mirror of
https://github.com/opsxcq/mirror-textfiles.com.git
synced 2025-09-01 00:51:52 +02:00
3683 lines
222 KiB
Plaintext
3683 lines
222 KiB
Plaintext
350 BC
|
|
|
|
ON THE HEAVENS
|
|
|
|
by Aristotle
|
|
|
|
translated by J. L. Stocks
|
|
|
|
Book I
|
|
|
|
1
|
|
|
|
THE science which has to do with nature clearly concerns itself
|
|
for the most part with bodies and magnitudes and their properties
|
|
and movements, but also with the principles of this sort of substance,
|
|
as many as they may be. For of things constituted by nature some are
|
|
bodies and magnitudes, some possess body and magnitude, and some are
|
|
principles of things which possess these. Now a continuum is that
|
|
which is divisible into parts always capable of subdivision, and a
|
|
body is that which is every way divisible. A magnitude if divisible
|
|
one way is a line, if two ways a surface, and if three a body.
|
|
Beyond these there is no other magnitude, because the three dimensions
|
|
are all that there are, and that which is divisible in three
|
|
directions is divisible in all. For, as the Pythagoreans say, the
|
|
world and all that is in it is determined by the number three, since
|
|
beginning and middle and end give the number of an 'all', and the
|
|
number they give is the triad. And so, having taken these three from
|
|
nature as (so to speak) laws of it, we make further use of the
|
|
number three in the worship of the Gods. Further, we use the terms
|
|
in practice in this way. Of two things, or men, we say 'both', but not
|
|
'all': three is the first number to which the term 'all' has been
|
|
appropriated. And in this, as we have said, we do but follow the
|
|
lead which nature gives. Therefore, since 'every' and 'all' and
|
|
'complete' do not differ from one another in respect of form, but
|
|
only, if at all, in their matter and in that to which they are
|
|
applied, body alone among magnitudes can be complete. For it alone
|
|
is determined by the three dimensions, that is, is an 'all'. But if it
|
|
is divisible in three dimensions it is every way divisible, while
|
|
the other magnitudes are divisible in one dimension or in two alone:
|
|
for the divisibility and continuity of magnitudes depend upon the
|
|
number of the dimensions, one sort being continuous in one
|
|
direction, another in two, another in all. All magnitudes, then, which
|
|
are divisible are also continuous. Whether we can also say that
|
|
whatever is continuous is divisible does not yet, on our present
|
|
grounds, appear. One thing, however, is clear. We cannot pass beyond
|
|
body to a further kind, as we passed from length to surface, and
|
|
from surface to body. For if we could, it would cease to be true
|
|
that body is complete magnitude. We could pass beyond it only in
|
|
virtue of a defect in it; and that which is complete cannot be
|
|
defective, since it has being in every respect. Now bodies which are
|
|
classed as parts of the whole are each complete according to our
|
|
formula, since each possesses every dimension. But each is
|
|
determined relatively to that part which is next to it by contact, for
|
|
which reason each of them is in a sense many bodies. But the whole
|
|
of which they are parts must necessarily be complete, and thus, in
|
|
accordance with the meaning of the word, have being, not in some
|
|
respect only, but in every respect.
|
|
|
|
2
|
|
|
|
The question as to the nature of the whole, whether it is infinite
|
|
in size or limited in its total mass, is a matter for subsequent
|
|
inquiry. We will now speak of those parts of the whole which are
|
|
specifically distinct. Let us take this as our starting-point. All
|
|
natural bodies and magnitudes we hold to be, as such, capable of
|
|
locomotion; for nature, we say, is their principle of movement. But
|
|
all movement that is in place, all locomotion, as we term it, is
|
|
either straight or circular or a combination of these two, which are
|
|
the only simple movements. And the reason of this is that these two,
|
|
the straight and the circular line, are the only simple magnitudes.
|
|
Now revolution about the centre is circular motion, while the upward
|
|
and downward movements are in a straight line, 'upward' meaning motion
|
|
away from the centre, and 'downward' motion towards it. All simple
|
|
motion, then, must be motion either away from or towards or about
|
|
the centre. This seems to be in exact accord with what we said
|
|
above: as body found its completion in three dimensions, so its
|
|
movement completes itself in three forms.
|
|
|
|
Bodies are either simple or compounded of such; and by simple bodies
|
|
I mean those which possess a principle of movement in their own
|
|
nature, such as fire and earth with their kinds, and whatever is
|
|
akin to them. Necessarily, then, movements also will be either
|
|
simple or in some sort compound-simple in the case of the simple
|
|
bodies, compound in that of the composite-and in the latter case the
|
|
motion will be that of the simple body which prevails in the
|
|
composition. Supposing, then, that there is such a thing as simple
|
|
movement, and that circular movement is an instance of it, and that
|
|
both movement of a simple body is simple and simple movement is of a
|
|
simple body (for if it is movement of a compound it will be in
|
|
virtue of a prevailing simple element), then there must necessarily be
|
|
some simple body which revolves naturally and in virtue of its own
|
|
nature with a circular movement. By constraint, of course, it may be
|
|
brought to move with the motion of something else different from
|
|
itself, but it cannot so move naturally, since there is one sort of
|
|
movement natural to each of the simple bodies. Again, if the unnatural
|
|
movement is the contrary of the natural and a thing can have no more
|
|
than one contrary, it will follow that circular movement, being a
|
|
simple motion, must be unnatural, if it is not natural, to the body
|
|
moved. If then (1) the body, whose movement is circular, is fire or
|
|
some other element, its natural motion must be the contrary of the
|
|
circular motion. But a single thing has a single contrary; and
|
|
upward and downward motion are the contraries of one another. If, on
|
|
the other hand, (2) the body moving with this circular motion which is
|
|
unnatural to it is something different from the elements, there will
|
|
be some other motion which is natural to it. But this cannot be. For
|
|
if the natural motion is upward, it will be fire or air, and if
|
|
downward, water or earth. Further, this circular motion is necessarily
|
|
primary. For the perfect is naturally prior to the imperfect, and
|
|
the circle is a perfect thing. This cannot be said of any straight
|
|
line:-not of an infinite line; for, if it were perfect, it would
|
|
have a limit and an end: nor of any finite line; for in every case
|
|
there is something beyond it, since any finite line can be extended.
|
|
And so, since the prior movement belongs to the body which naturally
|
|
prior, and circular movement is prior to straight, and movement in a
|
|
straight line belongs to simple bodies-fire moving straight upward and
|
|
earthy bodies straight downward towards the centre-since this is so,
|
|
it follows that circular movement also must be the movement of some
|
|
simple body. For the movement of composite bodies is, as we said,
|
|
determined by that simple body which preponderates in the composition.
|
|
These premises clearly give the conclusion that there is in nature
|
|
some bodily substance other than the formations we know, prior to them
|
|
all and more divine than they. But it may also be proved as follows.
|
|
We may take it that all movement is either natural or unnatural, and
|
|
that the movement which is unnatural to one body is natural to
|
|
another-as, for instance, is the case with the upward and downward
|
|
movements, which are natural and unnatural to fire and earth
|
|
respectively. It necessarily follows that circular movement, being
|
|
unnatural to these bodies, is the natural movement of some other.
|
|
Further, if, on the one hand, circular movement is natural to
|
|
something, it must surely be some simple and primary body which is
|
|
ordained to move with a natural circular motion, as fire is ordained
|
|
to fly up and earth down. If, on the other hand, the movement of the
|
|
rotating bodies about the centre is unnatural, it would be
|
|
remarkable and indeed quite inconceivable that this movement alone
|
|
should be continuous and eternal, being nevertheless contrary to
|
|
nature. At any rate the evidence of all other cases goes to show
|
|
that it is the unnatural which quickest passes away. And so, if, as
|
|
some say, the body so moved is fire, this movement is just as
|
|
unnatural to it as downward movement; for any one can see that fire
|
|
moves in a straight line away from the centre. On all these grounds,
|
|
therefore, we may infer with confidence that there is something beyond
|
|
the bodies that are about us on this earth, different and separate
|
|
from them; and that the superior glory of its nature is
|
|
proportionate to its distance from this world of ours.
|
|
|
|
3
|
|
|
|
In consequence of what has been said, in part by way of assumption
|
|
and in part by way of proof, it is clear that not every body either
|
|
possesses lightness or heaviness. As a preliminary we must explain
|
|
in what sense we are using the words 'heavy' and 'light',
|
|
sufficiently, at least, for our present purpose: we can examine the
|
|
terms more closely later, when we come to consider their essential
|
|
nature. Let us then apply the term 'heavy' to that which naturally
|
|
moves towards the centre, and 'light' to that which moves naturally
|
|
away from the centre. The heaviest thing will be that which sinks to
|
|
the bottom of all things that move downward, and the lightest that
|
|
which rises to the surface of everything that moves upward. Now,
|
|
necessarily, everything which moves either up or down possesses
|
|
lightness or heaviness or both-but not both relatively to the same
|
|
thing: for things are heavy and light relatively to one another;
|
|
air, for instance, is light relatively to water, and water light
|
|
relatively to earth. The body, then, which moves in a circle cannot
|
|
possibly possess either heaviness or lightness. For neither
|
|
naturally nor unnaturally can it move either towards or away from
|
|
the centre. Movement in a straight line certainly does not belong to
|
|
it naturally, since one sort of movement is, as we saw, appropriate to
|
|
each simple body, and so we should be compelled to identify it with
|
|
one of the bodies which move in this way. Suppose, then, that the
|
|
movement is unnatural. In that case, if it is the downward movement
|
|
which is unnatural, the upward movement will be natural; and if it
|
|
is the upward which is unnatural, the downward will be natural. For we
|
|
decided that of contrary movements, if the one is unnatural to
|
|
anything, the other will be natural to it. But since the natural
|
|
movement of the whole and of its part of earth, for instance, as a
|
|
whole and of a small clod-have one and the same direction, it results,
|
|
in the first place, that this body can possess no lightness or
|
|
heaviness at all (for that would mean that it could move by its own
|
|
nature either from or towards the centre, which, as we know, is
|
|
impossible); and, secondly, that it cannot possibly move in the way of
|
|
locomotion by being forced violently aside in an upward or downward
|
|
direction. For neither naturally nor unnaturally can it move with
|
|
any other motion but its own, either itself or any part of it, since
|
|
the reasoning which applies to the whole applies also to the part.
|
|
|
|
It is equally reasonable to assume that this body will be
|
|
ungenerated and indestructible and exempt from increase and
|
|
alteration, since everything that comes to be comes into being from
|
|
its contrary and in some substrate, and passes away likewise in a
|
|
substrate by the action of the contrary into the contrary, as we
|
|
explained in our opening discussions. Now the motions of contraries
|
|
are contrary. If then this body can have no contrary, because there
|
|
can be no contrary motion to the circular, nature seems justly to have
|
|
exempted from contraries the body which was to be ungenerated and
|
|
indestructible. For it is in contraries that generation and decay
|
|
subsist. Again, that which is subject to increase increases upon
|
|
contact with a kindred body, which is resolved into its matter. But
|
|
there is nothing out of which this body can have been generated. And
|
|
if it is exempt from increase and diminution, the same reasoning leads
|
|
us to suppose that it is also unalterable. For alteration is
|
|
movement in respect of quality; and qualitative states and
|
|
dispositions, such as health and disease, do not come into being
|
|
without changes of properties. But all natural bodies which change
|
|
their properties we see to be subject without exception to increase
|
|
and diminution. This is the case, for instance, with the bodies of
|
|
animals and their parts and with vegetable bodies, and similarly
|
|
also with those of the elements. And so, if the body which moves
|
|
with a circular motion cannot admit of increase or diminution, it is
|
|
reasonable to suppose that it is also unalterable.
|
|
|
|
The reasons why the primary body is eternal and not subject to
|
|
increase or diminution, but unaging and unalterable and unmodified,
|
|
will be clear from what has been said to any one who believes in our
|
|
assumptions. Our theory seems to confirm experience and to be
|
|
confirmed by it. For all men have some conception of the nature of the
|
|
gods, and all who believe in the existence of gods at all, whether
|
|
barbarian or Greek, agree in allotting the highest place to the deity,
|
|
surely because they suppose that immortal is linked with immortal
|
|
and regard any other supposition as inconceivable. If then there is,
|
|
as there certainly is, anything divine, what we have just said about
|
|
the primary bodily substance was well said. The mere evidence of the
|
|
senses is enough to convince us of this, at least with human
|
|
certainty. For in the whole range of time past, so far as our
|
|
inherited records reach, no change appears to have taken place
|
|
either in the whole scheme of the outermost heaven or in any of its
|
|
proper parts. The common name, too, which has been handed down from
|
|
our distant ancestors even to our own day, seems to show that they
|
|
conceived of it in the fashion which we have been expressing. The same
|
|
ideas, one must believe, recur in men's minds not once or twice but
|
|
again and again. And so, implying that the primary body is something
|
|
else beyond earth, fire, air, and water, they gave the highest place a
|
|
name of its own, aither, derived from the fact that it 'runs always'
|
|
for an eternity of time. Anaxagoras, however, scandalously misuses
|
|
this name, taking aither as equivalent to fire.
|
|
|
|
It is also clear from what has been said why the number of what we
|
|
call simple bodies cannot be greater than it is. The motion of a
|
|
simple body must itself be simple, and we assert that there are only
|
|
these two simple motions, the circular and the straight, the latter
|
|
being subdivided into motion away from and motion towards the centre.
|
|
|
|
4
|
|
|
|
That there is no other form of motion opposed as contrary to the
|
|
circular may be proved in various ways. In the first place, there is
|
|
an obvious tendency to oppose the straight line to the circular. For
|
|
concave and convex are a not only regarded as opposed to one
|
|
another, but they are also coupled together and treated as a unity
|
|
in opposition to the straight. And so, if there is a contrary to
|
|
circular motion, motion in a straight line must be recognized as
|
|
having the best claim to that name. But the two forms of rectilinear
|
|
motion are opposed to one another by reason of their places; for up
|
|
and down is a difference and a contrary opposition in place. Secondly,
|
|
it may be thought that the same reasoning which holds good of the
|
|
rectilinear path applies also the circular, movement from A to B being
|
|
opposed as contrary to movement from B to A. But what is meant is
|
|
still rectilinear motion. For that is limited to a single path,
|
|
while the circular paths which pass through the same two points are
|
|
infinite in number. Even if we are confined to the single semicircle
|
|
and the opposition is between movement from C to D and from D to C
|
|
along that semicircle, the case is no better. For the motion is the
|
|
same as that along the diameter, since we invariably regard the
|
|
distance between two points as the length of the straight line which
|
|
joins them. It is no more satisfactory to construct a circle and treat
|
|
motion 'along one semicircle as contrary to motion along the other.
|
|
For example, taking a complete circle, motion from E to F on the
|
|
semicircle G may be opposed to motion from F to E on the semicircle H.
|
|
But even supposing these are contraries, it in no way follows that the
|
|
reverse motions on the complete circumference contraries. Nor again
|
|
can motion along the circle from A to B be regarded as the contrary of
|
|
motion from A to C: for the motion goes from the same point towards
|
|
the same point, and contrary motion was distinguished as motion from a
|
|
contrary to its contrary. And even if the motion round a circle is the
|
|
contrary of the reverse motion, one of the two would be ineffective:
|
|
for both move to the same point, because that which moves in a circle,
|
|
at whatever point it begins, must necessarily pass through all the
|
|
contrary places alike. (By contrarieties of place I mean up and
|
|
down, back and front, and right and left; and the contrary oppositions
|
|
of movements are determined by those of places.) One of the motions,
|
|
then, would be ineffective, for if the two motions were of equal
|
|
strength, there would be no movement either way, and if one of the two
|
|
were preponderant, the other would be inoperative. So that if both
|
|
bodies were there, one of them, inasmuch as it would not be moving
|
|
with its own movement, would be useless, in the sense in which a
|
|
shoe is useless when it is not worn. But God and nature create nothing
|
|
that has not its use.
|
|
|
|
5
|
|
|
|
This being clear, we must go on to consider the questions which
|
|
remain. First, is there an infinite body, as the majority of the
|
|
ancient philosophers thought, or is this an impossibility? The
|
|
decision of this question, either way, is not unimportant, but
|
|
rather all-important, to our search for the truth. It is this
|
|
problem which has practically always been the source of the
|
|
differences of those who have written about nature as a whole. So it
|
|
has been and so it must be; since the least initial deviation from the
|
|
truth is multiplied later a thousandfold. Admit, for instance, the
|
|
existence of a minimum magnitude, and you will find that the minimum
|
|
which you have introduced, small as it is, causes the greatest
|
|
truths of mathematics to totter. The reason is that a principle is
|
|
great rather in power than in extent; hence that which was small at
|
|
the start turns out a giant at the end. Now the conception of the
|
|
infinite possesses this power of principles, and indeed in the
|
|
sphere of quantity possesses it in a higher degree than any other
|
|
conception; so that it is in no way absurd or unreasonable that the
|
|
assumption that an infinite body exists should be of peculiar moment
|
|
to our inquiry. The infinite, then, we must now discuss, opening the
|
|
whole matter from the beginning.
|
|
|
|
Every body is necessarily to be classed either as simple or as
|
|
composite; the infinite body, therefore, will be either simple or
|
|
composite.
|
|
|
|
But it is clear, further, that if the simple bodies are finite,
|
|
the composite must also be finite, since that which is composed of
|
|
bodies finite both in number and in magnitude is itself finite in
|
|
respect of number and magnitude: its quantity is in fact the same as
|
|
that of the bodies which compose it. What remains for us to
|
|
consider, then, is whether any of the simple bodies can be infinite in
|
|
magnitude, or whether this is impossible. Let us try the primary
|
|
body first, and then go on to consider the others.
|
|
|
|
The body which moves in a circle must necessarily be finite in every
|
|
respect, for the following reasons. (1) If the body so moving is
|
|
infinite, the radii drawn from the centre will be infinite. But the
|
|
space between infinite radii is infinite: and by the space between the
|
|
radii I mean the area outside which no magnitude which is in contact
|
|
with the two lines can be conceived as falling. This, I say, will be
|
|
infinite: first, because in the case of finite radii it is always
|
|
finite; and secondly, because in it one can always go on to a width
|
|
greater than any given width; thus the reasoning which forces us to
|
|
believe in infinite number, because there is no maximum, applies
|
|
also to the space between the radii. Now the infinite cannot be
|
|
traversed, and if the body is infinite the interval between the
|
|
radii is necessarily infinite: circular motion therefore is an
|
|
impossibility. Yet our eyes tell us that the heavens revolve in a
|
|
circle, and by argument also we have determined that there is
|
|
something to which circular movement belongs.
|
|
|
|
(2) Again, if from a finite time a finite time be subtracted, what
|
|
remains must be finite and have a beginning. And if the time of a
|
|
journey has a beginning, there must be a beginning also of the
|
|
movement, and consequently also of the distance traversed. This
|
|
applies universally. Take a line, ACE, infinite in one direction, E,
|
|
and another line, BB, infinite in both directions. Let ACE describe
|
|
a circle, revolving upon C as centre. In its movement it will cut BB
|
|
continuously for a certain time. This will be a finite time, since the
|
|
total time is finite in which the heavens complete their circular
|
|
orbit, and consequently the time subtracted from it, during which
|
|
the one line in its motion cuts the other, is also finite. Therefore
|
|
there will be a point at which ACE began for the first time to cut BB.
|
|
This, however, is impossible. The infinite, then, cannot revolve in
|
|
a circle; nor could the world, if it were infinite.
|
|
|
|
(3) That the infinite cannot move may also be shown as follows.
|
|
Let A be a finite line moving past the finite line, B. Of necessity
|
|
A will pass clear of B and B of A at the same moment; for each
|
|
overlaps the other to precisely the same extent. Now if the two were
|
|
both moving, and moving in contrary directions, they would pass
|
|
clear of one another more rapidly; if one were still and the other
|
|
moving past it, less rapidly; provided that the speed of the latter
|
|
were the same in both cases. This, however, is clear: that it is
|
|
impossible to traverse an infinite line in a finite time. Infinite
|
|
time, then, would be required. (This we demonstrated above in the
|
|
discussion of movement.) And it makes no difference whether a finite
|
|
is passing by an infinite or an infinite by a finite. For when A is
|
|
passing B, then B overlaps A and it makes no difference whether B is
|
|
moved or unmoved, except that, if both move, they pass clear of one
|
|
another more quickly. It is, however, quite possible that a moving
|
|
line should in certain cases pass one which is stationary quicker than
|
|
it passes one moving in an opposite direction. One has only to imagine
|
|
the movement to be slow where both move and much faster where one is
|
|
stationary. To suppose one line stationary, then, makes no
|
|
difficulty for our argument, since it is quite possible for A to
|
|
pass B at a slower rate when both are moving than when only one is.
