not a likeness as if it were a
|
|
likeness.
|
|
|
|
Mnemonic exercises aim at preserving one's memory of something by
|
|
repeatedly reminding him of it; which implies nothing else (on the
|
|
learner's part) than the frequent contemplation of something (viz. the
|
|
'mnemonic', whatever it may be) as a likeness, and not as out of
|
|
relation.
|
|
|
|
As regards the question, therefore, what memory or remembering is,
|
|
it has now been shown that it is the state of a presentation,
|
|
related as a likeness to that of which it is a presentation; and as to
|
|
the question of which of the faculties within us memory is a function,
|
|
(it has been shown) that it is a function of the primary faculty of
|
|
sense-perception, i.e. of that faculty whereby we perceive time.
|
|
|
|
2
|
|
|
|
Next comes the subject of Recollection, in dealing with which we
|
|
must assume as fundamental the truths elicited above in our
|
|
introductory discussions. For recollection is not the 'recovery' or
|
|
'acquisition' of memory; since at the instant when one at first learns
|
|
(a fact of science) or experiences (a particular fact of sense), he
|
|
does not thereby 'recover' a memory, inasmuch as none has preceded,
|
|
nor does he acquire one ab initio. It is only at the instant when
|
|
the aforesaid state or affection (of the aisthesis or upolepsis) is
|
|
implanted in the soul that memory exists, and therefore memory is
|
|
not itself implanted concurrently with the continuous implantation
|
|
of the (original) sensory experience.
|
|
|
|
Further: at the very individual and concluding instant when first
|
|
(the sensory experience or scientific knowledge) has been completely
|
|
implanted, there is then already established in the person affected
|
|
the (sensory) affection, or the scientific knowledge (if one ought
|
|
to apply the term 'scientific knowledge' to the (mnemonic) state or
|
|
affection; and indeed one may well remember, in the 'incidental'
|
|
sense, some of the things (i.e. ta katholou) which are properly
|
|
objects of scientific knowledge); but to remember, strictly and
|
|
properly speaking, is an activity which will not be immanent until the
|
|
original experience has undergone lapse of time. For one remembers now
|
|
what one saw or otherwise experienced formerly; the moment of the
|
|
original experience and the moment of the memory of it are never
|
|
identical.
|
|
|
|
Again, (even when time has elapsed, and one can be said really to
|
|
have acquired memory, this is not necessarily recollection, for
|
|
firstly) it is obviously possible, without any present act of
|
|
recollection, to remember as a continued consequence of the original
|
|
perception or other experience; whereas when (after an interval of
|
|
obliviscence) one recovers some scientific knowledge which he had
|
|
before, or some perception, or some other experience, the state of
|
|
which we above declared to be memory, it is then, and then only,
|
|
that this recovery may amount to a recollection of any of the things
|
|
aforesaid. But, (though as observed above, remembering does not
|
|
necessarily imply recollecting), recollecting always implies
|
|
remembering, and actualized memory follows (upon the successful act of
|
|
recollecting).
|
|
|
|
But secondly, even the assertion that recollection is the
|
|
reinstatement in consciousness of something which was there before but
|
|
had disappeared requires qualification. This assertion may be true,
|
|
but it may also be false; for the same person may twice learn (from
|
|
some teacher), or twice discover (i.e. excogitate), the same fact.
|
|
Accordingly, the act of recollecting ought (in its definition) to be
|
|
distinguished from these acts; i.e. recollecting must imply in those
|
|
who recollect the presence of some spring over and above that from
|
|
which they originally learn.
|
|
|
|
Acts of recollection, as they occur in experience, are due to the
|
|
fact that one movement has by nature another that succeeds it in
|
|
regular order.
|
|
|
|
If this order be necessary, whenever a subject experiences the
|
|
former of two movements thus connected, it will (invariably)
|
|
experience the latter; if, however, the order be not necessary, but
|
|
customary, only in the majority of cases will the subject experience
|
|
the latter of the two movements. But it is a fact that there are
|
|
some movements, by a single experience of which persons take the
|
|
impress of custom more deeply than they do by experiencing others many
|
|
times; hence upon seeing some things but once we remember them
|
|
better than others which we may have been frequently.