|
|
If, therefore, the time which the finite moving line takes to pass the
|
|
other is infinite, then necessarily the time occupied by the motion of
|
|
the infinite past the finite is also infinite. For the infinite to
|
|
move at all is thus absolutely impossible; since the very smallest
|
|
movement conceivable must take an infinity of time. Moreover the
|
|
heavens certainly revolve, and they complete their circular orbit in a
|
|
finite time; so that they pass round the whole extent of any line
|
|
within their orbit, such as the finite line AB. The revolving body,
|
|
therefore, cannot be infinite.
|
|
|
|
(4) Again, as a line which has a limit cannot be infinite, or, if it
|
|
is infinite, is so only in length, so a surface cannot be infinite
|
|
in that respect in which it has a limit; or, indeed, if it is
|
|
completely determinate, in any respect whatever. Whether it be a
|
|
square or a circle or a sphere, it cannot be infinite, any more than a
|
|
foot-rule can. There is then no such thing as an infinite sphere or
|
|
square or circle, and where there is no circle there can be no
|
|
circular movement, and similarly where there is no infinite at all
|
|
there can be no infinite movement; and from this it follows that, an
|
|
infinite circle being itself an impossibility, there can be no
|
|
circular motion of an infinite body.
|
|
|
|
(5) Again, take a centre C, an infinite line, AB, another infinite
|
|
line at right angles to it, E, and a moving radius, CD. CD will
|
|
never cease contact with E, but the position will always be
|
|
something like CE, CD cutting E at F. The infinite line, therefore,
|
|
refuses to complete the circle.
|
|
|
|
(6) Again, if the heaven is infinite and moves in a circle, we shall
|
|
have to admit that in a finite time it has traversed the infinite. For
|
|
suppose the fixed heaven infinite, and that which moves within it
|
|
equal to it. It results that when the infinite body has completed
|
|
its revolution, it has traversed an infinite equal to itself in a
|
|
finite time. But that we know to be impossible.
|
|
|
|
(7) It can also be shown, conversely, that if the time of revolution
|
|
is finite, the area traversed must also be finite; but the area
|
|
traversed was equal to itself; therefore, it is itself finite.
|
|
|
|
We have now shown that the body which moves in a circle is not
|
|
endless or infinite, but has its limit.
|
|
|
|
6
|
|
|
|
Further, neither that which moves towards nor that which moves
|
|
away from the centre can be infinite. For the upward and downward
|
|
motions are contraries and are therefore motions towards contrary
|
|
places. But if one of a pair of contraries is determinate, the other
|
|
must be determinate also. Now the centre is determined; for, from
|
|
whatever point the body which sinks to the bottom starts its
|
|
downward motion, it cannot go farther than the centre. The centre,
|
|
therefore, being determinate, the upper place must also be
|
|
determinate. But if these two places are determined and finite, the
|
|
corresponding bodies must also be finite. Further, if up and down
|
|
are determinate, the intermediate place is also necessarily
|
|
determinate. For, if it is indeterminate, the movement within it
|
|
will be infinite; and that we have already shown to be an
|
|
impossibility. The middle region then is determinate, and consequently
|
|
any body which either is in it, or might be in it, is determinate. But
|
|
the bodies which move up and down may be in it, since the one moves
|
|
naturally away from the centre and the other towards it.
|
|
|
|
From this alone it is clear that an infinite body is an
|
|
impossibility; but there is a further point. If there is no such thing
|
|
as infinite weight, then it follows that none of these bodies can be
|
|
infinite. For the supposed infinite body would have to be infinite
|
|
in weight. (The same argument applies to lightness: for as the one
|
|
supposition involves infinite weight, so the infinity of the body
|
|
which rises to the surface involves infinite lightness.) This is
|
|
proved as follows. Assume the weight to be finite, and take an
|
|
infinite body, AB, of the weight C. Subtract from the infinite body
|
|
a finite mass, BD, the weight of which shall be E. E then is less than
|
|
C, since it is the weight of a lesser mass. Suppose then that the
|
|
smaller goes into the greater a certain number of times, and take BF
|
|
bearing the same proportion to BD which the greater weight bears to
|
|
the smaller. For you may subtract as much as you please from an
|
|
infinite. If now the masses are proportionate to the weights, and
|
|
the lesser weight is that of the lesser mass, the greater must be that
|
|
of the greater. The weights, therefore, of the finite and of the
|
|
infinite body are equal. Again, if the weight of a greater body is
|
|
greater than that of a less, the weight of GB will be greater than
|
|
that of FB; and thus the weight of the finite body is greater than
|
|
that of the infinite. And, further, the weight of unequal masses
|
|
will be the same, since the infinite and the finite cannot be equal.
|
|
It does not matter whether the weights are commensurable or not. If
|
|
(a) they are incommensurable the same reasoning holds. For instance,
|
|
suppose E multiplied by three is rather more than C: the weight of
|
|
three masses of the full size of BD will be greater than C. We thus
|
|
arrive at the same impossibility as before. Again (b) we may assume
|
|
weights which are commensurate; for it makes no difference whether
|
|
we begin with the weight or with the mass. For example, assume the
|
|
weight E to be commensurate with C, and take from the infinite mass
|
|
a part BD of weight E. Then let a mass BF be taken having the same
|
|
proportion to BD which the two weights have to one another. (For the
|
|
mass being infinite you may subtract from it as much as you please.)
|
|
These assumed bodies will be commensurate in mass and in weight alike.
|
|
Nor again does it make any difference to our demonstration whether the
|
|
total mass has its weight equally or unequally distributed. For it
|
|
must always be Possible to take from the infinite mass a body of equal
|
|
weight to BD by diminishing or increasing the size of the section to
|
|
the necessary extent.
|
|
|
|
From what we have said, then, it is clear that the weight of the
|
|
infinite body cannot be finite. It must then be infinite. We have
|
|
therefore only to show this to be impossible in order to prove an
|
|
infinite body impossible. But the impossibility of infinite weight can
|
|
be shown in the following way. A given weight moves a given distance
|
|
in a given time; a weight which is as great and more moves the same
|
|
distance in a less time, the times being in inverse proportion to
|
|
the weights. For instance, if one weight is twice another, it will
|
|
take half as long over a given movement. Further, a finite weight
|
|
traverses any finite distance in a finite time. It necessarily follows
|
|
from this that infinite weight, if there is such a thing, being, on
|
|
the one hand, as great and more than as great as the finite, will move
|
|
accordingly, but being, on the other hand, compelled to move in a time
|
|
inversely proportionate to its greatness, cannot move at all. The time
|
|
should be less in proportion as the weight is greater. But there is no
|
|
proportion between the infinite and the finite: proportion can only
|
|
hold between a less and a greater finite time. And though you may
|
|
say that the time of the movement can be continually diminished, yet
|
|
there is no minimum. Nor, if there were, would it help us. For some
|
|
finite body could have been found greater than the given finite in the
|
|
same proportion which is supposed to hold between the infinite and the
|
|
given finite; so that an infinite and a finite weight must have
|
|
traversed an equal distance in equal time. But that is impossible.
|
|
Again, whatever the time, so long as it is finite, in which the
|
|
infinite performs the motion, a finite weight must necessarily move
|
|
a certain finite distance in that same time. Infinite weight is
|
|
therefore impossible, and the same reasoning applies also to
|
|
infinite lightness. Bodies then of infinite weight and of infinite
|
|
lightness are equally impossible.
|
|
|
|
That there is no infinite body may be shown, as we have shown it, by
|
|
a detailed consideration of the various cases. But it may also be
|
|
shown universally, not only by such reasoning as we advanced in our
|
|
discussion of principles (though in that passage we have already
|
|
determined universally the sense in which the existence of an infinite
|
|
is to be asserted or denied), but also suitably to our present purpose
|
|
in the following way. That will lead us to a further question. Even if
|
|
the total mass is not infinite, it may yet be great enough to admit
|
|
a plurality of universes. The question might possibly be raised
|
|
whether there is any obstacle to our believing that there are other
|
|
universes composed on the pattern of our own, more than one, though
|
|
stopping short of infinity. First, however, let us treat of the
|
|
infinite universally.
|
|
|
|
7
|
|
|
|
Every body must necessarily be either finite or infinite, and if
|
|
infinite, either of similar or of dissimilar parts. If its parts are
|
|
dissimilar, they must represent either a finite or an infinite
|
|
number of kinds. That the kinds cannot be infinite is evident, if
|
|
our original presuppositions remain unchallenged. For the primary
|
|
movements being finite in number, the kinds of simple body are
|
|
necessarily also finite, since the movement of a simple body is
|
|
simple, and the simple movements are finite, and every natural body
|
|
must always have its proper motion. Now if the infinite body is to
|
|
be composed of a finite number of kinds, then each of its parts must
|
|
necessarily be infinite in quantity, that is to say, the water,
|
|
fire, &c., which compose it. But this is impossible, because, as we
|
|
have already shown, infinite weight and lightness do not exist.
|
|
Moreover it would be necessary also that their places should be
|
|
infinite in extent, so that the movements too of all these bodies
|
|
would be infinite. But this is not possible, if we are to hold to
|
|
the truth of our original presuppositions and to the view that neither
|
|
that which moves downward, nor, by the same reasoning, that which
|
|
moves upward, can prolong its movement to infinity. For it is true
|
|
in regard to quality, quantity, and place alike that any process of
|
|
change is impossible which can have no end. I mean that if it is
|
|
impossible for a thing to have come to be white, or a cubit long, or
|
|
in Egypt, it is also impossible for it to be in process of coming to
|
|
be any of these. It is thus impossible for a thing to be moving to a
|
|
place at which in its motion it can never by any possibility arrive.
|
|
Again, suppose the body to exist in dispersion, it may be maintained
|
|
none the less that the total of all these scattered particles, say, of
|
|
fire, is infinite. But body we saw to be that which has extension
|
|
every way. How can there be several dissimilar elements, each
|
|
infinite? Each would have to be infinitely extended every way.
|
|
|
|
It is no more conceivable, again, that the infinite should exist
|
|
as a whole of similar parts. For, in the first place, there is no
|
|
other (straight) movement beyond those mentioned: we must therefore
|
|
give it one of them. And if so, we shall have to admit either infinite
|
|
weight or infinite lightness. Nor, secondly, could the body whose
|
|
movement is circular be infinite, since it is impossible for the
|
|
infinite to move in a circle. This, indeed, would be as good as saying
|
|
that the heavens are infinite, which we have shown to be impossible.
|
|
|
|
Moreover, in general, it is impossible that the infinite should move
|
|
at all. If it did, it would move either naturally or by constraint:
|
|
and if by constraint, it possesses also a natural motion, that is to
|
|
say, there is another place, infinite like itself, to which it will
|
|
move. But that is impossible.
|
|
|
|
That in general it is impossible for the infinite to be acted upon
|
|
by the finite or to act upon it may be shown as follows.
|
|
|
|
(1. The infinite cannot be acted upon by the finite.) Let A be an
|
|
infinite, B a finite, C the time of a given movement produced by one
|
|
in the other. Suppose, then, that A was heated, or impelled, or
|
|
modified in any way, or caused to undergo any sort of movement
|
|
whatever, by in the time C. Let D be less than B; and, assuming that a
|
|
lesser agent moves a lesser patient in an equal time, call the
|
|
quantity thus modified by D, E. Then, as D is to B, so is E to some
|
|
finite quantum. We assume that the alteration of equal by equal
|
|
takes equal time, and the alteration of less by less or of greater
|
|
by greater takes the same time, if the quantity of the patient is such
|
|
as to keep the proportion which obtains between the agents, greater
|
|
and less. If so, no movement can be caused in the infinite by any
|
|
finite agent in any time whatever. For a less agent will produce
|
|
that movement in a less patient in an equal time, and the
|
|
proportionate equivalent of that patient will be a finite quantity,
|
|
since no proportion holds between finite and infinite.
|
|
|
|
(2. The infinite cannot act upon the finite.) Nor, again, can
|
|
the infinite produce a movement in the finite in any time whatever.
|
|
Let A be an infinite, B a finite, C the time of action. In the time C,
|
|
D will produce that motion in a patient less than B, say F. Then
|
|
take E, bearing the same proportion to D as the whole BF bears to F. E
|
|
will produce the motion in BF in the time C. Thus the finite and
|
|
infinite effect the same alteration in equal times. But this is
|
|
impossible; for the assumption is that the greater effects it in a
|
|
shorter time. It will be the same with any time that can be taken,
|
|
so that there will no time in which the infinite can effect this
|
|
movement. And, as to infinite time, in that nothing can move another
|
|
or be moved by it. For such time has no limit, while the action and
|
|
reaction have.
|
|
|
|
(3. There is no interaction between infinites.) Nor can infinite
|
|
be acted upon in any way by infinite. Let A and B be infinites, CD
|
|
being the time of the action A of upon B. Now the whole B was modified
|
|
in a certain time, and the part of this infinite, E, cannot be so
|
|
modified in the same time, since we assume that a less quantity
|
|
makes the movement in a less time. Let E then, when acted upon by A,
|
|
complete the movement in the time D. Then, as D is to CD, so is E to
|
|
some finite part of B. This part will necessarily be moved by A in the
|
|
time CD. For we suppose that the same agent produces a given effect on
|
|
a greater and a smaller mass in longer and shorter times, the times
|
|
and masses varying proportionately. There is thus no finite time in
|
|
which infinites can move one another. Is their time then infinite? No,
|
|
for infinite time has no end, but the movement communicated has.
|
|
|
|
If therefore every perceptible body possesses the power of acting or
|
|
of being acted upon, or both of these, it is impossible that an
|
|
infinite body should be perceptible. All bodies, however, that
|
|
occupy place are perceptible. There is therefore no infinite body
|
|
beyond the heaven. Nor again is there anything of limited extent
|
|
beyond it. And so beyond the heaven there is no body at all. For if
|
|
you suppose it an object of intelligence, it will be in a
|
|
place-since place is what 'within' and 'beyond' denote-and therefore
|
|
an object of perception. But nothing that is not in a place is
|
|
perceptible.
|
|
|
|
The question may also be examined in the light of more general
|
|
considerations as follows. The infinite, considered as a whole of
|
|
similar parts, cannot, on the one hand, move in a circle. For there is
|
|
no centre of the infinite, and that which moves in a circle moves
|
|
about the centre. Nor again can the infinite move in a straight
|
|
line. For there would have to be another place infinite like itself to
|
|
be the goal of its natural movement and another, equally great, for
|
|
the goal of its unnatural movement. Moreover, whether its
|
|
rectilinear movement is natural or constrained, in either case the
|
|
force which causes its motion will have to be infinite. For infinite
|
|
force is force of an infinite body, and of an infinite body the
|
|
force is infinite. So the motive body also will be infinite. (The
|
|
proof of this is given in our discussion of movement, where it is
|
|
shown that no finite thing possesses infinite power, and no infinite
|
|
thing finite power.) If then that which moves naturally can also
|
|
move unnaturally, there will be two infinites, one which causes, and
|
|
another which exhibits the latter motion. Again, what is it that moves
|
|
the infinite? If it moves itself, it must be animate. But how can it
|
|
possibly be conceived as an infinite animal? And if there is something
|
|
else that moves it, there will be two infinites, that which moves
|
|
and that which is moved, differing in their form and power.
|
|
|
|
If the whole is not continuous, but exists, as Democritus and
|
|
Leucippus think, in the form of parts separated by void, there must
|
|
necessarily be one movement of all the multitude. They are
|
|
distinguished, we are told, from one another by their figures; but
|
|
their nature is one, like many pieces of gold separated from one
|
|
another. But each piece must, as we assert, have the same motion.
|
|
For a single clod moves to the same place as the whole mass of
|
|
earth, and a spark to the same place as the whole mass of fire. So
|
|
that if it be weight that all possess, no body is, strictly
|
|
speaking, light: and if lightness be universal, none is heavy.
|
|
Moreover, whatever possesses weight or lightness will have its place
|
|
either at one of the extremes or in the middle region. But this is
|
|
impossible while the world is conceived as infinite. And, generally,
|
|
that which has no centre or extreme limit, no up or down, gives the
|
|
bodies no place for their motion; and without that movement is
|
|
impossible. A thing must move either naturally or unnaturally, and the
|
|
two movements are determined by the proper and alien places. Again,
|
|
a place in which a thing rests or to which it moves unnaturally,
|
|
must be the natural place for some other body, as experience shows.
|
|
Necessarily, therefore, not everything possesses weight or
|
|
lightness, but some things do and some do not. From these arguments
|
|
then it is clear that the body of the universe is not infinite.
|
|
|
|
8
|
|
|
|
We must now proceed to explain why there cannot be more than one
|
|
heaven-the further question mentioned above. For it may be thought
|
|
that we have not proved universal of bodies that none whatever can
|
|
exist outside our universe, and that our argument applied only to
|
|
those of indeterminate extent.
|
|
|
|
Now all things rest and move naturally and by constraint. A thing
|
|
moves naturally to a place in which it rests without constraint, and
|
|
rests naturally in a place to which it moves without constraint. On
|
|
the other hand, a thing moves by constraint to a place in which it
|
|
rests by constraint, and rests by constraint in a place to which it
|
|
moves by constraint. Further, if a given movement is due to
|
|
constraint, its contrary is natural. If, then, it is by constraint
|
|
that earth moves from a certain place to the centre here, its movement
|
|
from here to there will be natural, and if earth from there rests here
|
|
without constraint, its movement hither will be natural. And the
|
|
natural movement in each case is one. Further, these worlds, being
|
|
similar in nature to ours, must all be composed of the same bodies
|
|
as it. Moreover each of the bodies, fire, I mean, and earth and
|
|
their intermediates, must have the same power as in our world. For
|
|
if these names are used equivocally, if the identity of name does
|
|
not rest upon an identity of form in these elements and ours, then the
|
|
whole to which they belong can only be called a world by equivocation.
|
|
Clearly, then, one of the bodies will move naturally away from the
|
|
centre and another towards the centre, since fire must be identical
|
|
with fire, earth with earth, and so on, as the fragments of each are
|
|
identical in this world. That this must be the case is evident from
|
|
the principles laid down in our discussion of the movements, for these
|
|
are limited in number, and the distinction of the elements depends
|
|
upon the distinction of the movements. Therefore, since the
|
|
movements are the same, the elements must also be the same everywhere.
|
|
The particles of earth, then, in another world move naturally also
|
|
to our centre and its fire to our circumference. This, however, is
|
|
impossible, since, if it were true, earth must, in its own world, move
|
|
upwards, and fire to the centre; in the same way the earth of our
|
|
world must move naturally away from the centre when it moves towards
|
|
the centre of another universe. This follows from the supposed
|
|
juxtaposition of the worlds. For either we must refuse to admit the
|
|
identical nature of the simple bodies in the various universes, or,
|
|
admitting this, we must make the centre and the extremity one as
|
|
suggested. This being so, it follows that there cannot be more
|
|
worlds than one.
|
|
|
|
To postulate a difference of nature in the simple bodies according
|
|
as they are more or less distant from their proper places is
|
|
unreasonable. For what difference can it make whether we say that a
|
|
thing is this distance away or that? One would have to suppose a
|
|
difference proportionate to the distance and increasing with it, but
|
|
the form is in fact the same. Moreover, the bodies must have some
|
|
movement, since the fact that they move is quite evident. Are we to
|
|
say then that all their movements, even those which are mutually
|
|
contrary, are due to constraint? No, for a body which has no natural
|
|
movement at all cannot be moved by constraint. If then the bodies have
|
|
a natural movement, the movement of the particular instances of each
|
|
form must necessarily have for goal a place numerically one, i.e. a
|
|
particular centre or a particular extremity. If it be suggested that
|
|
the goal in each case is one in form but numerically more than one, on
|
|
the analogy of particulars which are many though each undifferentiated
|
|
in form, we reply that the variety of goal cannot be limited to this
|
|
portion or that but must extend to all alike. For all are equally
|
|
undifferentiated in form, but any one is different numerically from
|
|
any other. What I mean is this: if the portions in this world behave
|
|
similarly both to one another and to those in another world, then
|
|
the portion which is taken hence will not behave differently either
|
|
from the portions in another world or from those in the same world,
|
|
but similarly to them, since in form no portion differs from
|
|
another. The result is that we must either abandon our present
|
|
assumption or assert that the centre and the extremity are each
|
|
numerically one. But this being so, the heaven, by the same evidence
|
|
and the same necessary inferences, must be one only and no more.
|
|
|
|
A consideration of the other kinds of movement also makes it plain
|
|
that there is some point to which earth and fire move naturally. For
|
|
in general that which is moved changes from something into
|
|
something, the starting-point and the goal being different in form,
|
|
and always it is a finite change. For instance, to recover health is
|
|
to change from disease to health, to increase is to change from
|
|
smallness to greatness. Locomotion must be similar: for it also has
|
|
its goal and starting-point--and therefore the starting-point and
|
|
the goal of the natural movement must differ in form-just as the
|
|
movement of coming to health does not take any direction which
|
|
chance or the wishes of the mover may select. Thus, too, fire and
|
|
earth move not to infinity but to opposite points; and since the
|
|
opposition in place is between above and below, these will be the
|
|
limits of their movement. (Even in circular movement there is a sort
|
|
of opposition between the ends of the diameter, though the movement as
|
|
a whole has no contrary: so that here too the movement has in a
|
|
sense an opposed and finite goal.) There must therefore be some end to
|
|
locomotion: it cannot continue to infinity.
|
|
|
|
This conclusion that local movement is not continued to infinity
|
|
is corroborated by the fact that earth moves more quickly the nearer
|
|
it is to the centre, and fire the nearer it is to the upper place. But
|
|
if movement were infinite speed would be infinite also; and if speed
|
|
then weight and lightness. For as superior speed in downward
|
|
movement implies superior weight, so infinite increase of weight
|
|
necessitates infinite increase of speed.
|
|
|
|
Further, it is not the action of another body that makes one of
|
|
these bodies move up and the other down; nor is it constraint, like
|
|
the 'extrusion' of some writers. For in that case the larger the
|
|
mass of fire or earth the slower would be the upward or downward
|
|
movement; but the fact is the reverse: the greater the mass of fire or
|
|
earth the quicker always is its movement towards its own place. Again,
|
|
the speed of the movement would not increase towards the end if it
|
|
were due to constraint or extrusion; for a constrained movement always
|
|
diminishes in speed as the source of constraint becomes more
|
|
distant, and a body moves without constraint to the place whence it
|
|
was moved by constraint.
|
|
|
|
A consideration of these points, then, gives adequate assurance of
|
|
the truth of our contentions. The same could also be shown with the
|
|
aid of the discussions which fall under First Philosophy, as well as
|
|
from the nature of the circular movement, which must be eternal both
|
|
here and in the other worlds. It is plain, too, from the following
|
|
considerations that the universe must be one.
|
|
|
|
The bodily elements are three, and therefore the places of the
|
|
elements will be three also; the place, first, of the body which sinks
|
|
to the bottom, namely the region about the centre; the place,
|
|
secondly, of the revolving body, namely the outermost place, and
|
|
thirdly, the intermediate place, belonging to the intermediate body.
|
|
Here in this third place will be the body which rises to the
|
|
surface; since, if not here, it will be elsewhere, and it cannot be
|
|
elsewhere: for we have two bodies, one weightless, one endowed with
|
|
weight, and below is place of the body endowed with weight, since
|
|
the region about the centre has been given to the heavy body. And
|
|
its position cannot be unnatural to it, for it would have to be
|
|
natural to something else, and there is nothing else. It must then
|
|
occupy the intermediate place. What distinctions there are within
|
|
the intermediate itself we will explain later on.
|
|
|
|
We have now said enough to make plain the character and number of
|
|
the bodily elements, the place of each, and further, in general, how
|
|
many in number the various places are.
|
|
|
|
9
|
|
|
|
We must show not only that the heaven is one, but also that more
|
|
than one heaven is and, further, that, as exempt from decay and
|
|
generation, the heaven is eternal. We may begin by raising a
|
|
difficulty. From one point of view it might seem impossible that the
|
|
heaven should be one and unique, since in all formations and
|
|
products whether of nature or of art we can distinguish the shape in
|
|
itself and the shape in combination with matter. For instance the form
|
|
of the sphere is one thing and the gold or bronze sphere another;
|
|
the shape of the circle again is one thing, the bronze or wooden
|
|
circle another. For when we state the essential nature of the sphere
|
|
or circle we do not include in the formula gold or bronze, because
|
|
they do not belong to the essence, but if we are speaking of the
|
|
copper or gold sphere we do include them. We still make the
|
|
distinction even if we cannot conceive or apprehend any other
|
|
example beside the particular thing. This may, of course, sometimes be
|
|
the case: it might be, for instance, that only one circle could be
|
|
found; yet none the less the difference will remain between the
|
|
being of circle and of this particular circle, the one being form, the
|
|
other form in matter, i.e. a particular thing. Now since the
|
|
universe is perceptible it must be regarded as a particular; for
|
|
everything that is perceptible subsists, as we know, in matter. But if
|
|
it is a particular, there will be a distinction between the being of
|
|
'this universe' and of 'universe' unqualified. There is a
|
|
difference, then, between 'this universe' and simple 'universe'; the
|
|
second is form and shape, the first form in combination with matter;
|
|
and any shape or form has, or may have, more than one particular
|
|
instance.
|
|
|
|
On the supposition of Forms such as some assert, this must be the
|
|
case, and equally on the view that no such entity has a separate
|
|
existence. For in every case in which the essence is in matter it is a
|
|
fact of observation that the particulars of like form are several or
|
|
infinite in number. Hence there either are, or may be, more heavens
|
|
than one. On these grounds, then, it might be inferred either that
|
|
there are or that there might be several heavens. We must, however,
|
|
return and ask how much of this argument is correct and how much not.
|
|
|
|
Now it is quite right to say that the formula of the shape apart
|
|
from the matter must be different from that of the shape in the
|
|
matter, and we may allow this to be true. We are not, however,
|
|
therefore compelled to assert a plurality of worlds. Such a
|
|
plurality is in fact impossible if this world contains the entirety of
|
|
matter, as in fact it does. But perhaps our contention can be made
|
|
clearer in this way. Suppose 'aquilinity' to be curvature in the
|
|
nose or flesh, and flesh to be the matter of aquilinity. Suppose
|
|
further, that all flesh came together into a single whole of flesh
|
|
endowed with this aquiline quality. Then neither would there be, nor
|
|
could there arise, any other thing that was aquiline. Similarly,
|
|
suppose flesh and bones to be the matter of man, and suppose a man
|
|
to be created of all flesh and all bones in indissoluble union. The
|
|
possibility of another man would be removed. Whatever case you took it
|
|
would be the same. The general rule is this: a thing whose essence
|
|
resides in a substratum of matter can never come into being in the
|
|
absence of all matter. Now the universe is certainly a particular
|
|
and a material thing: if however, it is composed not of a part but
|
|
of the whole of matter, then though the being of 'universe' and of
|
|
'this universe' are still distinct, yet there is no other universe,
|
|
and no possibility of others being made, because all the matter is
|
|
already included in this. It remains, then, only to prove that it is
|
|
composed of all natural perceptible body.
|
|
|
|
First, however, we must explain what we mean by 'heaven' and in
|
|
how many senses we use the word, in order to make clearer the object
|
|
of our inquiry. (a) In one sense, then, we call 'heaven' the substance
|
|
of the extreme circumference of the whole, or that natural body
|
|
whose place is at the extreme circumference. We recognize habitually a
|
|
special right to the name 'heaven' in the extremity or upper region,
|
|
which we take to be the seat of all that is divine. (b) In another
|
|
sense, we use this name for the body continuous with the extreme
|
|
circumference which contains the moon, the sun, and some of the stars;
|
|
these we say are 'in the heaven'. (c) In yet another sense we give the
|
|
name to all body included within extreme circumference, since we
|
|
habitually call the whole or totality 'the heaven'. The word, then, is
|
|
used in three senses.
|
|
|
|
Now the whole included within the extreme circumference must be
|
|
composed of all physical and sensible body, because there neither
|
|
is, nor can come into being, any body outside the heaven. For if there
|
|
is a natural body outside the extreme circumference it must be
|
|
either a simple or a composite body, and its position must be either
|
|
natural or unnatural. But it cannot be any of the simple bodies.
|
|
For, first, it has been shown that that which moves in a circle cannot
|
|
change its place. And, secondly, it cannot be that which moves from
|
|
the centre or that which lies lowest. Naturally they could not be
|
|
there, since their proper places are elsewhere; and if these are there
|
|
unnaturally, the exterior place will be natural to some other body,
|
|
since a place which is unnatural to one body must be natural to
|
|
another: but we saw that there is no other body besides these. Then it
|
|
is not possible that any simple body should be outside the heaven.
|
|
But, if no simple body, neither can any mixed body be there: for the
|
|
presence of the simple body is involved in the presence of the
|
|
mixture. Further neither can any body come into that place: for it
|
|
will do so either naturally or unnaturally, and will be either
|
|
simple or composite; so that the same argument will apply, since it
|
|
makes no difference whether the question is 'does A exist?' or
|
|
'could A come to exist?' From our arguments then it is evident not
|
|
only that there is not, but also that there could never come to be,
|
|
any bodily mass whatever outside the circumference. The world as a
|
|
whole, therefore, includes all its appropriate matter, which is, as we
|
|
saw, natural perceptible body. So that neither are there now, nor have
|
|
there ever been, nor can there ever be formed more heavens than one,
|
|
but this heaven of ours is one and unique and complete.
|
|
|
|
It is therefore evident that there is also no place or void or
|
|
time outside the heaven. For in every place body can be present; and
|
|
void is said to be that in which the presence of body, though not
|
|
actual, is possible; and time is the number of movement. But in the
|
|
absence of natural body there is no movement, and outside the
|
|
heaven, as we have shown, body neither exists nor can come to exist.
|
|
It is clear then that there is neither place, nor void, nor time,
|
|
outside the heaven. Hence whatever is there, is of such a nature as
|
|
not to occupy any place, nor does time age it; nor is there any change
|
|
in any of the things which lie beyond the outermost motion; they
|
|
continue through their entire duration unalterable and unmodified,
|
|
living the best and most selfsufficient of lives. As a matter of fact,
|
|
this word 'duration' possessed a divine significance for the ancients,
|
|
for the fulfilment which includes the period of life of any
|
|
creature, outside of which no natural development can fall, has been
|
|
called its duration. On the same principle the fulfilment of the whole
|
|
heaven, the fulfilment which includes all time and infinity, is
|
|
'duration'-a name based upon the fact that it is always-duration
|
|
immortal and divine. From it derive the being and life which other
|
|
things, some more or less articulately but others feebly, enjoy. So,
|
|
too, in its discussions concerning the divine, popular philosophy
|
|
often propounds the view that whatever is divine, whatever is
|
|
primary and supreme, is necessarily unchangeable. This fact confirms
|
|
what we have said. For there is nothing else stronger than it to
|
|
move it-since that would mean more divine-and it has no defect and
|
|
lacks none of its proper excellences. Its unceasing movement, then, is
|
|
also reasonable, since everything ceases to move when it comes to
|
|
its proper place, but the body whose path is the circle has one and
|
|
the same place for starting-point and goal.
|
|
|
|
10
|
|
|
|
Having established these distinctions, we may now proceed to the
|
|
question whether the heaven is ungenerated or generated,
|
|
indestructible or destructible. Let us start with a review of the
|
|
theories of other thinkers; for the proofs of a theory are
|
|
difficulties for the contrary theory. Besides, those who have first
|
|
heard the pleas of our adversaries will be more likely to credit the
|
|
assertions which we are going to make. We shall be less open to the
|
|
charge of procuring judgement by default. To give a satisfactory
|
|
decision as to the truth it is necessary to be rather an arbitrator
|
|
than a party to the dispute.
|
|
|
|
That the world was generated all are agreed, but, generation over,
|
|
some say that it is eternal, others say that it is destructible like
|
|
any other natural formation. Others again, with Empedliocles of
|
|
Acragas and Heraclitus of Ephesus, believe that there is alternation
|
|
in the destructive process, which takes now this direction, now
|
|
that, and continues without end.
|
|
|
|
Now to assert that it was generated and yet is eternal is to
|
|
assert the impossible; for we cannot reasonably attribute to
|
|
anything any characteristics but those which observation detects in
|
|
many or all instances. But in this case the facts point the other way:
|
|
generated things are seen always to be destroyed. Further, a thing
|
|
whose present state had no beginning and which could not have been
|
|
other than it was at any previous moment throughout its entire
|
|
duration, cannot possibly be changed. For there will have to be some
|
|
cause of change, and if this had been present earlier it would have
|
|
made possible another condition of that to which any other condition
|
|
was impossible. Suppose that the world was formed out of elements
|
|
which were formerly otherwise conditioned than as they are now. Then
|
|
(1) if their condition was always so and could not have been
|
|
otherwise, the world could never have come into being. And (2) if
|
|
the world did come into being, then, clearly, their condition must
|
|
have been capable of change and not eternal: after combination
|
|
therefore they will be dispersed, just as in the past after dispersion
|
|
they came into combination, and this process either has been, or could
|
|
have been, indefinitely repeated. But if this is so, the world
|
|
cannot be indestructible, and it does not matter whether the change of
|
|
condition has actually occurred or remains a possibility.
|
|
|
|
Some of those who hold that the world, though indestructible, was
|
|
yet generated, try to support their case by a parallel which is
|
|
illusory. They say that in their statements about its generation
|
|
they are doing what geometricians do when they construct their
|
|
figures, not implying that the universe really had a beginning, but
|
|
for didactic reasons facilitating understanding by exhibiting the
|
|
object, like the figure, as in course of formation. The two cases,
|
|
as we said, are not parallel; for, in the construction of the
|
|
figure, when the various steps are completed the required figure
|
|
forthwith results; but in these other demonstrations what results is
|
|
not that which was required. Indeed it cannot be so; for antecedent
|
|
and consequent, as assumed, are in contradiction. The ordered, it is
|
|
said, arose out of the unordered; and the same thing cannot be at
|
|
the same time both ordered and unordered; there must be a process
|
|
and a lapse of time separating the two states. In the figure, on the
|
|
other hand, there is no temporal separation. It is clear then that the
|
|
universe cannot be at once eternal and generated.
|
|
|
|
To say that the universe alternately combines and dissolves is no
|
|
more paradoxical than to make it eternal but varying in shape. It is
|
|
as if one were to think that there was now destruction and now
|
|
existence when from a child a man is generated, and from a man a
|
|
child. For it is clear that when the elements come together the result
|
|
is not a chance system and combination, but the very same as
|
|
before-especially on the view of those who hold this theory, since
|
|
they say that the contrary is the cause of each state. So that if
|
|
the totality of body, which is a continuum, is now in this order or
|
|
disposition and now in that, and if the combination of the whole is
|
|
a world or heaven, then it will not be the world that comes into being
|
|
and is destroyed, but only its dispositions.
|
|
|
|
If the world is believed to be one, it is impossible to suppose that
|
|
it should be, as a whole, first generated and then destroyed, never to
|
|
reappear; since before it came into being there was always present the
|
|
combination prior to it, and that, we hold, could never change if it
|
|
was never generated. If, on the other hand, the worlds are infinite in
|
|
number the view is more plausible. But whether this is, or is not,
|
|
impossible will be clear from what follows. For there are some who
|
|
think it possible both for the ungenerated to be destroyed and for the
|
|
generated to persist undestroyed. (This is held in the Timaeus,
|
|
where Plato says that the heaven, though it was generated, will none
|
|
the less exist to eternity.) So far as the heaven is concerned we have
|
|
answered this view with arguments appropriate to the nature of the
|
|
heaven: on the general question we shall attain clearness when we
|
|
examine the matter universally.
|
|
|
|
11
|
|
|
|
We must first distinguish the senses in which we use the words
|
|
'ungenerated' and 'generated', 'destructible' and 'indestructible'.
|
|
These have many meanings, and though it may make no difference to
|
|
the argument, yet some confusion of mind must result from treating
|
|
as uniform in its use a word which has several distinct
|
|
applications. The character which is the ground of the predication
|
|
will always remain obscure.
|
|
|
|
The word 'ungenerated' then is used (a) in one sense whenever
|
|
something now is which formerly was not, no process of becoming or
|
|
change being involved. Such is the case, according to some, with
|
|
contact and motion, since there is no process of coming to be in
|
|
contact or in motion. (b) It is used in another sense, when
|
|
something which is capable of coming to be, with or without process,
|
|
does not exist; such a thing is ungenerated in the sense that its
|
|
generation is not a fact but a possibility. (c) It is also applied
|
|
where there is general impossibility of any generation such that the
|
|
thing now is which then was not. And 'impossibility' has two uses:
|
|
first, where it is untrue to say that the thing can ever come into
|
|
being, and secondly, where it cannot do so easily, quickly, or well.
|
|
In the same way the word 'generated' is used, (a) first, where what
|
|
formerly was not afterwards is, whether a process of becoming was or
|
|
was not involved, so long as that which then was not, now is; (b)
|
|
secondly, of anything capable of existing, 'capable' being defined
|
|
with reference either to truth or to facility; (c) thirdly, of
|
|
anything to which the passage from not being to being belongs, whether
|
|
already actual, if its existence is due to a past process of becoming,
|
|
or not yet actual but only possible. The uses of the words
|
|
'destructible' and 'indestructible' are similar. 'Destructible' is
|
|
applied (a) to that which formerly was and afterwards either is not or
|
|
might not be, whether a period of being destroyed and changed
|
|
intervenes or not; and (b) sometimes we apply the word to that which a
|
|
process of destruction may cause not to be; and also (c) in a third
|
|
sense, to that which is easily destructible, to the 'easily
|
|
destroyed', so to speak. Of the indestructible the same account
|
|
holds good. It is either (a) that which now is and now is not, without
|
|
any process of destruction, like contact, which without being
|
|
destroyed afterwards is not, though formerly it was; or (b) that which
|
|
is but might not be, or which will at some time not be, though it
|
|
now is. For you exist now and so does the contact; yet both are
|
|
destructible, because a time will come when it will not be true of you
|
|
that you exist, nor of these things that they are in contact.
|
|
Thirdly (c) in its most proper use, it is that which is, but is
|
|
incapable of any destruction such that the thing which now is later
|
|
ceases to be or might cease to be; or again, that which has not yet
|
|
been destroyed, but in the future may cease to be. For
|
|
indestructible is also used of that which is destroyed with
|
|
difficulty.
|
|
|
|
This being so, we must ask what we mean by 'possible' and
|
|
'impossible'. For in its most proper use the predicate
|
|
'indestructible' is given because it is impossible that the thing
|
|
should be destroyed, i.e. exist at one time and not at another. And
|
|
'ungenerated' also involves impossibility when used for that which
|
|
cannot be generated, in such fashion that, while formerly it was
|
|
not, later it is. An instance is a commensurable diagonal. Now when we
|
|
speak of a power to move or to lift weights, we refer always to the
|
|
maximum. We speak, for instance, of a power to lift a hundred
|
|
talents or walk a hundred stades-though a power to effect the
|
|
maximum is also a power to effect any part of the maximum-since we
|
|
feel obliged in defining the power to give the limit or maximum. A
|
|
thing, then, which is within it. If, for example, a man can lift a
|
|
hundred talents, he can also lift two, and if he can walk a hundred
|
|
stades, he can also walk two. But the power is of the maximum, and a
|
|
thing said, with reference to its maximum, to be incapable of so
|
|
much is also incapable of any greater amount. It is, for instance,
|
|
clear that a person who cannot walk a thousand stades will also be
|
|
unable to walk a thousand and one. This point need not trouble us, for
|
|
we may take it as settled that what is, in the strict sense,
|
|
possible is determined by a limiting maximum. Now perhaps the
|
|
objection might be raised that there is no necessity in this, since he
|
|
who sees a stade need not see the smaller measures contained in it,
|
|
while, on the contrary, he who can see a dot or hear a small sound
|
|
will perceive what is greater. This, however, does not touch our
|
|
argument. The maximum may be determined either in the power or in
|
|
its object. The application of this is plain. Superior sight is
|
|
sight of the smaller body, but superior speed is that of the greater
|
|
body.