|
|
|
|
Whenever therefore, we are recollecting, we are experiencing certain
|
|
of the antecedent movements until finally we experience the one
|
|
after which customarily comes that which we seek. This explains why we
|
|
hunt up the series (of kineseis) having started in thought either from
|
|
a present intuition or some other, and from something either
|
|
similar, or contrary, to what we seek, or else from that which is
|
|
contiguous with it. Such is the empirical ground of the process of
|
|
recollection; for the mnemonic movements involved in these
|
|
starting-points are in some cases identical, in others, again,
|
|
simultaneous, with those of the idea we seek, while in others they
|
|
comprise a portion of them, so that the remnant which one
|
|
experienced after that portion (and which still requires to be excited
|
|
in memory) is comparatively small.
|
|
|
|
Thus, then, it is that persons seek to recollect, and thus, too,
|
|
it is that they recollect even without the effort of seeking to do so,
|
|
viz. when the movement implied in recollection has supervened on
|
|
some other which is its condition. For, as a rule, it is when
|
|
antecedent movements of the classes here described have first been
|
|
excited, that the particular movement implied in recollection follows.
|
|
We need not examine a series of which the beginning and end lie far
|
|
apart, in order to see how (by recollection) we remember; one in which
|
|
they lie near one another will serve equally well. For it is clear
|
|
that the method is in each case the same, that is, one hunts up the
|
|
objective series, without any previous search or previous
|
|
recollection. For (there is, besides the natural order, viz. the order
|
|
of the pralmata, or events of the primary experience, also a customary
|
|
order, and) by the effect of custom the mnemonic movements tend to
|
|
succeed one another in a certain order. Accordingly, therefore, when
|
|
one wishes to recollect, this is what he will do: he will try to
|
|
obtain a beginning of movement whose sequel shall be the movement
|
|
which he desires to reawaken. This explains why attempts at
|
|
recollection succeed soonest and best when they start from a beginning
|
|
(of some objective series). For, in order of succession, the
|
|
mnemonic movements are to one another as the objective facts (from
|
|
which they are derived). Accordingly, things arranged in a fixed
|
|
order, like the successive demonstrations in geometry, are easy to
|
|
remember (or recollect) while badly arranged subjects are remembered
|
|
with difficulty.
|
|
|
|
Recollecting differs also in this respect from relearning, that
|
|
one who recollects will be able, somehow, to move, solely by his own
|
|
effort, to the term next after the starting-point. When one cannot
|
|
do this of himself, but only by external assistance, he no longer
|
|
remembers (i.e. he has totally forgotten, and therefore of course
|
|
cannot recollect). It often happens that, though a person cannot
|
|
recollect at the moment, yet by seeking he can do so, and discovers
|
|
what he seeks. This he succeeds in doing by setting up many movements,
|
|
until finally he excites one of a kind which will have for its
|
|
sequel the fact he wishes to recollect. For remembering (which is
|
|
the condicio sine qua non of recollecting) is the existence,
|
|
potentially, in the mind of a movement capable of stimulating it to
|
|
the desired movement, and this, as has been said, in such a way that
|
|
the person should be moved (prompted to recollection) from within
|
|
himself, i.e. in consequence of movements wholly contained within
|
|
himself.
|
|
|
|
But one must get hold of a starting-point. This explains why it is
|
|
that persons are supposed to recollect sometimes by starting from
|
|
mnemonic loci. The cause is that they pass swiftly in thought from one
|
|
point to another, e.g. from milk to white, from white to mist, and
|
|
thence to moist, from which one remembers Autumn (the 'season of
|
|
mists'), if this be the season he is trying to recollect.