|
|
|
|
12
|
|
|
|
Having established these distinctions we car now proceed to the
|
|
sequel. If there are thing! capable both of being and of not being,
|
|
there must be some definite maximum time of their being and not being;
|
|
a time, I mean, during which continued existence is possible to them
|
|
and a time during which continued nonexistence is possible. And this
|
|
is true in every category, whether the thing is, for example, 'man',
|
|
or 'white', or 'three cubits long', or whatever it may be. For if
|
|
the time is not definite in quantity, but longer than any that can
|
|
be suggested and shorter than none, then it will be possible for one
|
|
and the same thing to exist for infinite time and not to exist for
|
|
another infinity. This, however, is impossible.
|
|
|
|
Let us take our start from this point. The impossible and the
|
|
false have not the same significance. One use of 'impossible' and
|
|
'possible', and 'false' and 'true', is hypothetical. It is impossible,
|
|
for instance, on a certain hypothesis that the triangle should have
|
|
its angles equal to two right angles, and on another the diagonal is
|
|
commensurable. But there are also things possible and impossible,
|
|
false and true, absolutely. Now it is one thing to be absolutely
|
|
false, and another thing to be absolutely impossible. To say that
|
|
you are standing when you are not standing is to assert a falsehood,
|
|
but not an impossibility. Similarly to say that a man who is playing
|
|
the harp, but not singing, is singing, is to say what is false but not
|
|
impossible. To say, however, that you are at once standing and
|
|
sitting, or that the diagonal is commensurable, is to say what is
|
|
not only false but also impossible. Thus it is not the same thing to
|
|
make a false and to make an impossible hypothesis, and from the
|
|
impossible hypothesis impossible results follow. A man has, it is
|
|
true, the capacity at once of sitting and of standing, because when he
|
|
possesses the one he also possesses the other; but it does not
|
|
follow that he can at once sit and stand, only that at another time he
|
|
can do the other also. But if a thing has for infinite time more
|
|
than one capacity, another time is impossible and the times must
|
|
coincide. Thus if a thing which exists for infinite time is
|
|
destructible, it will have the capacity of not being. Now if it exists
|
|
for infinite time let this capacity be actualized; and it will be in
|
|
actuality at once existent and non-existent. Thus a false conclusion
|
|
would follow because a false assumption was made, but if what was
|
|
assumed had not been impossible its consequence would not have been
|
|
impossible.
|
|
|
|
Anything then which always exists is absolutely imperishable. It
|
|
is also ungenerated, since if it was generated it will have the
|
|
power for some time of not being. For as that which formerly was,
|
|
but now is not, or is capable at some future time of not being, is
|
|
destructible, so that which is capable of formerly not having been
|
|
is generated. But in the case of that which always is, there is no
|
|
time for such a capacity of not being, whether the supposed time is
|
|
finite or infinite; for its capacity of being must include the
|
|
finite time since it covers infinite time.
|
|
|
|
It is therefore impossible that one and the same thing should be
|
|
capable of always existing and of always not-existing. And 'not always
|
|
existing', the contradictory, is also excluded. Thus it is
|
|
impossible for a thing always to exist and yet to be destructible.
|
|
Nor, similarly, can it be generated. For of two attributes if B cannot
|
|
be present without A, the impossibility A of proves the
|
|
impossibility of B. What always is, then, since it is incapable of
|
|
ever not being, cannot possibly be generated. But since the
|
|
contradictory of 'that which is always capable of being' 'that which
|
|
is not always capable of being'; while 'that which is always capable
|
|
of not being' is the contrary, whose contradictory in turn is 'that
|
|
which is not always capable of not being', it is necessary that the
|
|
contradictories of both terms should be predicable of one and the same
|
|
thing, and thus that, intermediate between what always is and what
|
|
always is not, there should be that to which being and not-being are
|
|
both possible; for the contradictory of each will at times be true
|
|
of it unless it always exists. Hence that which not always is not will
|
|
sometimes be and sometimes not be; and it is clear that this is true
|
|
also of that which cannot always be but sometimes is and therefore
|
|
sometimes is not. One thing, then, will have the power of being, and
|
|
will thus be intermediate between the other two.
|
|
|
|
Expresed universally our argument is as follows. Let there be two
|
|
attributes, A and B, not capable of being present in any one thing
|
|
together, while either A or C and either B or D are capable of being
|
|
present in everything. Then C and D must be predicated of everything
|
|
of which neither A nor B is predicated. Let E lie between A and B; for
|
|
that which is neither of two contraries is a mean between them. In E
|
|
both C and D must be present, for either A or C is present
|
|
everywhere and therefore in E. Since then A is impossible, C must be
|
|
present, and the same argument holds of D.
|
|
|
|
Neither that which always is, therefore, nor that which always is
|
|
not is either generated or destructible. And clearly whatever is
|
|
generated or destructible is not eternal. If it were, it would be at
|
|
once capable of always being and capable of not always being, but it
|
|
has already been shown that this is impossible. Surely then whatever
|
|
is ungenerated and in being must be eternal, and whatever is
|
|
indestructible and in being must equally be so. (I use the words
|
|
'ungenerated' and 'indestructible' in their proper sense,
|
|
'ungenerated' for that which now is and could not at any previous time
|
|
have been truly said not to be; 'indestructible' for that which now is
|
|
and cannot at any future time be truly said not to be.) If, again, the
|
|
two terms are coincident, if the ungenerated is indestructible, and
|
|
the indestructible ungenearted, then each of them is coincident with
|
|
'eternal'; anything ungenerated is eternal and anything indestructible
|
|
is eternal. This is clear too from the definition of the terms,
|
|
Whatever is destructible must be generated; for it is either
|
|
ungenerated, or generated, but, if ungenerated, it is by hypothesis
|
|
indestructible. Whatever, further, is generated must be
|
|
destructible. For it is either destructible or indestructible, but, if
|
|
indestructible, it is by hypothesis ungenerated.
|
|
|
|
If, however, 'indestructible' and 'ungenerated' are not
|
|
coincident, there is no necessity that either the ungenerated or the
|
|
indestructible should be eternal. But they must be coincident, for the
|
|
following reasons. The terms 'generated' and 'destructible' are
|
|
coincident; this is obvious from our former remarks, since between
|
|
what always is and what always is not there is an intermediate which
|
|
is neither, and that intermediate is the generated and destructible.
|
|
For whatever is either of these is capable both of being and of not
|
|
being for a definite time: in either case, I mean, there is a
|
|
certain period of time during which the thing is and another during
|
|
which it is not. Anything therefore which is generated or destructible
|
|
must be intermediate. Now let A be that which always is and B that
|
|
which always is not, C the generated, and D the destructible. Then C
|
|
must be intermediate between A and B. For in their case there is no
|
|
time in the direction of either limit, in which either A is not or B
|
|
is. But for the generated there must be such a time either actually or
|
|
potentially, though not for A and B in either way. C then will be, and
|
|
also not be, for a limited length of time, and this is true also of D,
|
|
the destructible. Therefore each is both generated and destructible.
|
|
Therefore 'generated' and 'destructible' are coincident. Now let E
|
|
stand for the ungenerated, F for the generated, G for the
|
|
indestructible, and H for the destructible. As for F and H, it has
|
|
been shown that they are coincident. But when terms stand to one
|
|
another as these do, F and H coincident, E and F never predicated of
|
|
the same thing but one or other of everything, and G and H likewise,
|
|
then E and G must needs be coincident. For suppose that E is not
|
|
coincident with G, then F will be, since either E or F is
|
|
predictable of everything. But of that of which F is predicated H will
|
|
be predicable also. H will then be coincident with G, but this we
|
|
saw to be impossible. And the same argument shows that G is coincident
|
|
with E.
|
|
|
|
Now the relation of the ungenerated (E) to the generated (F) is
|
|
the same as that of the indestructible (G) to the destructible (H). To
|
|
say then that there is no reason why anything should not be
|
|
generated and yet indestructible or ungenerated and yet destroyed,
|
|
to imagine that in the one case generation and in the other case
|
|
destruction occurs once for all, is to destroy part of the data. For
|
|
(1) everything is capable of acting or being acted upon, of being or
|
|
not being, either for an infinite, or for a definitely limited space
|
|
of time; and the infinite time is only a possible alternative
|
|
because it is after a fashion defined, as a length of time which
|
|
cannot be exceeded. But infinity in one direction is neither
|
|
infinite or finite. (2) Further, why, after always existing, was the
|
|
thing destroyed, why, after an infinity of not being, was it
|
|
generated, at one moment rather than another? If every moment is alike
|
|
and the moments are infinite in number, it is clear that a generated
|
|
or destructible thing existed for an infinite time. It has therefore
|
|
for an infinite time the capacity of not being (since the capacity
|
|
of being and the capacity of not being will be present together), if
|
|
destructible, in the time before destruction, if generated, in the
|
|
time after generation. If then we assume the two capacities to be
|
|
actualized, opposites will be present together. (3) Further, this
|
|
second capacity will be present like the first at every moment, so
|
|
that the thing will have for an infinite time the capacity both of
|
|
being and of not being; but this has been shown to be impossible.
|
|
(4) Again, if the capacity is present prior to the activity, it will
|
|
be present for all time, even while the thing was as yet ungenerated
|
|
and non-existent, throughout the infinite time in which it was capable
|
|
of being generated. At that time, then, when it was not, at that
|
|
same time it had the capacity of being, both of being then and of
|
|
being thereafter, and therefore for an infinity of time.
|
|
|
|
It is clear also on other grounds that it is impossible that the
|
|
destructible should not at some time be destroyed. For otherwise it
|
|
will always be at once destructible and in actuality indestructible,
|
|
so that it will be at the same time capable of always existing and
|
|
of not always existing. Thus the destructible is at some time actually
|
|
destroyed. The generable, similarly, has been generated, for it is
|
|
capable of having been generated and thus also of not always existing.
|
|
|
|
We may also see in the following way how impossible it is either for
|
|
a thing which is generated to be thenceforward indestructible, or
|
|
for a thing which is ungenerated and has always hitherto existed to be
|
|
destroyed. Nothing that is by chance can be indestructible or
|
|
ungenerated, since the products of chance and fortune are opposed to
|
|
what is, or comes to be, always or usually, while anything which
|
|
exists for a time infinite either absolutely or in one direction, is
|
|
in existence either always or usually. That which is by chance,
|
|
then, is by nature such as to exist at one time and not at another.
|
|
But in things of that character the contradictory states proceed
|
|
from one and the same capacity, the matter of the thing being the
|
|
cause equally of its existence and of its non-existence. Hence
|
|
contradictories would be present together in actuality.
|
|
|
|
Further, it cannot truly be said of a thing now that it exists
|
|
last year, nor could it be said last year that it exists now. It is
|
|
therefore impossible for what once did not exist later to be
|
|
eternal. For in its later state it will possess the capacity of not
|
|
existing, only not of not existing at a time when it exists-since then
|
|
it exists in actuality-but of not existing last year or in the past.
|
|
Now suppose it to be in actuality what it is capable of being. It will
|
|
then be true to say now that it does not exist last year. But this
|
|
is impossible. No capacity relates to being in the past, but always to
|
|
being in the present or future. It is the same with the notion of an
|
|
eternity of existence followed later by non-existence. In the later
|
|
state the capacity will be present for that which is not there in
|
|
actuality. Actualize, then, the capacity. It will be true to say now
|
|
that this exists last year or in the past generally.
|
|
|
|
Considerations also not general like these but proper to the subject
|
|
show it to be impossible that what was formerly eternal should later
|
|
be destroyed or that what formerly was not should later be eternal.
|
|
Whatever is destructible or generated is always alterable. Now
|
|
alteration is due to contraries, and the things which compose the
|
|
natural body are the very same that destroy it.
|
|
|
|
Book II
|
|
|
|
1
|
|
|
|
THAT the heaven as a whole neither came into being nor admits of
|
|
destruction, as some assert, but is one and eternal, with no end or
|
|
beginning of its total duration, containing and embracing in itself
|
|
the infinity of time, we may convince ourselves not only by the
|
|
arguments already set forth but also by a consideration of the views
|
|
of those who differ from us in providing for its generation. If our
|
|
view is a possible one, and the manner of generation which they assert
|
|
is impossible, this fact will have great weight in convincing us of
|
|
the immortality and eternity of the world. Hence it is well to
|
|
persuade oneself of the truth of the ancient and truly traditional
|
|
theories, that there is some immortal and divine thing which possesses
|
|
movement, but movement such as has no limit and is rather itself the
|
|
limit of all other movement. A limit is a thing which contains; and
|
|
this motion, being perfect, contains those imperfect motions which
|
|
have a limit and a goal, having itself no beginning or end, but
|
|
unceasing through the infinity of time, and of other movements, to
|
|
some the cause of their beginning, to others offering the goal. The
|
|
ancients gave to the Gods the heaven or upper place, as being alone
|
|
immortal; and our present argument testifies that it is indestructible
|
|
and ungenerated. Further, it is unaffected by any mortal discomfort,
|
|
and, in addition, effortless; for it needs no constraining necessity
|
|
to keep it to its path, and prevent it from moving with some other
|
|
movement more natural to itself. Such a constrained movement would
|
|
necessarily involve effort the more so, the more eternal it were-and
|
|
would be inconsistent with perfection. Hence we must not believe the
|
|
old tale which says that the world needs some Atlas to keep it
|
|
safe-a tale composed, it would seem, by men who, like later
|
|
thinkers, conceived of all the upper bodies as earthy and endowed with
|
|
weight, and therefore supported it in their fabulous way upon
|
|
animate necessity. We must no more believe that than follow Empedocles
|
|
when he says that the world, by being whirled round, received a
|
|
movement quick enough to overpower its own downward tendency, and thus
|
|
has been kept from destruction all this time. Nor, again, is it
|
|
conceivable that it should persist eternally by the necessitation of a
|
|
soul. For a soul could not live in such conditions painlessly or
|
|
happily, since the movement involves constraint, being imposed on
|
|
the first body, whose natural motion is different, and imposed
|
|
continuously. It must therefore be uneasy and devoid of all rational
|
|
satisfaction; for it could not even, like the soul of mortal
|
|
animals, take recreation in the bodily relaxation of sleep. An Ixion's
|
|
lot must needs possess it, without end or respite. If then, as we
|
|
said, the view already stated of the first motion is a possible one,
|
|
it is not only more appropriate so to conceive of its eternity, but
|
|
also on this hypothesis alone are we able to advance a theory
|
|
consistent with popular divinations of the divine nature. But of
|
|
this enough for the present.
|
|
|
|
2
|
|
|
|
Since there are some who say that there is a right and a left in the
|
|
heaven, with those who are known as Pythagoreans-to whom indeed the
|
|
view really belongs-we must consider whether, if we are to apply these
|
|
principles to the body of the universe, we should follow their
|
|
statement of the matter or find a better way. At the start we may
|
|
say that, if right and left are applicable, there are prior principles
|
|
which must first be applied. These principles have been analysed in
|
|
the discussion of the movements of animals, for the reason that they
|
|
are proper to animal nature. For in some animals we find all such
|
|
distinctions of parts as this of right and left clearly present, and
|
|
in others some; but in plants we find only above and below. Now if
|
|
we are to apply to the heaven such a distinction of parts, we must
|
|
exect, as we have said, to find in it also the distinction which in
|
|
animals is found first of them all. The distinctions are three,
|
|
namely, above and below, front and its opposite, right and left-all
|
|
these three oppositions we expect to find in the perfect body-and each
|
|
may be called a principle. Above is the principle of length, right
|
|
of breadth, front of depth. Or again we may connect them with the
|
|
various movements, taking principle to mean that part, in a thing
|
|
capable of movement, from which movement first begins. Growth starts
|
|
from above, locomotion from the right, sensemovement from in front
|
|
(for front is simply the part to which the senses are directed). Hence
|
|
we must not look for above and below, right and left, front and
|
|
back, in every kind of body, but only in those which, being animate,
|
|
have a principle of movement within themselves. For in no inanimate
|
|
thing do we observe a part from which movement originates. Some do not
|
|
move at all, some move, but not indifferently in any direction;
|
|
fire, for example, only upward, and earth only to the centre. It is
|
|
true that we speak of above and below, right and left, in these bodies
|
|
relatively to ourselves. The reference may be to our own right
|
|
hands, as with the diviner, or to some similarity to our own
|
|
members, such as the parts of a statue possess; or we may take the
|
|
contrary spatial order, calling right that which is to our left, and
|
|
left that which is to our right. We observe, however, in the things
|
|
themselves none of these distinctions; indeed if they are turned round
|
|
we proceed to speak of the opposite parts as right and left, a boy
|
|
land below, front and back. Hence it is remarkable that the
|
|
Pythagoreans should have spoken of these two principles, right and
|
|
left, only, to the exclusion of the other four, which have as good a
|
|
title as they. There is no less difference between above and below
|
|
or front and back in animals generally than between right and left.
|
|
The difference is sometimes only one of function, sometimes also one
|
|
of shape; and while the distinction of above and below is
|
|
characteristic of all animate things, whether plants or animals,
|
|
that of right and left is not found in plants. Further, inasmuch as
|
|
length is prior to breadth, if above is the principle of length, right
|
|
of breadth, and if the principle of that which is prior is itself
|
|
prior, then above will be prior to right, or let us say, since 'prior'
|
|
is ambiguous, prior in order of generation. If, in addition, above
|
|
is the region from which movement originates, right the region in
|
|
which it starts, front the region to which it is directed, then on
|
|
this ground too above has a certain original character as compared
|
|
with the other forms of position. On these two grounds, then, they may
|
|
fairly be criticized, first, for omitting the more fundamental
|
|
principles, and secondly, for thinking that the two they mentioned
|
|
were attributable equally to everything.
|
|
|
|
Since we have already determined that functions of this kind
|
|
belong to things which possess, a principle of movement, and that
|
|
the heaven is animate and possesses a principle of movement, clearly
|
|
the heaven must also exhibit above and below, right and left. We
|
|
need not be troubled by the question, arising from the spherical shape
|
|
of the world, how there can be a distinction of right and left
|
|
within it, all parts being alike and all for ever in motion. We must
|
|
think of the world as of something in which right differs from left in
|
|
shape as well as in other respects, which subsequently is included
|
|
in a sphere. The difference of function will persist, but will
|
|
appear not to by reason of the regularity of shape. In the same
|
|
fashion must we conceive of the beginning of its movement. For even if
|
|
it never began to move, yet it must possess a principle from which
|
|
it would have begun to move if it had begun, and from which it would
|
|
begin again if it came to a stand. Now by its length I mean the
|
|
interval between its poles, one pole being above and the other
|
|
below; for two hemispheres are specially distinguished from all others
|
|
by the immobility of the poles. Further, by 'transverse' in the
|
|
universe we commonly mean, not above and below, but a direction
|
|
crossing the line of the poles, which, by implication, is length:
|
|
for transverse motion is motion crossing motion up and down. Of the
|
|
poles, that which we see above us is the lower region, and that
|
|
which we do not see is the upper. For right in anything is, as we say,
|
|
the region in which locomotion originates, and the rotation of the
|
|
heaven originates in the region from which the stars rise. So this
|
|
will be the right, and the region where they set the left. If then
|
|
they begin from the right and move round to the right, the upper
|
|
must be the unseen pole. For if it is the pole we see, the movement
|
|
will be leftward, which we deny to be the fact. Clearly then the
|
|
invisible pole is above. And those who live in the other hemisphere
|
|
are above and to the right, while we are below and to the left. This
|
|
is just the opposite of the view of the Pythagoreans, who make us
|
|
above and on the right side and those in the other hemisphere below
|
|
and on the left side; the fact being the exact opposite. Relatively,
|
|
however, to the secondary revolution, I mean that of the planets, we
|
|
are above and on the right and they are below and on the left. For the
|
|
principle of their movement has the reverse position, since the
|
|
movement itself is the contrary of the other: hence it follows that we
|
|
are at its beginning and they at its end. Here we may end our
|
|
discussion of the distinctions of parts created by the three
|
|
dimensions and of the consequent differences of position.
|
|
|
|
3
|
|
|
|
Since circular motion is not the contrary of the reverse circular
|
|
motion, we must consider why there is more than one motion, though
|
|
we have to pursue our inquiries at a distance-a distance created not
|
|
so much by our spatial position as by the fact that our senses
|
|
enable us to perceive very few of the attributes of the heavenly
|
|
bodies. But let not that deter us. The reason must be sought in the
|
|
following facts. Everything which has a function exists for its
|
|
function. The activity of God is immortality, i.e. eternal life.
|
|
Therefore the movement of that which is divine must be eternal. But
|
|
such is the heaven, viz. a divine body, and for that reason to it is
|
|
given the circular body whose nature it is to move always in a circle.
|
|
Why, then, is not the whole body of the heaven of the same character
|
|
as that part? Because there must be something at rest at the centre of
|
|
the revolving body; and of that body no part can be at rest, either
|
|
elsewhere or at the centre. It could do so only if the body's
|
|
natural movement were towards the centre. But the circular movement is
|
|
natural, since otherwise it could not be eternal: for nothing
|
|
unnatural is eternal. The unnatural is subsequent to the natural,
|
|
being a derangement of the natural which occurs in the course of its
|
|
generation. Earth then has to exist; for it is earth which is at
|
|
rest at the centre. (At present we may take this for granted: it shall
|
|
be explained later.) But if earth must exist, so must fire. For, if
|
|
one of a pair of contraries naturally exists, the other, if it is
|
|
really contrary, exists also naturally. In some form it must be
|
|
present, since the matter of contraries is the same. Also, the
|
|
positive is prior to its privation (warm, for instance, to cold),
|
|
and rest and heaviness stand for the privation of lightness and
|
|
movement. But further, if fire and earth exist, the intermediate
|
|
bodies must exist also: each element stands in a contrary relation
|
|
to every other. (This, again, we will here take for granted and try
|
|
later to explain.) these four elements generation clearly is involved,
|
|
since none of them can be eternal: for contraries interact with one
|
|
another and destroy one another. Further, it is inconceivable that a
|
|
movable body should be eternal, if its movement cannot be regarded
|
|
as naturally eternal: and these bodies we know to possess movement.
|
|
Thus we see that generation is necessarily involved. But if so,
|
|
there must be at least one other circular motion: for a single
|
|
movement of the whole heaven would necessitate an identical relation
|
|
of the elements of bodies to one another. This matter also shall be
|
|
cleared up in what follows: but for the present so much is clear, that
|
|
the reason why there is more than one circular body is the necessity
|
|
of generation, which follows on the presence of fire, which, with that
|
|
of the other bodies, follows on that of earth; and earth is required
|
|
because eternal movement in one body necessitates eternal rest in
|
|
another.
|
|
|
|
4
|
|
|
|
The shape of the heaven is of necessity spherical; for that is the
|
|
shape most appropriate to its substance and also by nature primary.
|
|
|
|
First, let us consider generally which shape is primary among planes
|
|
and solids alike. Every plane figure must be either rectilinear or
|
|
curvilinear. Now the rectilinear is bounded by more than one line, the
|
|
curvilinear by one only. But since in any kind the one is naturally
|
|
prior to the many and the simple to the complex, the circle will be
|
|
the first of plane figures. Again, if by complete, as previously
|
|
defined, we mean a thing outside which no part of itself can be found,
|
|
and if addition is always possible to the straight line but never to
|
|
the circular, clearly the line which embraces the circle is
|
|
complete. If then the complete is prior to the incomplete, it
|
|
follows on this ground also that the circle is primary among
|
|
figures. And the sphere holds the same position among solids. For it
|
|
alone is embraced by a single surface, while rectilinear solids have
|
|
several. The sphere is among solids what the circle is among plane
|
|
figures. Further, those who divide bodies into planes and generate
|
|
them out of planes seem to bear witness to the truth of this. Alone
|
|
among solids they leave the sphere undivided, as not possessing more
|
|
than one surface: for the division into surfaces is not just
|
|
dividing a whole by cutting it into its parts, but division of another
|
|
fashion into parts different in form. It is clear, then, that the
|
|
sphere is first of solid figures.
|
|
|
|
If, again, one orders figures according to their numbers, it is most
|
|
natural to arrange them in this way. The circle corresponds to the
|
|
number one, the triangle, being the sum of two right angles, to the
|
|
number two. But if one is assigned to the triangle, the circle will
|
|
not be a figure at all.
|
|
|
|
Now the first figure belongs to the first body, and the first body
|
|
is that at the farthest circumference. It follows that the body
|
|
which revolves with a circular movement must be spherical. The same
|
|
then will be true of the body continuous with it: for that which is
|
|
continuous with the spherical is spherical. The same again holds of
|
|
the bodies between these and the centre. Bodies which are bounded by
|
|
the spherical and in contact with it must be, as wholes, spherical;
|
|
and the bodies below the sphere of the planets are contiguous with the
|
|
sphere above them. The sphere then will be spherical throughout; for
|
|
every body within it is contiguous and continuous with spheres.
|
|
|
|
Again, since the whole revolves, palpably and by assumption, in a
|
|
circle, and since it has been shown that outside the farthest
|
|
circumference there is neither void nor place, from these grounds also
|
|
it will follow necessarily that the heaven is spherical. For if it
|
|
is to be rectilinear in shape, it will follow that there is place
|
|
and body and void without it. For a rectilinear figure as it
|
|
revolves never continues in the same room, but where formerly was
|
|
body, is now none, and where now is none, body will be in a moment
|
|
because of the projection at the corners. Similarly, if the world
|
|
had some other figure with unequal radii, if, for instance, it were
|
|
lentiform, or oviform, in every case we should have to admit space and
|
|
void outside the moving body, because the whole body would not
|
|
always occupy the same room.
|
|
|
|
Again, if the motion of the heaven is the measure of all movements
|
|
whatever in virtue of being alone continuous and regular and
|
|
eternal, and if, in each kind, the measure is the minimum, and the
|
|
minimum movement is the swiftest, then, clearly, the movement of the
|
|
heaven must be the swiftest of all movements. Now of lines which
|
|
return upon themselves the line which bounds the circle is the
|
|
shortest; and that movement is the swiftest which follows the shortest
|
|
line. Therefore, if the heaven moves in a circle and moves more
|
|
swiftly than anything else, it must necessarily be spherical.
|
|
|
|
Corroborative evidence may be drawn from the bodies whose position
|
|
is about the centre. If earth is enclosed by water, water by air,
|
|
air by fire, and these similarly by the upper bodies-which while not
|
|
continuous are yet contiguous with them-and if the surface of water is
|
|
spherical, and that which is continuous with or embraces the spherical
|
|
must itself be spherical, then on these grounds also it is clear
|
|
that the heavens are spherical. But the surface of water is seen to be
|
|
spherical if we take as our starting-point the fact that water
|
|
naturally tends to collect in a hollow place-'hollow' meaning
|
|
'nearer the centre'. Draw from the centre the lines AB, AC, and let
|
|
their extremities be joined by the straight line BC. The line AD,
|
|
drawn to the base of the triangle, will be shorter than either of
|
|
the radii. Therefore the place in which it terminates will be a hollow
|
|
place. The water then will collect there until equality is
|
|
established, that is until the line AE is equal to the two radii. Thus
|
|
water forces its way to the ends of the radii, and there only will
|
|
it rest: but the line which connects the extremities of the radii is
|
|
circular: therefore the surface of the water BEC is spherical.
|
|
|
|
It is plain from the foregoing that the universe is spherical. It is
|
|
plain, further, that it is turned (so to speak) with a finish which no
|
|
manufactured thing nor anything else within the range of our
|
|
observation can even approach. For the matter of which these are
|
|
composed does not admit of anything like the same regularity and
|
|
finish as the substance of the enveloping body; since with each step
|
|
away from earth the matter manifestly becomes finer in the same
|
|
proportion as water is finer than earth.
|
|
|
|
5
|
|
|
|
Now there are two ways of moving along a circle, from A to B or from
|
|
A to C, and we have already explained that these movements are not
|
|
contrary to one another. But nothing which concerns the eternal can be
|
|
a matter of chance or spontaneity, and the heaven and its circular
|
|
motion are eternal. We must therefore ask why this motion takes one
|
|
direction and not the other. Either this is itself an ultimate fact or
|
|
there is an ultimate fact behind it. It may seem evidence of excessive
|
|
folly or excessive zeal to try to provide an explanation of some
|
|
things, or of everything, admitting no exception. The criticism,
|
|
however, is not always just: one should first consider what reason
|
|
there is for speaking, and also what kind of certainty is looked
|
|
for, whether human merely or of a more cogent kind. When any one shall
|
|
succeed in finding proofs of greater precision, gratitude will be
|
|
due to him for the discovery, but at present we must be content with a
|
|
probable solution. If nature always follows the best course
|
|
possible, and, just as upward movement is the superior form of
|
|
rectilinear movement, since the upper region is more divine than the
|
|
lower, so forward movement is superior to backward, then front and
|
|
back exhibits, like right and left, as we said before and as the
|
|
difficulty just stated itself suggests, the distinction of prior and
|
|
posterior, which provides a reason and so solves our difficulty.
|
|
Supposing that nature is ordered in the best way possible, this may
|
|
stand as the reason of the fact mentioned. For it is best to move with
|
|
a movement simple and unceasing, and, further, in the superior of
|
|
two possible directions.
|
|
|
|
6
|
|
|
|
We have next to show that the movement of the heaven is regular
|
|
and not irregular. This applies only to the first heaven and the first
|
|
movement; for the lower spheres exhibit a composition of several
|
|
movements into one. If the movement is uneven, clearly there will be
|
|
acceleration, maximum speed, and retardation, since these appear in
|
|
all irregular motions. The maximum may occur either at the
|
|
starting-point or at the goal or between the two; and we expect
|
|
natural motion to reach its maximum at the goal, unnatural motion at
|
|
the starting-point, and missiles midway between the two. But
|
|
circular movement, having no beginning or limit or middle in the
|
|
direct sense of the words, has neither whence nor whither nor
|
|
middle: for in time it is eternal, and in length it returns upon
|
|
itself without a break. If then its movement has no maximum, it can
|
|
have no irregularity, since irregularity is produced by retardation
|
|
and acceleration. Further, since everything that is moved is moved
|
|
by something, the cause of the irregularity of movement must lie
|
|
either in the mover or in the moved or both. For if the mover moved
|
|
not always with the same force, or if the moved were altered and did
|
|
not remain the same, or if both were to change, the result might
|
|
well be an irregular movement in the moved. But none of these
|
|
possibilities can be conceived as actual in the case of the heavens.
|
|
As to that which is moved, we have shown that it is primary and simple
|
|
and ungenerated and indestructible and generally unchanging; and the
|
|
mover has an even better right to these attributes. It is the
|
|
primary that moves the primary, the simple the simple, the
|
|
indestructible and ungenerated that which is indestructible and
|
|
ungenerated. Since then that which is moved, being a body, is
|
|
nevertheless unchanging, how should the mover, which is incorporeal,
|
|
be changed?
|
|
|
|
It follows then, further, that the motion cannot be irregular. For
|
|
if irregularity occurs, there must be change either in the movement as
|
|
a whole, from fast to slow and slow to fast, or in its parts. That
|
|
there is no irregularity in the parts is obvious, since, if there
|
|
were, some divergence of the stars would have taken place before now
|
|
in the infinity of time, as one moved slower and another faster: but
|
|
no alteration of their intervals is ever observed. Nor again is a
|
|
change in the movement as a whole admissible. Retardation is always
|
|
due to incapacity, and incapacity is unnatural. The incapacities of
|
|
animals, age, decay, and the like, are all unnatural, due, it seems,
|
|
to the fact that the whole animal complex is made up of materials
|
|
which differ in respect of their proper places, and no single part
|
|
occupies its own place. If therefore that which is primary contains
|
|
nothing unnatural, being simple and unmixed and in its proper place
|
|
and having no contrary, then it has no place for incapacity, nor,
|
|
consequently, for retardation or (since acceleration involves
|
|
retardation) for acceleration. Again, it is inconceivable that the
|
|
mover should first show incapacity for an infinite time, and
|
|
capacity afterwards for another infinity. For clearly nothing which,
|
|
like incapacity, unnatural ever continues for an infinity of time; nor
|
|
does the unnatural endure as long as the natural, or any form of
|
|
incapacity as long as the capacity. But if the movement is retarded it
|
|
must necessarily be retarded for an infinite time. Equally
|
|
impossible is perpetual acceleration or perpetual retardation. For
|
|
such movement would be infinite and indefinite, but every movement, in
|
|
our view, proceeds from one point to another and is definite in
|
|
character. Again, suppose one assumes a minimum time in less than
|
|
which the heaven could not complete its movement. For, as a given walk
|
|
or a given exercise on the harp cannot take any and every time, but
|
|
every performance has its definite minimum time which is
|
|
unsurpassable, so, one might suppose, the movement of the heaven could
|
|
not be completed in any and every time. But in that case perpetual
|
|
acceleration is impossible (and, equally, perpetual retardation: for
|
|
the argument holds of both and each), if we may take acceleration to
|
|
proceed by identical or increasing additions of speed and for an
|
|
infinite time. The remaining alternative is to say that the movement
|
|
exhibits an alternation of slower and faster: but this is a mere
|
|
fiction and quite inconceivable. Further, irregularity of this kind
|
|
would be particularly unlikely to pass unobserved, since contrast
|
|
makes observation easy.
|
|
|
|
That there is one heaven, then, only, and that it is ungenerated and
|
|
eternal, and further that its movement is regular, has now been
|
|
sufficiently explained.
|
|
|
|
7
|
|
|
|
We have next to speak of the stars, as they are called, of their
|
|
composition, shape, and movements. It would be most natural and
|
|
consequent upon what has been said that each of the stars should be
|
|
composed of that substance in which their path lies, since, as we
|
|
said, there is an element whose natural movement is circular. In so
|
|
saying we are only following the same line of thought as those who say
|
|
that the stars are fiery because they believe the upper body to be
|
|
fire, the presumption being that a thing is composed of the same stuff
|
|
as that in which it is situated. The warmth and light which proceed
|
|
from them are caused by the friction set up in the air by their
|
|
motion. Movement tends to create fire in wood, stone, and iron; and
|
|
with even more reason should it have that effect on air, a substance
|
|
which is closer to fire than these. An example is that of missiles,
|
|
which as they move are themselves fired so strongly that leaden
|
|
balls are melted; and if they are fired the surrounding air must be
|
|
similarly affected. Now while the missiles are heated by reason of
|
|
their motion in air, which is turned into fire by the agitation
|
|
produced by their movement, the upper bodies are carried on a moving
|
|
sphere, so that, though they are not themselves fired, yet the air
|
|
underneath the sphere of the revolving body is necessarily heated by
|
|
its motion, and particularly in that part where the sun is attached to
|
|
it. Hence warmth increases as the sun gets nearer or higher or
|
|
overhead. Of the fact, then, that the stars are neither fiery nor move
|
|
in fire, enough has been said.
|
|
|
|
8
|
|
|
|
Since changes evidently occur not only in the position of the
|
|
stars but also in that of the whole heaven, there are three
|
|
possibilities. Either (1) both are at rest, or (2) both are in motion,
|
|
or (3) the one is at rest and the other in motion.
|
|
|
|
(1) That both should be at rest is impossible; for, if the earth
|
|
is at rest, the hypothesis does not account for the observations;
|
|
and we take it as granted that the earth is at rest. It remains either
|
|
that both are moved, or that the one is moved and the other at rest.
|
|
|
|
(2) On the view, first, that both are in motion, we have the
|
|
absurdity that the stars and the circles move with the same speed,
|
|
i.e. that the ace of every star is that of the circle in it moves. For
|
|
star and circle are seen to come back to the same place at the same
|
|
moment; from which it follows that the star has traversed the circle
|
|
and the circle has completed its own movement, i.e. traversed its
|
|
own circumference, at one and the same moment. But it is difficult
|
|
to conceive that the pace of each star should be exactly
|
|
proportioned to the size of its circle. That the pace of each circle
|
|
should be proportionate to its size is not absurd but inevitable:
|
|
but that the same should be true of the movement of the stars
|
|
contained in the circles is quite incredible. For if, on the one
|
|
and, we suppose that the star which moves on the greater circle is
|
|
necessarily swifter, clearly we also admit that if stars shifted their
|
|
position so as to exchange circles, the slower would become swifter
|
|
and the swifter slower. But this would show that their movement was
|
|
not their own, but due to the circles. If, on the other hand, the
|
|
arrangement was a chance combination, the coincidence in every case of
|
|
a greater circle with a swifter movement of the star contained in it
|
|
is too much to believe. In one or two cases it might not inconceivably
|
|
fall out so, but to imagine it in every case alike is a mere
|
|
fiction. Besides, chance has no place in that which is natural, and
|
|
what happens everywhere and in every case is no matter of chance.
|
|
|
|
(3) The same absurdity is equally plain if it is supposed that the
|
|
circles stand still and that it is the stars themselves which move.
|
|
For it will follow that the outer stars are the swifter, and that
|
|
the pace of the stars corresponds to the size of their circles.
|
|
|
|
Since, then, we cannot reasonably suppose either that both are in
|
|
motion or that the star alone moves, the remaining alternative is that
|
|
the circles should move, while the stars are at rest and move with the
|
|
circles to which they are attached. Only on this supposition are we
|
|
involved in no absurd consequence. For, in the first place, the
|
|
quicker movement of the larger circle is natural when all the
|
|
circles are attached to the same centre. Whenever bodies are moving
|
|
with their proper motion, the larger moves quicker. It is the same
|
|
here with the revolving bodies: for the are intercepted by two radii
|
|
will be larger in the larger circle, and hence it is not surprising
|
|
that the revolution of the larger circle should take the same time
|
|
as that of the smaller. And secondly, the fact that the heavens do not
|
|
break in pieces follows not only from this but also from the proof
|
|
already given of the continuity of the whole.
|
|
|
|
Again, since the stars are spherical, as our opponents assert and we
|
|
may consistently admit, inasmuch as we construct them out of the
|
|
spherical body, and since the spherical body has two movements
|
|
proper to itself, namely rolling and spinning, it follows that if
|
|
the stars have a movement of their own, it will be one of these. But
|
|
neither is observed. (1) Suppose them to spin. They would then stay
|
|
where they were, and not change their place, as, by observation and
|
|
general consent, they do. Further, one would expect them all to
|
|
exhibit the same movement: but the only star which appears to
|
|
possess this movement is the sun, at sunrise or sunset, and this
|
|
appearance is due not to the sun itself but to the distance from which
|
|
we observe it. The visual ray being excessively prolonged becomes weak
|
|
and wavering. The same reason probably accounts for the apparent
|
|
twinkling of the fixed stars and the absence of twinkling in the
|
|
planets. The planets are near, so that the visual ray reaches them
|
|
in its full vigour, but when it comes to the fixed stars it is
|
|
quivering because of the distance and its excessive extension; and its
|
|
tremor produces an appearance of movement in the star: for it makes no
|
|
difference whether movement is set up in the ray or in the object of
|
|
vision.
|
|
|
|
(2) On the other hand, it is also clear that the stars do not
|
|
roll. For rolling involves rotation: but the 'face', as it is
|
|
called, of the moon is always seen. Therefore, since any movement of
|
|
their own which the stars possessed would presumably be one proper
|
|
to themselves, and no such movement is observed in them, clearly
|
|
they have no movement of their own.
|
|
|
|
There is, further, the absurdity that nature has bestowed upon
|
|
them no organ appropriate to such movement. For nature leaves
|
|
nothing to chance, and would not, while caring for animals, overlook
|
|
things so precious. Indeed, nature seems deliberately to have stripped
|
|
them of everything which makes selforiginated progression possible,
|
|
and to have removed them as far as possible from things which have
|
|
organs of movement. This is just why it seems proper that the whole
|
|
heaven and every star should be spherical. For while of all shapes the
|
|
sphere is the most convenient for movement in one place, making
|
|
possible, as it does, the swiftest and most selfcontained motion,
|
|
for forward movement it is the most unsuitable, least of all
|
|
resembling shapes which are self-moved, in that it has no dependent or
|
|
projecting part, as a rectilinear figure has, and is in fact as far as
|
|
possible removed in shape from ambulatory bodies. Since, therefore,
|
|
the heavens have to move in one lace, and the stars are not required
|
|
to move themselves forward, it is natural that both should be
|
|
spherical-a shape which best suits the movement of the one and the
|
|
immobility of the other.
|
|
|
|
9
|
|
|
|
From all this it is clear that the theory that the movement of the
|
|
stars produces a harmony, i.e. that the sounds they make are
|
|
concordant, in spite of the grace and originality with which it has
|
|
been stated, is nevertheless untrue. Some thinkers suppose that the
|
|
motion of bodies of that size must produce a noise, since on our earth
|
|
the motion of bodies far inferior in size and in speed of movement has
|
|
that effect. Also, when the sun and the moon, they say, and all the
|
|
stars, so great in number and in size, are moving with so rapid a
|
|
motion, how should they not produce a sound immensely great?