|
|
|
|
It seems true in general that the middle point also among all things
|
|
is a good mnemonic starting-point from which to reach any of them. For
|
|
if one does not recollect before, he will do so when he has come to
|
|
this, or, if not, nothing can help him; as, e.g. if one were to have
|
|
in mind the numerical series denoted by the symbols A, B, G, D, E,
|
|
Z, I, H, O. For, if he does not remember what he wants at E, then at E
|
|
he remembers O; because from E movement in either direction is
|
|
possible, to D or to Z. But, if it is not for one of these that he
|
|
is searching, he will remember (what he is searching for) when he
|
|
has come to G if he is searching for H or I. But if (it is) not (for H
|
|
or I that he is searching, but for one of the terms that remain), he
|
|
will remember by going to A, and so in all cases (in which one
|
|
starts from a middle point). The cause of one's sometimes recollecting
|
|
and sometimes not, though starting from the same point, is, that
|
|
from the same starting-point a movement can be made in several
|
|
directions, as, for instance, from G to I or to D. If, then, the
|
|
mind has not (when starting from E) moved in an old path (i.e. one
|
|
in which it moved first having the objective experience, and that,
|
|
therefore, in which un-'ethized' phusis would have it again move),
|
|
it tends to move to the more customary; for (the mind having, by
|
|
chance or otherwise, missed moving in the 'old' way) Custom now
|
|
assumes the role of Nature. Hence the rapidity with which we recollect
|
|
what we frequently think about. For as regular sequence of events is
|
|
in accordance with nature, so, too, regular sequence is observed in
|
|
the actualization of kinesis (in consciousness), and here frequency
|
|
tends to produce (the regularity of) nature. And since in the realm of
|
|
nature occurrences take place which are even contrary to nature, or
|
|
fortuitous, the same happens a fortiori in the sphere swayed by
|
|
custom, since in this sphere natural law is not similarly established.
|
|
Hence it is that (from the same starting-point) the mind receives an
|
|
impulse to move sometimes in the required direction, and at other
|
|
times otherwise, (doing the latter) particularly when something else
|
|
somehow deflects the mind from the right direction and attracts it
|
|
to itself. This last consideration explains too how it happens that,
|
|
when we want to remember a name, we remember one somewhat like it,
|
|
indeed, but blunder in reference to (i.e. in pronouncing) the one we
|
|
intended.
|
|
|
|
Thus, then, recollection takes place.
|
|
|
|
But the point of capital importance is that (for the purpose of
|
|
recollection) one should cognize, determinately or indeterminately,
|
|
the time-relation (of that which he wishes to recollect). There
|
|
is,-let it be taken as a fact,-something by which one distinguishes
|
|
a greater and a smaller time; and it is reasonable to think that one
|
|
does this in a way analogous to that in which one discerns (spacial)
|
|
magnitudes. For it is not by the mind's reaching out towards them,
|
|
as some say a visual ray from the eye does (in seeing), that one
|
|
thinks of large things at a distance in space (for even if they are
|
|
not there, one may similarly think them); but one does so by a
|
|
proportionate mental movement. For there are in the mind the like
|
|
figures and movements (i.e. 'like' to those of objects and events).
|
|
Therefore, when one thinks the greater objects, in what will his
|
|
thinking those differ from his thinking the smaller? (In nothing,)
|
|
because all the internal though smaller are as it were proportional to
|
|
the external. Now, as we may assume within a person something
|
|
proportional to the forms (of distant magnitudes), so, too, we may
|
|
doubtless assume also something else proportional to their
|
|
distances. As, therefore, if one has (psychically) the movement in AB,
|
|
BE, he constructs in thought (i.e. knows objectively) GD, since AG and
|
|
GD bear equal ratios respectively (to AB and BE), (so he who
|
|
recollects also proceeds). Why then does he construct GD rather than
|
|
ZH? Is it not because as AG is to AB, so is O to I? These movements
|
|
therefore (sc. in AB, BE, and in O:I) he has simultaneously. But if he
|
|
wishes to construct to thought ZH, he has in mind BE in like manner as
|
|
before (when constructing GD), but now, instead of (the movements of
|
|
the ratio) O:I, he has in mind (those of the ratio K:L; for
|
|
K:L::ZA:BA. (See diagram.)
|
|
|
|
When, therefore, the 'movement' corresponding to the object and that
|
|
corresponding to its time concur, then one actually remembers. If
|
|
one supposes (himself to move in these different but concurrent
|
|
ways) without really doing so, he supposes himself to remember.
|
|
|
|
For one may be mistaken, and think that he remembers when he
|
|
really does not. But it is not possible, conversely, that when one
|
|
actually remembers he should not suppose himself to remember, but
|
|
should remember unconsciously. For remembering, as we have conceived
|
|
it, essentially implies consciousness of itself. If, however, the
|
|
movement corresponding to the objective fact takes place without
|
|
that corresponding to the time, or, if the latter takes place
|
|
without the former, one does not remember.
|
|
|
|
The movement answering to the time is of two kinds. Sometimes in
|
|
remembering a fact one has no determinate time-notion of it, no such
|
|
notion as that e.g. he did something or other on the day before
|
|
yesterday; while in other cases he has a determinate notion-of the
|
|
time. Still, even though one does not remember with actual
|
|
determination of the time, he genuinely remembers, none the less.
|
|
Persons are wont to say that they remember (something), but yet do not
|
|
know when (it occurred, as happens) whenever they do not know
|
|
determinately the exact length of time implied in the 'when'.
|
|
|
|
It has been already stated that those who have a good memory are not
|
|
identical with those who are quick at recollecting. But the act of
|
|
recollecting differs from that of remembering, not only
|
|
chronologically, but also in this, that many also of the other animals
|
|
(as well as man) have memory, but, of all that we are acquainted with,
|
|
none, we venture to say, except man, shares in the faculty of
|
|
recollection. The cause of this is that recollection is, as it were
|
|
a mode of inference. For he who endeavours to recollect infers that he
|
|
formerly saw, or heard, or had some such experience, and the process
|
|
(by which he succeeds in recollecting) is, as it were, a sort of
|
|
investigation. But to investigate in this way belongs naturally to
|
|
those animals alone which are also endowed with the faculty of
|
|
deliberation; (which proves what was said above), for deliberation
|
|
is a form of inference.
|
|
|
|
That the affection is corporeal, i.e. that recollection is a
|
|
searching for an 'image' in a corporeal substrate, is proved by the
|
|
fact that in some persons, when, despite the most strenuous
|
|
application of thought, they have been unable to recollect, it (viz.
|
|
the anamnesis = the effort at recollection) excites a feeling of
|
|
discomfort, which, even though they abandon the effort at
|
|
recollection, persists in them none the less; and especially in
|
|
persons of melancholic temperament. For these are most powerfully
|
|
moved by presentations. The reason why the effort of recollection is
|
|
not under the control of their will is that, as those who throw a
|
|
stone cannot stop it at their will when thrown, so he who tries to
|
|
recollect and 'hunts' (after an idea) sets up a process in a
|
|
material part, (that) in which resides the affection. Those who have
|
|
moisture around that part which is the centre of sense-perception
|
|
suffer most discomfort of this kind. For when once the moisture has
|
|
been set in motion it is not easily brought to rest, until the idea
|
|
which was sought for has again presented itself, and thus the movement
|
|
has found a straight course. For a similar reason bursts of anger or
|
|
fits of terror, when once they have excited such motions, are not at
|
|
once allayed, even though the angry or terrified persons (by efforts
|
|
of will) set up counter motions, but the passions continue to move
|
|
them on, in the same direction as at first, in opposition to such
|
|
counter motions. The affection resembles also that in the case of
|
|
words, tunes, or sayings, whenever one of them has become inveterate
|
|
on the lips. People give them up and resolve to avoid them; yet
|
|
again they find themselves humming the forbidden air, or using the
|
|
prohibited word. Those whose upper parts are abnormally large, as.
|
|
is the case with dwarfs, have abnormally weak memory, as compared with
|
|
their opposites, because of the great weight which they have resting
|
|
upon the organ of perception, and because their mnemonic movements
|
|
are, from the very first, not able to keep true to a course, but are
|
|
dispersed, and because, in the effort at recollection, these movements
|
|
do not easily find a direct onward path. Infants and very old
|
|
persons have bad memories, owing to the amount of movement going on
|
|
within them; for the latter are in process of rapid decay, the
|
|
former in process of vigorous growth; and we may add that children,
|
|
until considerably advanced in years, are dwarf-like in their bodily
|
|
structure. Such then is our theory as regards memory and remembering
|
|
their nature, and the particular organ of the soul by which animals
|
|
remember; also as regards recollection, its formal definition, and the
|
|
manner and causes-of its performance.
|
|
|
|
-THE END-
|
|
.
|