|
|
Starting from this argument and from the observation that their
|
|
speeds, as measured by their distances, are in the same ratios as
|
|
musical concordances, they assert that the sound given forth by the
|
|
circular movement of the stars is a harmony. Since, however, it
|
|
appears unaccountable that we should not hear this music, they explain
|
|
this by saying that the sound is in our ears from the very moment of
|
|
birth and is thus indistinguishable from its contrary silence, since
|
|
sound and silence are discriminated by mutual contrast. What happens
|
|
to men, then, is just what happens to coppersmiths, who are so
|
|
accustomed to the noise of the smithy that it makes no difference to
|
|
them. But, as we said before, melodious and poetical as the theory is,
|
|
it cannot be a true account of the facts. There is not only the
|
|
absurdity of our hearing nothing, the ground of which they try to
|
|
remove, but also the fact that no effect other than sensitive is
|
|
produced upon us. Excessive noises, we know, shatter the solid
|
|
bodies even of inanimate things: the noise of thunder, for instance,
|
|
splits rocks and the strongest of bodies. But if the moving bodies are
|
|
so great, and the sound which penetrates to us is proportionate to
|
|
their size, that sound must needs reach us in an intensity many
|
|
times that of thunder, and the force of its action must be immense.
|
|
Indeed the reason why we do not hear, and show in our bodies none of
|
|
the effects of violent force, is easily given: it is that there is
|
|
no noise. But not only is the explanation evident; it is also a
|
|
corroboration of the truth of the views we have advanced. For the very
|
|
difficulty which made the Pythagoreans say that the motion of the
|
|
stars produces a concord corroborates our view. Bodies which are
|
|
themselves in motion, produce noise and friction: but those which
|
|
are attached or fixed to a moving body, as the parts to a ship, can no
|
|
more create noise, than a ship on a river moving with the stream.
|
|
Yet by the same argument one might say it was absurd that on a large
|
|
vessel the motion of mast and poop should not make a great noise,
|
|
and the like might be said of the movement of the vessel itself. But
|
|
sound is caused when a moving body is enclosed in an unmoved body, and
|
|
cannot be caused by one enclosed in, and continuous with, a moving
|
|
body which creates no friction. We may say, then, in this matter
|
|
that if the heavenly bodies moved in a generally diffused mass of
|
|
air or fire, as every one supposes, their motion would necessarily
|
|
cause a noise of tremendous strength and such a noise would
|
|
necessarily reach and shatter us. Since, therefore, this effect is
|
|
evidently not produced, it follows that none of them can move with the
|
|
motion either of animate nature or of constraint. It is as though
|
|
nature had foreseen the result, that if their movement were other than
|
|
it is, nothing on this earth could maintain its character.
|
|
|
|
That the stars are spherical and are not selfmoved, has now been
|
|
explained.
|
|
|
|
10
|
|
|
|
With their order-I mean the position of each, as involving the
|
|
priority of some and the posteriority of others, and their
|
|
respective distances from the extremity-with this astronomy may be
|
|
left to deal, since the astronomical discussion is adequate. This
|
|
discussion shows that the movements of the several stars depend, as
|
|
regards the varieties of speed which they exhibit, on the distance
|
|
of each from the extremity. It is established that the outermost
|
|
revolution of the heavens is a simple movement and the swiftest of
|
|
all, and that the movement of all other bodies is composite and
|
|
relatively slow, for the reason that each is moving on its own
|
|
circle with the reverse motion to that of the heavens. This at once
|
|
leads us to expect that the body which is nearest to that first simple
|
|
revolution should take the longest time to complete its circle, and
|
|
that which is farthest from it the shortest, the others taking a
|
|
longer time the nearer they are and a shorter time the farther away
|
|
they are. For it is the nearest body which is most strongly
|
|
influenced, and the most remote, by reason of its distance, which is
|
|
least affected, the influence on the intermediate bodies varying, as
|
|
the mathematicians show, with their distance.
|
|
|
|
11
|
|
|
|
With regard to the shape of each star, the most reasonable view is
|
|
that they are spherical. It has been shown that it is not in their
|
|
nature to move themselves, and, since nature is no wanton or random
|
|
creator, clearly she will have given things which possess no
|
|
movement a shape particularly unadapted to movement. Such a shape is
|
|
the sphere, since it possesses no instrument of movement. Clearly then
|
|
their mass will have the form of a sphere. Again, what holds of one
|
|
holds of all, and the evidence of our eyes shows us that the moon is
|
|
spherical. For how else should the moon as it waxes and wanes show for
|
|
the most part a crescent-shaped or gibbous figure, and only at one
|
|
moment a half-moon? And astronomical arguments give further
|
|
confirmation; for no other hypothesis accounts for the crescent
|
|
shape of the sun's eclipses. One, then, of the heavenly bodies being
|
|
spherical, clearly the rest will be spherical also.
|
|
|
|
12
|
|
|
|
There are two difficulties, which may very reasonably here be
|
|
raised, of which we must now attempt to state the probable solution:
|
|
for we regard the zeal of one whose thirst after philosophy leads
|
|
him to accept even slight indications where it is very difficult to
|
|
see one's way, as a proof rather of modesty than of overconfidence.
|
|
|
|
Of many such problems one of the strangest is the problem why we
|
|
find the greatest number of movements in the intermediate bodies,
|
|
and not, rather, in each successive body a variety of movement
|
|
proportionate to its distance from the primary motion. For we should
|
|
expect, since the primary body shows one motion only, that the body
|
|
which is nearest to it should move with the fewest movements, say two,
|
|
and the one next after that with three, or some similar arrangement.
|
|
But the opposite is the case. The movements of the sun and moon are
|
|
fewer than those of some of the planets. Yet these planets are farther
|
|
from the centre and thus nearer to the primary body than they, as
|
|
observation has itself revealed. For we have seen the moon, half-full,
|
|
pass beneath the planet Mars, which vanished on its shadow side and
|
|
came forth by the bright and shining part. Similar accounts of other
|
|
stars are given by the Egyptians and Babylonians, whose observations
|
|
have been kept for very many years past, and from whom much of our
|
|
evidence about particular stars is derived. A second difficulty
|
|
which may with equal justice be raised is this. Why is it that the
|
|
primary motion includes such a multitude of stars that their whole
|
|
array seems to defy counting, while of the other stars each one is
|
|
separated off, and in no case do we find two or more attached to the
|
|
same motion?
|
|
|
|
On these questions, I say, it is well that we should seek to
|
|
increase our understanding, though we have but little to go upon,
|
|
and are placed at so great a distance from the facts in question.
|
|
Nevertheless there are certain principles on which if we base our
|
|
consideration we shall not find this difficulty by any means
|
|
insoluble. We may object that we have been thinking of the stars as
|
|
mere bodies, and as units with a serial order indeed but entirely
|
|
inanimate; but should rather conceive them as enjoying life and
|
|
action. On this view the facts cease to appear surprising. For it is
|
|
natural that the best-conditioned of all things should have its good
|
|
without action, that which is nearest to it should achieve it by
|
|
little and simple action, and that which is farther removed by a
|
|
complexity of actions, just as with men's bodies one is in good
|
|
condition without exercise at all, another after a short walk, while
|
|
another requires running and wrestling and hard training, and there
|
|
are yet others who however hard they worked themselves could never
|
|
secure this good, but only some substitute for it. To succeed often or
|
|
in many things is difficult. For instance, to throw ten thousand
|
|
Coan throws with the dice would be impossible, but to throw one or two
|
|
is comparatively easy. In action, again, when A has to be done to
|
|
get B, B to get C, and C to get D, one step or two present little
|
|
difficulty, but as the series extends the difficulty grows. We must,
|
|
then, think of the action of the lower stars as similar to that of
|
|
animals and plants. For on our earth it is man that has the greatest
|
|
variety of actions-for there are many goods that man can secure; hence
|
|
his actions are various and directed to ends beyond them-while the
|
|
perfectly conditioned has no need of action, since it is itself the
|
|
end, and action always requires two terms, end and means. The lower
|
|
animals have less variety of action than man; and plants perhaps
|
|
have little action and of one kind only. For either they have but
|
|
one attainable good (as indeed man has), or, if several, each
|
|
contributes directly to their ultimate good. One thing then has and
|
|
enjoys the ultimate good, other things attain to it, one immediately
|
|
by few steps, another by many, while yet another does not even attempt
|
|
to secure it but is satisfied to reach a point not far removed from
|
|
that consummation. Thus, taking health as the end, there will be one
|
|
thing that always possesses health, others that attain it, one by
|
|
reducing flesh, another by running and thus reducing flesh, another by
|
|
taking steps to enable himself to run, thus further increasing the
|
|
number of movements, while another cannot attain health itself, but
|
|
only running or reduction of flesh, so that one or other of these is
|
|
for such a being the end. For while it is clearly best for any being
|
|
to attain the real end, yet, if that cannot be, the nearer it is to
|
|
the best the better will be its state. It is for this reason that
|
|
the earth moves not at all and the bodies near to it with few
|
|
movements. For they do not attain the final end, but only come as near
|
|
to it as their share in the divine principle permits. But the first
|
|
heaven finds it immediately with a single movement, and the bodies
|
|
intermediate between the first and last heavens attain it indeed,
|
|
but at the cost of a multiplicity of movement.
|
|
|
|
As to the difficulty that into the one primary motion is crowded a
|
|
vast multitude of stars, while of the other stars each has been
|
|
separately given special movements of its own, there is in the first
|
|
place this reason for regarding the arrangement as a natural one. In
|
|
thinking of the life and moving principle of the several heavens one
|
|
must regard the first as far superior to the others. Such a
|
|
superiority would be reasonable. For this single first motion has to
|
|
move many of the divine bodies, while the numerous other motions
|
|
move only one each, since each single planet moves with a variety of
|
|
motions. Thus, then, nature makes matters equal and establishes a
|
|
certain order, giving to the single motion many bodies and to the
|
|
single body many motions. And there is a second reason why the other
|
|
motions have each only one body, in that each of them except the last,
|
|
i.e. that which contains the one star, is really moving many bodies.
|
|
For this last sphere moves with many others, to which it is fixed,
|
|
each sphere being actually a body; so that its movement will be a
|
|
joint product. Each sphere, in fact, has its particular natural
|
|
motion, to which the general movement is, as it were, added. But the
|
|
force of any limited body is only adequate to moving a limited body.
|
|
|
|
The characteristics of the stars which move with a circular
|
|
motion, in respect of substance and shape, movement and order, have
|
|
now been sufficiently explained.
|
|
|
|
13
|
|
|
|
It remains to speak of the earth, of its position, of the question
|
|
whether it is at rest or in motion, and of its shape.
|
|
|
|
I. As to its position there is some difference of opinion. Most
|
|
people-all, in fact, who regard the whole heaven as finite-say it lies
|
|
at the centre. But the Italian philosophers known as Pythagoreans take
|
|
the contrary view. At the centre, they say, is fire, and the earth
|
|
is one of the stars, creating night and day by its circular motion
|
|
about the centre. They further construct another earth in opposition
|
|
to ours to which they give the name counterearth. In all this they are
|
|
not seeking for theories and causes to account for observed facts, but
|
|
rather forcing their observations and trying to accommodate them to
|
|
certain theories and opinions of their own. But there are many
|
|
others who would agree that it is wrong to give the earth the
|
|
central position, looking for confirmation rather to theory than to
|
|
the facts of observation. Their view is that the most precious place
|
|
befits the most precious thing: but fire, they say, is more precious
|
|
than earth, and the limit than the intermediate, and the circumference
|
|
and the centre are limits. Reasoning on this basis they take the
|
|
view that it is not earth that lies at the centre of the sphere, but
|
|
rather fire. The Pythagoreans have a further reason. They hold that
|
|
the most important part of the world, which is the centre, should be
|
|
most strictly guarded, and name it, or rather the fire which
|
|
occupies that place, the 'Guardhouse of Zeus', as if the word 'centre'
|
|
were quite unequivocal, and the centre of the mathematical figure were
|
|
always the same with that of the thing or the natural centre. But it
|
|
is better to conceive of the case of the whole heaven as analogous
|
|
to that of animals, in which the centre of the animal and that of
|
|
the body are different. For this reason they have no need to be so
|
|
disturbed about the world, or to call in a guard for its centre:
|
|
rather let them look for the centre in the other sense and tell us
|
|
what it is like and where nature has set it. That centre will be
|
|
something primary and precious; but to the mere position we should
|
|
give the last place rather than the first. For the middle is what is
|
|
defined, and what defines it is the limit, and that which contains
|
|
or limits is more precious than that which is limited, see ing that
|
|
the latter is the matter and the former the essence of the system.
|
|
|
|
II. As to the position of the earth, then, this is the view which
|
|
some advance, and the views advanced concerning its rest or motion are
|
|
similar. For here too there is no general agreement. All who deny that
|
|
the earth lies at the centre think that it revolves about the
|
|
centre, and not the earth only but, as we said before, the
|
|
counter-earth as well. Some of them even consider it possible that
|
|
there are several bodies so moving, which are invisible to us owing to
|
|
the interposition of the earth. This, they say, accounts for the
|
|
fact that eclipses of the moon are more frequent than eclipses of
|
|
the sun: for in addition to the earth each of these moving bodies
|
|
can obstruct it. Indeed, as in any case the surface of the earth is
|
|
not actually a centre but distant from it a full hemisphere, there
|
|
is no more difficulty, they think, in accounting for the observed
|
|
facts on their view that we do not dwell at the centre, than on the
|
|
common view that the earth is in the middle. Even as it is, there is
|
|
nothing in the observations to suggest that we are removed from the
|
|
centre by half the diameter of the earth. Others, again, say that
|
|
the earth, which lies at the centre, is 'rolled', and thus in
|
|
motion, about the axis of the whole heaven, So it stands written in
|
|
the Timaeus.
|
|
|
|
III. There are similar disputes about the shape of the earth. Some
|
|
think it is spherical, others that it is flat and drum-shaped. For
|
|
evidence they bring the fact that, as the sun rises and sets, the part
|
|
concealed by the earth shows a straight and not a curved edge, whereas
|
|
if the earth were spherical the line of section would have to be
|
|
circular. In this they leave out of account the great distance of
|
|
the sun from the earth and the great size of the circumference, which,
|
|
seen from a distance on these apparently small circles appears
|
|
straight. Such an appearance ought not to make them doubt the circular
|
|
shape of the earth. But they have another argument. They say that
|
|
because it is at rest, the earth must necessarily have this shape. For
|
|
there are many different ways in which the movement or rest of the
|
|
earth has been conceived.
|
|
|
|
The difficulty must have occurred to every one. It would indeed be a
|
|
complacent mind that felt no surprise that, while a little bit of
|
|
earth, let loose in mid-air moves and will not stay still, and more
|
|
there is of it the faster it moves, the whole earth, free in midair,
|
|
should show no movement at all. Yet here is this great weight of
|
|
earth, and it is at rest. And again, from beneath one of these
|
|
moving fragments of earth, before it falls, take away the earth, and
|
|
it will continue its downward movement with nothing to stop it. The
|
|
difficulty then, has naturally passed into a common place of
|
|
philosophy; and one may well wonder that the solutions offered are not
|
|
seen to involve greater absurdities than the problem itself.
|
|
|
|
By these considerations some have been led to assert that the
|
|
earth below us is infinite, saying, with Xenophanes of Colophon,
|
|
that it has 'pushed its roots to infinity',-in order to save the
|
|
trouble of seeking for the cause. Hence the sharp rebuke of
|
|
Empedocles, in the words 'if the deeps of the earth are endless and
|
|
endless the ample ether-such is the vain tale told by many a tongue,
|
|
poured from the mouths of those who have seen but little of the whole.
|
|
Others say the earth rests upon water. This, indeed, is the oldest
|
|
theory that has been preserved, and is attributed to Thales of
|
|
Miletus. It was supposed to stay still because it floated like wood
|
|
and other similar substances, which are so constituted as to rest upon
|
|
but not upon air. As if the same account had not to be given of the
|
|
water which carries the earth as of the earth itself! It is not the
|
|
nature of water, any more than of earth, to stay in mid-air: it must
|
|
have something to rest upon. Again, as air is lighter than water, so
|
|
is water than earth: how then can they think that the naturally
|
|
lighter substance lies below the heavier? Again, if the earth as a
|
|
whole is capable of floating upon water, that must obviously be the
|
|
case with any part of it. But observation shows that this is not the
|
|
case. Any piece of earth goes to the bottom, the quicker the larger it
|
|
is. These thinkers seem to push their inquiries some way into the
|
|
problem, but not so far as they might. It is what we are all
|
|
inclined to do, to direct our inquiry not by the matter itself, but by
|
|
the views of our opponents: and even when interrogating oneself one
|
|
pushes the inquiry only to the point at which one can no longer
|
|
offer any opposition. Hence a good inquirer will be one who is ready
|
|
in bringing forward the objections proper to the genus, and that he
|
|
will be when he has gained an understanding of all the differences.
|
|
|
|
Anaximenes and Anaxagoras and Democritus give the flatness of the
|
|
earth as the cause of its staying still. Thus, they say, it does not
|
|
cut, but covers like a lid, the air beneath it. This seems to be the
|
|
way of flat-shaped bodies: for even the wind can scarcely move them
|
|
because of their power of resistance. The same immobility, they say,
|
|
is produced by the flatness of the surface which the earth presents to
|
|
the air which underlies it; while the air, not having room enough to
|
|
change its place because it is underneath the earth, stays there in
|
|
a mass, like the water in the case of the water-clock. And they adduce
|
|
an amount of evidence to prove that air, when cut off and at rest, can
|
|
bear a considerable weight.
|
|
|
|
Now, first, if the shape of the earth is not flat, its flatness
|
|
cannot be the cause of its immobility. But in their own account it
|
|
is rather the size of the earth than its flatness that causes it to
|
|
remain at rest. For the reason why the air is so closely confined that
|
|
it cannot find a passage, and therefore stays where it is, is its
|
|
great amount: and this amount great because the body which isolates
|
|
it, the earth, is very large. This result, then, will follow, even
|
|
if the earth is spherical, so long as it retains its size. So far as
|
|
their arguments go, the earth will still be at rest.
|
|
|
|
In general, our quarrel with those who speak of movement in this way
|
|
cannot be confined to the parts; it concerns the whole universe. One
|
|
must decide at the outset whether bodies have a natural movement or
|
|
not, whether there is no natural but only constrained movement.
|
|
Seeing, however, that we have already decided this matter to the
|
|
best of our ability, we are entitled to treat our results as
|
|
representing fact. Bodies, we say, which have no natural movement,
|
|
have no constrained movement; and where there is no natural and no
|
|
constrained movement there will be no movement at all. This is a
|
|
conclusion, the necessity of which we have already decided, and we
|
|
have seen further that rest also will be inconceivable, since rest,
|
|
like movement, is either natural or constrained. But if there is any
|
|
natural movement, constraint will not be the sole principle of
|
|
motion or of rest. If, then, it is by constraint that the earth now
|
|
keeps its place, the so-called 'whirling' movement by which its
|
|
parts came together at the centre was also constrained. (The form of
|
|
causation supposed they all borrow from observations of liquids and of
|
|
air, in which the larger and heavier bodies always move to the
|
|
centre of the whirl. This is thought by all those who try to
|
|
generate the heavens to explain why the earth came together at the
|
|
centre. They then seek a reason for its staying there; and some say,
|
|
in the manner explained, that the reason is its size and flatness,
|
|
others, with Empedocles, that the motion of the heavens, moving
|
|
about it at a higher speed, prevents movement of the earth, as the
|
|
water in a cup, when the cup is given a circular motion, though it
|
|
is often underneath the bronze, is for this same reason prevented from
|
|
moving with the downward movement which is natural to it.) But suppose
|
|
both the 'whirl' and its flatness (the air beneath being withdrawn)
|
|
cease to prevent the earth's motion, where will the earth move to
|
|
then? Its movement to the centre was constrained, and its rest at
|
|
the centre is due to constraint; but there must be some motion which
|
|
is natural to it. Will this be upward motion or downward or what? It
|
|
must have some motion; and if upward and downward motion are alike
|
|
to it, and the air above the earth does not prevent upward movement,
|
|
then no more could air below it prevent downward movement. For the
|
|
same cause must necessarily have the same effect on the same thing.
|
|
|
|
Further, against Empedocles there is another point which might be
|
|
made. When the elements were separated off by Hate, what caused the
|
|
earth to keep its place? Surely the 'whirl' cannot have been then also
|
|
the cause. It is absurd too not to perceive that, while the whirling
|
|
movement may have been responsible for the original coming together of
|
|
the art of earth at the centre, the question remains, why now do all
|
|
heavy bodies move to the earth. For the whirl surely does not come
|
|
near us. Why, again, does fire move upward? Not, surely, because of
|
|
the whirl. But if fire is naturally such as to move in a certain
|
|
direction, clearly the same may be supposed to hold of earth. Again,
|
|
it cannot be the whirl which determines the heavy and the light.
|
|
Rather that movement caused the pre-existent heavy and light things to
|
|
go to the middle and stay on the surface respectively. Thus, before
|
|
ever the whirl began, heavy and light existed; and what can have
|
|
been the ground of their distinction, or the manner and direction of
|
|
their natural movements? In the infinite chaos there can have been
|
|
neither above nor below, and it is by these that heavy and light are
|
|
determined.
|
|
|
|
It is to these causes that most writers pay attention: but there are
|
|
some, Anaximander, for instance, among the ancients, who say that
|
|
the earth keeps its place because of its indifference. Motion upward
|
|
and downward and sideways were all, they thought, equally
|
|
inappropriate to that which is set at the centre and indifferently
|
|
related to every extreme point; and to move in contrary directions
|
|
at the same time was impossible: so it must needs remain still. This
|
|
view is ingenious but not true. The argument would prove that
|
|
everything, whatever it be, which is put at the centre, must stay
|
|
there. Fire, then, will rest at the centre: for the proof turns on
|
|
no peculiar property of earth. But this does not follow. The
|
|
observed facts about earth are not only that it remains at the centre,
|
|
but also that it moves to the centre. The place to which any
|
|
fragment of earth moves must necessarily be the place to which the
|
|
whole moves; and in the place to which a thing naturally moves, it
|
|
will naturally rest. The reason then is not in the fact that the earth
|
|
is indifferently related to every extreme point: for this would
|
|
apply to any body, whereas movement to the centre is peculiar to
|
|
earth. Again it is absurd to look for a reason why the earth remains
|
|
at the centre and not for a reason why fire remains at the
|
|
extremity. If the extremity is the natural place of fire, clearly
|
|
earth must also have a natural place. But suppose that the centre is
|
|
not its place, and that the reason of its remaining there is this
|
|
necessity of indifference-on the analogy of the hair which, it is
|
|
said, however great the tension, will not break under it, if it be
|
|
evenly distributed, or of the men who, though exceedingly hungry and
|
|
thirsty, and both equally, yet being equidistant from food and
|
|
drink, is therefore bound to stay where he is-even so, it still
|
|
remains to explain why fire stays at the extremities. It is strange,
|
|
too, to ask about things staying still but not about their
|
|
motion,-why, I mean, one thing, if nothing stops it, moves up, and
|
|
another thing to the centre. Again, their statements are not true.
|
|
It happens, indeed, to be the case that a thing to which movement this
|
|
way and that is equally inappropriate is obliged to remain at the
|
|
centre. But so far as their argument goes, instead of remaining there,
|
|
it will move, only not as a mass but in fragments. For the argument
|
|
applies equally to fire. Fire, if set at the centre, should stay
|
|
there, like earth, since it will be indifferently related to every
|
|
point on the extremity. Nevertheless it will move, as in fact it
|
|
always does move when nothing stops it, away from the centre to the
|
|
extremity. It will not, however, move in a mass to a single point on
|
|
the circumference-the only possible result on the lines of the
|
|
indifference theory-but rather each corresponding portion of fire to
|
|
the corresponding part of the extremity, each fourth part, for
|
|
instance, to a fourth part of the circumference. For since no body
|
|
is a point, it will have parts. The expansion, when the body increased
|
|
the place occupied, would be on the same principle as the contraction,
|
|
in which the place was diminished. Thus, for all the indifference
|
|
theory shows to the contrary, earth also would have moved in this
|
|
manner away from the centre, unless the centre had been its natural
|
|
place.
|
|
|
|
We have now outlined the views held as to the shape, position, and
|
|
rest or movement of the earth.
|
|
|
|
14
|
|
|
|
Let us first decide the question whether the earth moves or is at
|
|
rest. For, as we said, there are some who make it one of the stars,
|
|
and others who, setting it at the centre, suppose it to be 'rolled'
|
|
and in motion about the pole as axis. That both views are untenable
|
|
will be clear if we take as our starting-point the fact that the
|
|
earth's motion, whether the earth be at the centre or away from it,
|
|
must needs be a constrained motion. It cannot be the movement of the
|
|
earth itself. If it were, any portion of it would have this
|
|
movement; but in fact every part moves in a straight line to the
|
|
centre. Being, then, constrained and unnatural, the movement could not
|
|
be eternal. But the order of the universe is eternal. Again,
|
|
everything that moves with the circular movement, except the first
|
|
sphere, is observed to be passed, and to move with more than one
|
|
motion. The earth, then, also, whether it move about the centre or
|
|
as stationary at it, must necessarily move with two motions. But if
|
|
this were so, there would have to be passings and turnings of the
|
|
fixed stars. Yet no such thing is observed. The same stars always rise
|
|
and set in the same parts of the earth.
|
|
|
|
Further, the natural movement of the earth, part and whole alike, is
|
|
the centre of the whole-whence the fact that it is now actually
|
|
situated at the centre-but it might be questioned since both centres
|
|
are the same, which centre it is that portions of earth and other
|
|
heavy things move to. Is this their goal because it is the centre of
|
|
the earth or because it is the centre of the whole? The goal,
|
|
surely, must be the centre of the whole. For fire and other light
|
|
things move to the extremity of the area which contains the centre. It
|
|
happens, however, that the centre of the earth and of the whole is the
|
|
same. Thus they do move to the centre of the earth, but
|
|
accidentally, in virtue of the fact that the earth's centre lies at
|
|
the centre of the whole. That the centre of the earth is the goal of
|
|
their movement is indicated by the fact that heavy bodies moving
|
|
towards the earth do not parallel but so as to make equal angles,
|
|
and thus to a single centre, that of the earth. It is clear, then,
|
|
that the earth must be at the centre and immovable, not only for the
|
|
reasons already given, but also because heavy bodies forcibly thrown
|
|
quite straight upward return to the point from which they started,
|
|
even if they are thrown to an infinite distance. From these
|
|
considerations then it is clear that the earth does not move and
|
|
does not lie elsewhere than at the centre.
|
|
|
|
From what we have said the explanation of the earth's immobility
|
|
is also apparent. If it is the nature of earth, as observation
|
|
shows, to move from any point to the centre, as of fire contrariwise
|
|
to move from the centre to the extremity, it is impossible that any
|
|
portion of earth should move away from the centre except by
|
|
constraint. For a single thing has a single movement, and a simple
|
|
thing a simple: contrary movements cannot belong to the same thing,
|
|
and movement away from the centre is the contrary of movement to it.
|
|
If then no portion of earth can move away from the centre, obviously
|
|
still less can the earth as a whole so move. For it is the nature of
|
|
the whole to move to the point to which the part naturally moves.
|
|
Since, then, it would require a force greater than itself to move
|
|
it, it must needs stay at the centre. This view is further supported
|
|
by the contributions of mathematicians to astronomy, since the
|
|
observations made as the shapes change by which the order of the stars
|
|
is determined, are fully accounted for on the hypothesis that the
|
|
earth lies at the centre. Of the position of the earth and of the
|
|
manner of its rest or movement, our discussion may here end.
|
|
|
|
Its shape must necessarily be spherical. For every portion of
|
|
earth has weight until it reaches the centre, and the jostling of
|
|
parts greater and smaller would bring about not a waved surface, but
|
|
rather compression and convergence of part and part until the centre
|
|
is reached. The process should be conceived by supposing the earth
|
|
to come into being in the way that some of the natural philosophers
|
|
describe. Only they attribute the downward movement to constraint, and
|
|
it is better to keep to the truth and say that the reason of this
|
|
motion is that a thing which possesses weight is naturally endowed
|
|
with a centripetal movement. When the mixture, then, was merely
|
|
potential, the things that were separated off moved similarly from
|
|
every side towards the centre. Whether the parts which came together
|
|
at the centre were distributed at the extremities evenly, or in some
|
|
other way, makes no difference. If, on the one hand, there were a
|
|
similar movement from each quarter of the extremity to the single
|
|
centre, it is obvious that the resulting mass would be similar on
|
|
every side. For if an equal amount is added on every side the
|
|
extremity of the mass will be everywhere equidistant from its
|
|
centre, i.e. the figure will be spherical. But neither will it in
|
|
any way affect the argument if there is not a similar accession of
|
|
concurrent fragments from every side. For the greater quantity,
|
|
finding a lesser in front of it, must necessarily drive it on, both
|
|
having an impulse whose goal is the centre, and the greater weight
|
|
driving the lesser forward till this goal is reached. In this we
|
|
have also the solution of a possible difficulty. The earth, it might
|
|
be argued, is at the centre and spherical in shape: if, then, a weight
|
|
many times that of the earth were added to one hemisphere, the
|
|
centre of the earth and of the whole will no longer be coincident.
|
|
So that either the earth will not stay still at the centre, or if it
|
|
does, it will be at rest without having its centre at the place to
|
|
which it is still its nature to move. Such is the difficulty. A
|
|
short consideration will give us an easy answer, if we first give
|
|
precision to our postulate that any body endowed with weight, of
|
|
whatever size, moves towards the centre. Clearly it will not stop when
|
|
its edge touches the centre. The greater quantity must prevail until
|
|
the body's centre occupies the centre. For that is the goal of its
|
|
impulse. Now it makes no difference whether we apply this to a clod or
|
|
common fragment of earth or to the earth as a whole. The fact
|
|
indicated does not depend upon degrees of size but applies universally
|
|
to everything that has the centripetal impulse. Therefore earth in
|
|
motion, whether in a mass or in fragments, necessarily continues to
|
|
move until it occupies the centre equally every way, the less being
|
|
forced to equalize itself by the greater owing to the forward drive of
|
|
the impulse.
|
|
|
|
If the earth was generated, then, it must have been formed in this
|
|
way, and so clearly its generation was spherical; and if it is
|
|
ungenerated and has remained so always, its character must be that
|
|
which the initial generation, if it had occurred, would have given it.
|
|
But the spherical shape, necessitated by this argument, follows also
|
|
from the fact that the motions of heavy bodies always make equal
|
|
angles, and are not parallel. This would be the natural form of
|
|
movement towards what is naturally spherical. Either then the earth is
|
|
spherical or it is at least naturally spherical. And it is right to
|
|
call anything that which nature intends it to be, and which belongs to
|
|
it, rather than that which it is by constraint and contrary to nature.
|
|
The evidence of the senses further corroborates this. How else would
|
|
eclipses of the moon show segments shaped as we see them? As it is,
|
|
the shapes which the moon itself each month shows are of every kind
|
|
straight, gibbous, and concave-but in eclipses the outline is always
|
|
curved: and, since it is the interposition of the earth that makes the
|
|
eclipse, the form of this line will be caused by the form of the
|
|
earth's surface, which is therefore spherical. Again, our observations
|
|
of the stars make it evident, not only that the earth is circular, but
|
|
also that it is a circle of no great size. For quite a small change of
|
|
position to south or north causes a manifest alteration of the
|
|
horizon. There is much change, I mean, in the stars which are
|
|
overhead, and the stars seen are different, as one moves northward
|
|
or southward. Indeed there are some stars seen in Egypt and in the
|
|
neighbourhood of Cyprus which are not seen in the northerly regions;
|
|
and stars, which in the north are never beyond the range of
|
|
observation, in those regions rise and set. All of which goes to
|
|
show not only that the earth is circular in shape, but also that it is
|
|
a sphere of no great size: for otherwise the effect of so slight a
|
|
change of place would not be quickly apparent. Hence one should not be
|
|
too sure of the incredibility of the view of those who conceive that
|
|
there is continuity between the parts about the pillars of Hercules
|
|
and the parts about India, and that in this way the ocean is one. As
|
|
further evidence in favour of this they quote the case of elephants, a
|
|
species occurring in each of these extreme regions, suggesting that
|
|
the common characteristic of these extremes is explained by their
|
|
continuity. Also, those mathematicians who try to calculate the size
|
|
of the earth's circumference arrive at the figure 400,000 stades. This
|
|
indicates not only that the earth's mass is spherical in shape, but
|
|
also that as compared with the stars it is not of great size.
|
|
|
|
Book III
|
|
|
|
1
|
|
|
|
WE have already discussed the first heaven and its parts, the moving
|
|
stars within it, the matter of which these are composed and their
|
|
bodily constitution, and we have also shown that they are
|
|
ungenerated and indestructible. Now things that we call natural are
|
|
either substances or functions and attributes of substances. As
|
|
substances I class the simple bodies-fire, earth, and the other
|
|
terms of the series-and all things composed of them; for example,
|
|
the heaven as a whole and its parts, animals, again, and plants and
|
|
their parts. By attributes and functions I mean the movements of these
|
|
and of all other things in which they have power in themselves to
|
|
cause movement, and also their alterations and reciprocal
|
|
transformations. It is obvious, then, that the greater part of the
|
|
inquiry into nature concerns bodies: for a natural substance is either
|
|
a body or a thing which cannot come into existence without body and
|
|
magnitude. This appears plainly from an analysis of the character of
|
|
natural things, and equally from an inspection of the instances of
|
|
inquiry into nature. Since, then, we have spoken of the primary
|
|
element, of its bodily constitution, and of its freedom from
|
|
destruction and generation, it remains to speak of the other two. In
|
|
speaking of them we shall be obliged also to inquire into generation
|
|
and destruction. For if there is generation anywhere, it must be in
|
|
these elements and things composed of them.
|
|
|
|
This is indeed the first question we have to ask: is generation a
|
|
fact or not? Earlier speculation was at variance both with itself
|
|
and with the views here put forward as to the true answer to this
|
|
question. Some removed generation and destruction from the world
|
|
altogether. Nothing that is, they said, is generated or destroyed, and
|
|
our conviction to the contrary is an illusion. So maintained the
|
|
school of Melissus and Parmenides. But however excellent their
|
|
theories may otherwise be, anyhow they cannot be held to speak as
|
|
students of nature. There may be things not subject to generation or
|
|
any kind of movement, but if so they belong to another and a higher
|
|
inquiry than the study of nature. They, however, had no idea of any
|
|
form of being other than the substance of things perceived; and when
|
|
they saw, what no one previously had seen, that there could be no
|
|
knowledge or wisdom without some such unchanging entities, they
|
|
naturally transferred what was true of them to things perceived.
|
|
Others, perhaps intentionally, maintain precisely the contrary opinion
|
|
to this. It has been asserted that everything in the world was subject
|
|
to generation and nothing was ungenerated, but that after being
|
|
generated some things remained indestructible while the rest were
|
|
again destroyed. This had been asserted in the first instance by
|
|
Hesiod and his followers, but afterwards outside his circle by the
|
|
earliest natural philosophers. But what these thinkers maintained
|
|
was that all else has been generated and, as they said, 'is flowing
|
|
away, nothing having any solidity, except one single thing which
|
|
persists as the basis of all these transformations. So we may
|
|
interpret the statements of Heraclitus of Ephesus and many others. And
|
|
some subject all bodies whatever to generation, by means of the
|
|
composition and separation of planes.
|
|
|
|
Discussion of the other views may be postponed. But this last theory
|
|
which composes every body of planes is, as the most superficial
|
|
observation shows, in many respects in plain contradiction with
|
|
mathematics. It is, however, wrong to remove the foundations of a
|
|
science unless you can replace them with others more convincing.
|
|
And, secondly, the same theory which composes solids of planes clearly
|
|
composes planes of lines and lines of points, so that a part of a line
|
|
need not be a line. This matter has been already considered in our
|
|
discussion of movement, where we have shown that an indivisible length
|
|
is impossible. But with respect to natural bodies there are
|
|
impossibilities involved in the view which asserts indivisible
|
|
lines, which we may briefly consider at this point. For the impossible
|
|
consequences which result from this view in the mathematical sphere
|
|
will reproduce themselves when it is applied to physical bodies, but
|
|
there will be difficulties in physics which are not present in
|
|
mathematics; for mathematics deals with an abstract and physics with a
|
|
more concrete object. There are many attributes necessarily present in
|
|
physical bodies which are necessarily excluded by indivisibility;
|
|
all attributes, in fact, which are divisible. There can be nothing
|
|
divisible in an indivisible thing, but the attributes of bodies are
|
|
all divisible in one of two ways. They are divisible into kinds, as
|
|
colour is divided into white and black, and they are divisible per
|
|
accidens when that which has them is divisible. In this latter sense
|
|
attributes which are simple are nevertheless divisible. Attributes
|
|
of this kind will serve, therefore, to illustrate the impossibility of
|
|
the view. It is impossible, if two parts of a thing have no weight,
|
|
that the two together should have weight. But either all perceptible
|
|
bodies or some, such as earth and water, have weight, as these
|
|
thinkers would themselves admit. Now if the point has no weight,
|
|
clearly the lines have not either, and, if they have not, neither have
|
|
the planes. Therefore no body has weight. It is, further, manifest
|
|
that their point cannot have weight. For while a heavy thing may
|
|
always be heavier than something and a light thing lighter than
|
|
something, a thing which is heavier or lighter than something need not
|
|
be itself heavy or light, just as a large thing is larger than others,
|
|
but what is larger is not always large. A thing which, judged
|
|
absolutely, is small may none the less be larger than other things.
|
|
Whatever, then, is heavy and also heavier than something else, must
|
|
exceed this by something which is heavy. A heavy thing therefore is
|
|
always divisible. But it is common ground that a point is indivisible.
|
|
Again, suppose that what is heavy or weight is a dense body, and
|
|
what is light rare. Dense differs from rare in containing more
|
|
matter in the same cubic area. A point, then, if it may be heavy or
|
|
light, may be dense or rare. But the dense is divisible while a
|
|
point is indivisible. And if what is heavy must be either hard or
|
|
soft, an impossible consequence is easy to draw. For a thing is soft
|
|
if its surface can be pressed in, hard if it cannot; and if it can
|
|
be pressed in it is divisible.
|
|
|
|
Moreover, no weight can consist of parts not possessing weight.
|
|
For how, except by the merest fiction, can they specify the number and
|
|
character of the parts which will produce weight? And, further, when
|
|
one weight is greater than another, the difference is a third
|
|
weight; from which it will follow that every indivisible part
|
|
possesses weight. For suppose that a body of four points possesses
|
|
weight. A body composed of more than four points will superior in
|
|
weight to it, a thing which has weight. But the difference between
|
|
weight and weight must be a weight, as the difference between white
|
|
and whiter is white. Here the difference which makes the superior
|
|
weight heavier is the single point which remains when the common
|
|
number, four, is subtracted. A single point, therefore, has weight.
|
|
|
|
Further, to assume, on the one hand, that the planes can only be put
|
|
in linear contact would be ridiculous. For just as there are two
|
|
ways of putting lines together, namely, end to and side by side, so
|
|
there must be two ways of putting planes together. Lines can be put
|
|
together so that contact is linear by laying one along the other,
|
|
though not by putting them end to end. But if, similarly, in putting
|
|
the lanes together, superficial contact is allowed as an alternative
|
|
to linear, that method will give them bodies which are not any element
|
|
nor composed of elements. Again, if it is the number of planes in a
|
|
body that makes one heavier than another, as the Timaeus explains,
|
|
clearly the line and the point will have weight. For the three cases
|
|
are, as we said before, analogous. But if the reason of differences of
|
|
weight is not this, but rather the heaviness of earth and the
|
|
lightness of fire, then some of the planes will be light and others
|
|
heavy (which involves a similar distinction in the lines and the
|
|
points); the earthplane, I mean, will be heavier than the
|
|
fire-plane. In general, the result is either that there is no
|
|
magnitude at all, or that all magnitude could be done away with. For a
|
|
point is to a line as a line is to a plane and as a plane is to a
|
|
body. Now the various forms in passing into one another will each be
|
|
resolved into its ultimate constituents. It might happen therefore
|
|
that nothing existed except points, and that there was no body at all.
|
|
A further consideration is that if time is similarly constituted,
|
|
there would be, or might be, a time at which it was done away with.
|
|
For the indivisible now is like a point in a line. The same
|
|
consequences follow from composing the heaven of numbers, as some of
|
|
the Pythagoreans do who make all nature out of numbers. For natural
|
|
bodies are manifestly endowed with weight and lightness, but an
|
|
assemblage of units can neither be composed to form a body nor possess
|
|
weight.
|
|
|
|
2
|
|
|
|
The necessity that each of the simple bodies should have a natural
|
|
movement may be shown as follows. They manifestly move, and if they
|
|
have no proper movement they must move by constraint: and the
|
|
constrained is the same as the unnatural. Now an unnatural movement
|
|
presupposes a natural movement which it contravenes, and which,
|
|
however many the unnatural movements, is always one. For naturally a
|
|
thing moves in one way, while its unnatural movements are manifold.
|
|
The same may be shown, from the fact of rest. Rest, also, must
|
|
either be constrained or natural, constrained in a place to which
|
|
movement was constrained, natural in a place movement to which was
|
|
natural. Now manifestly there is a body which is at rest at the
|
|
centre. If then this rest is natural to it, clearly motion to this
|
|
place is natural to it. If, on the other hand, its rest is
|
|
constrained, what is hindering its motion? Something, which is at
|
|
rest: but if so, we shall simply repeat the same argument; and
|
|
either we shall come to an ultimate something to which rest where it
|
|
is or we shall have an infinite process, which is impossible. The
|
|
hindrance to its movement, then, we will suppose, is a moving thing-as
|
|
Empedocles says that it is the vortex which keeps the earth still-:
|
|
but in that case we ask, where would it have moved to but for the
|
|
vortex? It could not move infinitely; for to traverse an infinite is
|
|
impossible, and impossibilities do not happen. So the moving thing
|
|
must stop somewhere, and there rest not by constraint but naturally.
|
|
But a natural rest proves a natural movement to the place of rest.
|
|
Hence Leucippus and Democritus, who say that the primary bodies are in
|
|
perpetual movement in the void or infinite, may be asked to explain
|
|
the manner of their motion and the kind of movement which is natural
|
|
to them. For if the various elements are constrained by one another to
|
|
move as they do, each must still have a natural movement which the
|
|
constrained contravenes, and the prime mover must cause motion not
|
|
by constraint but naturally. If there is no ultimate natural cause
|
|
of movement and each preceding term in the series is always moved by
|
|
constraint, we shall have an infinite process. The same difficulty
|
|
is involved even if it is supposed, as we read in the Timaeus, that
|
|
before the ordered world was made the elements moved without order.
|
|
Their movement must have been due either to constraint or to their
|
|
nature. And if their movement was natural, a moment's consideration
|
|
shows that there was already an ordered world. For the prime mover
|
|
must cause motion in virtue of its own natural movement, and the other
|
|
bodies, moving without constraint, as they came to rest in their
|
|
proper places, would fall into the order in which they now stand,
|
|
the heavy bodies moving towards the centre and the light bodies away
|
|
from it. But that is the order of their distribution in our world.
|
|
There is a further question, too, which might be asked. Is it possible
|
|
or impossible that bodies in unordered movement should combine in some
|
|
cases into combinations like those of which bodies of nature's
|
|
composing are composed, such, I mean, as bones and flesh? Yet this
|
|
is what Empedocles asserts to have occurred under Love. 'Many a head',
|
|
says he, 'came to birth without a neck.' The answer to the view that
|
|
there are infinite bodies moving in an infinite is that, if the
|
|
cause of movement is single, they must move with a single motion,
|
|
and therefore not without order; and if, on the other hand, the causes
|
|
are of infinite variety, their motions too must be infinitely
|
|
varied. For a finite number of causes would produce a kind of order,
|
|
since absence of order is not proved by diversity of direction in
|
|
motions: indeed, in the world we know, not all bodies, but only bodies
|
|
of the same kind, have a common goal of movement. Again, disorderly
|
|
movement means in reality unnatural movement, since the order proper
|
|
to perceptible things is their nature. And there is also absurdity and
|
|
impossibility in the notion that the disorderly movement is infinitely
|
|
continued. For the nature of things is the nature which most of them
|
|
possess for most of the time. Thus their view brings them into the
|
|
contrary position that disorder is natural, and order or system
|
|
unnatural. But no natural fact can originate in chance. This is a
|
|
point which Anaxagoras seems to have thoroughly grasped; for he starts
|
|
his cosmogony from unmoved things. The others, it is true, make things
|
|
collect together somehow before they try to produce motion and
|
|
separation. But there is no sense in starting generation from an
|
|
original state in which bodies are separated and in movement. Hence
|
|
Empedocles begins after the process ruled by Love: for he could not
|
|
have constructed the heaven by building it up out of bodies in
|
|
separation, making them to combine by the power of Love, since our
|
|
world has its constituent elements in separation, and therefore
|
|
presupposes a previous state of unity and combination.
|
|
|
|
These arguments make it plain that every body has its natural
|
|
movement, which is not constrained or contrary to its nature. We go on
|
|
to show that there are certain bodies whose necessary impetus is
|
|
that of weight and lightness. Of necessity, we assert, they must move,
|
|
and a moved thing which has no natural impetus cannot move either
|
|
towards or away from the centre. Suppose a body A without weight,
|
|
and a body B endowed with weight. Suppose the weightless body to
|
|
move the distance CD, while B in the same time moves the distance
|
|
CE, which will be greater since the heavy thing must move further. Let
|
|
the heavy body then be divided in the proportion CE: CD (for there
|
|
is no reason why a part of B should not stand in this relation to
|
|
the whole). Now if the whole moves the whole distance CE, the part
|
|
must in the same time move the distance CD. A weightless body,
|
|
therefore, and one which has weight will move the same distance, which
|
|
is impossible. And the same argument would fit the case of
|
|
lightness. Again, a body which is in motion but has neither weight nor
|
|
lightness, must be moved by constraint, and must continue its
|
|
constrained movement infinitely. For there will be a force which moves
|
|
it, and the smaller and lighter a body is the further will a given
|
|
force move it. Now let A, the weightless body, be moved the distance
|
|
CE, and B, which has weight, be moved in the same time the distance
|
|
CD. Dividing the heavy body in the proportion CE:CD, we subtract
|
|
from the heavy body a part which will in the same time move the
|
|
distance CE, since the whole moved CD: for the relative speeds of
|
|
the two bodies will be in inverse ratio to their respective sizes.
|
|
Thus the weightless body will move the same distance as the heavy in
|
|
the same time. But this is impossible. Hence, since the motion of
|
|
the weightless body will cover a greater distance than any that is
|
|
suggested, it will continue infinitely. It is therefore obvious that
|
|
every body must have a definite weight or lightness. But since
|
|
'nature' means a source of movement within the thing itself, while a
|
|
force is a source of movement in something other than it or in
|
|
itself qua other, and since movement is always due either to nature or
|
|
to constraint, movement which is natural, as downward movement is to a
|
|
stone, will be merely accelerated by an external force, while an
|
|
unnatural movement will be due to the force alone. In either case
|
|
the air is as it were instrumental to the force. For air is both light
|
|
and heavy, and thus qua light produces upward motion, being
|
|
propelled and set in motion by the force, and qua heavy produces a
|
|
downward motion. In either case the force transmits the movement to
|
|
the body by first, as it were, impregnating the air. That is why a
|
|
body moved by constraint continues to move when that which gave the
|
|
impulse ceases to accompany it. Otherwise, i.e. if the air were not
|
|
endowed with this function, constrained movement would be
|
|
impossible. And the natural movement of a body may be helped on in the
|
|
same way. This discussion suffices to show (1) that all bodies are
|
|
either light or heavy, and (2) how unnatural movement takes place.
|
|
|
|
From what has been said earlier it is plain that there cannot be
|
|
generation either of everything or in an absolute sense of anything.
|
|
It is impossible that everything should be generated, unless an
|
|
extra-corporeal void is possible. For, assuming generation, the
|
|
place which is to be occupied by that which is coming to be, must have
|
|
been previously occupied by void in which no body was. Now it is quite
|
|
possible for one body to be generated out of another, air for instance
|
|
out of fire, but in the absence of any pre-existing mass generation is
|
|
impossible. That which is potentially a certain kind of body may, it
|
|
is true, become such in actuality, But if the potential body was not
|
|
already in actuality some other kind of body, the existence of an
|
|
extra-corporeal void must be admitted.
|
|
|
|
3
|
|
|
|
It remains to say what bodies are subject to generation, and why.
|
|
Since in every case knowledge depends on what is primary, and the
|
|
elements are the primary constituents of bodies, we must ask which
|
|
of such bodies are elements, and why; and after that what is their
|
|
number and character. The answer will be plain if we first explain
|
|
what kind of substance an element is. An element, we take it, is a
|
|
body into which other bodies may be analysed, present in them
|
|
potentially or in actuality (which of these, is still disputable), and
|
|
not itself divisible into bodies different in form. That, or something
|
|
like it, is what all men in every case mean by element. Now if what we
|
|
have described is an element, clearly there must be such bodies. For
|
|
flesh and wood and all other similar bodies contain potentially fire
|
|
and earth, since one sees these elements exuded from them; and, on the
|
|
other hand, neither in potentiality nor in actuality does fire contain
|
|
flesh or wood, or it would exude them. Similarly, even if there were
|
|
only one elementary body, it would not contain them. For though it
|
|
will be either flesh or bone or something else, that does not at
|
|
once show that it contained these in potentiality: the further
|
|
question remains, in what manner it becomes them. Now Anaxagoras
|
|
opposes Empedocles' view of the elements. Empedocles says that fire
|
|
and earth and the related bodies are elementary bodies of which all
|
|
things are composed; but this Anaxagoras denies. His elements are
|
|
the homoeomerous things, viz. flesh, bone, and the like. Earth and
|
|
fire are mixtures, composed of them and all the other seeds, each
|
|
consisting of a collection of all the homoeomerous bodies,
|
|
separately invisible; and that explains why from these two bodies
|
|
all others are generated. (To him fire and aither are the same thing.)
|
|
But since every natural body has it proper movement, and movements are
|
|
either simple or mixed, mixed in mixed bodies and simple in simple,
|
|
there must obviously be simple bodies; for there are simple movements.
|
|
It is plain, then, that there are elements, and why.
|
|
|
|
4
|
|
|
|
The next question to consider is whether the elements are finite
|
|
or infinite in number, and, if finite, what their number is. Let us
|
|
first show reason or denying that their number is infinite, as some
|
|
suppose. We begin with the view of Anaxagoras that all the
|
|
homoeomerous bodies are elements. Any one who adopts this view
|
|
misapprehends the meaning of element. Observation shows that even
|
|
mixed bodies are often divisible into homoeomerous parts; examples are
|
|
flesh, bone, wood, and stone. Since then the composite cannot be an
|
|
element, not every homoeomerous body can be an element; only, as we
|
|
said before, that which is not divisible into bodies different in
|
|
form. But even taking 'element' as they do, they need not assert an
|
|
infinity of elements, since the hypothesis of a finite number will
|
|
give identical results. Indeed even two or three such bodies serve the
|
|
purpose as well, as Empedocles' attempt shows. Again, even on their
|
|
view it turns out that all things are not composed of homocomerous
|
|
bodies. They do not pretend that a face is composed of faces, or
|
|
that any other natural conformation is composed of parts like
|
|
itself. Obviously then it would be better to assume a finite number of
|
|
principles. They should, in fact, be as few as possible,
|
|
consistently with proving what has to be proved. This is the common
|
|
demand of mathematicians, who always assume as principles things
|
|
finite either in kind or in number. Again, if body is distinguished
|
|
from body by the appropriate qualitative difference, and there is a
|
|
limit to the number of differences (for the difference lies in
|
|
qualities apprehended by sense, which are in fact finite in number,
|
|
though this requires proof), then manifestly there is necessarily a
|
|
limit to the number of elements.
|
|
|
|
There is, further, another view-that of Leucippus and Democritus
|
|
of Abdera-the implications of which are also unacceptable. The primary
|
|
masses, according to them, are infinite in number and indivisible in
|
|
mass: one cannot turn into many nor many into one; and all things
|
|
are generated by their combination and involution. Now this view in
|
|
a sense makes things out to be numbers or composed of numbers. The
|
|
exposition is not clear, but this is its real meaning. And further,
|
|
they say that since the atomic bodies differ in shape, and there is an
|
|
infinity of shapes, there is an infinity of simple bodies. But they
|
|
have never explained in detail the shapes of the various elements,
|
|
except so far to allot the sphere to fire. Air, water, and the rest
|
|
they distinguished by the relative size of the atom, assuming that the
|
|
atomic substance was a sort of master-seed for each and every element.
|
|
Now, in the first place, they make the mistake already noticed. The
|
|
principles which they assume are not limited in number, though such
|
|
limitation would necessitate no other alteration in their theory.
|
|
Further, if the differences of bodies are not infinite, plainly the
|
|
elements will not be an infinity. Besides, a view which asserts atomic
|
|
bodies must needs come into conflict with the mathematical sciences,
|
|
in addition to invalidating many common opinions and apparent data
|
|
of sense perception. But of these things we have already spoken in our
|
|
discussion of time and movement. They are also bound to contradict
|
|
themselves. For if the elements are atomic, air, earth, and water
|
|
cannot be differentiated by the relative sizes of their atoms, since
|
|
then they could not be generated out of one another. The extrusion
|
|
of the largest atoms is a process that will in time exhaust the
|
|
supply; and it is by such a process that they account for the
|
|
generation of water, air, and earth from one another. Again, even on
|
|
their own presuppositions it does not seem as if the clements would be
|
|
infinite in number. The atoms differ in figure, and all figures are
|
|
composed of pyramids, rectilinear the case of rectilinear figures,
|
|
while the sphere has eight pyramidal parts. The figures must have
|
|
their principles, and, whether these are one or two or more, the
|
|
simple bodies must be the same in number as they. Again, if every
|
|
element has its proper movement, and a simple body has a simple
|
|
movement, and the number of simple movements is not infinite,
|
|
because the simple motions are only two and the number of places is
|
|
not infinite, on these grounds also we should have to deny that the
|
|
number of elements is infinite.
|
|
|
|
5
|
|
|
|
Since the number of the elements must be limited, it remains to
|
|
inquire whether there is more than one element. Some assume one
|
|
only, which is according to some water, to others air, to others fire,
|
|
to others again something finer than water and denser than air, an
|
|
infinite body-so they say-bracing all the heavens.
|
|
|
|
Now those who decide for a single element, which is either water
|
|
or air or a body finer than water and denser than air, and proceed
|
|
to generate other things out of it by use of the attributes density
|
|
and rarity, all alike fail to observe the fact that they are depriving
|
|
the element of its priority. Generation out of the elements is, as
|
|
they say, synthesis, and generation into the elements is analysis,
|
|
so that the body with the finer parts must have priority in the
|
|
order of nature. But they say that fire is of all bodies the finest.
|
|
Hence fire will be first in the natural order. And whether the
|
|
finest body is fire or not makes no difference; anyhow it must be
|
|
one of the other bodies that is primary and not that which is
|
|
intermediate. Again, density and rarity, as instruments of generation,
|
|
are equivalent to fineness and coarseness, since the fine is rare, and
|
|
coarse in their use means dense. But fineness and coarseness, again,
|
|
are equivalent to greatness and smallness, since a thing with small
|
|
parts is fine and a thing with large parts coarse. For that which
|
|
spreads itself out widely is fine, and a thing composed of small parts
|
|
is so spread out. In the end, then, they distinguish the various other
|
|
substances from the element by the greatness and smallness of their
|
|
parts. This method of distinction makes all judgement relative.
|
|
There will be no absolute distinction between fire, water, and air,
|
|
but one and the same body will be relatively to this fire,
|
|
relatively to something else air. The same difficulty is involved
|
|
equally in the view elements and distinguishes them by their greatness
|
|
and smallness. The principle of distinction between bodies being
|
|
quantity, the various sizes will be in a definite ratio, and
|
|
whatever bodies are in this ratio to one another must be air, fire,
|
|
earth, and water respectively. For the ratios of smaller bodies may be
|
|
repeated among greater bodies.
|
|
|
|
Those who start from fire as the single element, while avoiding this
|
|
difficulty, involve themselves in many others. Some of them give
|
|
fire a particular shape, like those who make it a pyramid, and this on
|
|
one of two grounds. The reason given may be-more crudely-that the
|
|
pyramid is the most piercing of figures as fire is of bodies,
|
|
or-more ingeniously-the position may be supported by the following
|
|
argument. As all bodies are composed of that which has the finest
|
|
parts, so all solid figures are composed of pryamids: but the finest
|
|
body is fire, while among figures the pyramid is primary and has the
|
|
smallest parts; and the primary body must have the primary figure:
|
|
therefore fire will be a pyramid. Others, again, express no opinion on
|
|
the subject of its figure, but simply regard it as the of the finest
|
|
parts, which in combination will form other bodies, as the fusing of
|
|
gold-dust produces solid gold. Both of these views involve the same
|
|
difficulties. For (1) if, on the one hand, they make the primary
|
|
body an atom, the view will be open to the objections already advanced
|
|
against the atomic theory. And further the theory is inconsistent with
|
|
a regard for the facts of nature. For if all bodies are quantitatively
|
|
commensurable, and the relative size of the various homoeomerous
|
|
masses and of their several elements are in the same ratio, so that
|
|
the total mass of water, for instance, is related to the total mass of
|
|
air as the elements of each are to one another, and so on, and if
|
|
there is more air than water and, generally, more of the finer body
|
|
than of the coarser, obviously the element of water will be smaller
|
|
than that of air. But the lesser quantity is contained in the greater.
|
|
Therefore the air element is divisible. And the same could be shown of
|
|
fire and of all bodies whose parts are relatively fine. (2) If, on the
|
|
other hand, the primary body is divisible, then (a) those who give
|
|
fire a special shape will have to say that a part of fire is not fire,
|
|
because a pyramid is not composed of pyramids, and also that not every
|
|
body is either an element or composed of elements, since a part of
|
|
fire will be neither fire nor any other element. And (b) those whose
|
|
ground of distinction is size will have to recognize an element
|
|
prior to the element, a regress which continues infinitely, since
|
|
every body is divisible and that which has the smallest parts is the
|
|
element. Further, they too will have to say that the same body is
|
|
relatively to this fire and relatively to that air, to others again
|
|
water and earth.
|
|
|
|
The common error of all views which assume a single element is
|
|
that they allow only one natural movement, which is the same for every
|
|
body. For it is a matter of observation that a natural body
|
|
possesses a principle of movement. If then all bodies are one, all
|
|
will have one movement. With this motion the greater their quantity
|
|
the more they will move, just as fire, in proportion as its quantity
|
|
is greater, moves faster with the upward motion which belongs to it.
|
|
But the fact is that increase of quantity makes many things move the
|
|
faster downward. For these reasons, then, as well as from the
|
|
distinction already established of a plurality of natural movements,
|
|
it is impossible that there should be only one element. But if the
|
|
elements are not an infinity and not reducible to one, they must be
|
|
several and finite in number.
|
|
|
|
6
|
|
|
|
First we must inquire whether the elements are eternal or subject to
|
|
generation and destruction; for when this question has been answered
|
|
their number and character will be manifest. In the first place,
|
|
they cannot be eternal. It is a matter of observation that fire,
|
|
water, and every simple body undergo a process of analysis, which must
|
|
either continue infinitely or stop somewhere. (1) Suppose it infinite.
|
|
Then the time occupied by the process will be infinite, and also
|
|
that occupied by the reverse process of synthesis. For the processes
|
|
of analysis and synthesis succeed one another in the various parts. It
|
|
will follow that there are two infinite times which are mutually
|
|
exclusive, the time occupied by the synthesis, which is infinite,
|
|
being preceded by the period of analysis. There are thus two
|
|
mutually exclusive infinites, which is impossible. (2) Suppose, on the
|
|
other hand, that the analysis stops somewhere. Then the body at
|
|
which it stops will be either atomic or, as Empedocles seems to have
|
|
intended, a divisible body which will yet never be divided. The
|
|
foregoing arguments show that it cannot be an atom; but neither can it
|
|
be a divisible body which analysis will never reach. For a smaller
|
|
body is more easily destroyed than a larger; and a destructive process
|
|
which succeeds in destroying, that is, in resolving into smaller
|
|
bodies, a body of some size, cannot reasonably be expected to fail
|
|
with the smaller body. Now in fire we observe a destruction of two
|
|
kinds: it is destroyed by its contrary when it is quenched, and by
|
|
itself when it dies out. But the effect is produced by a greater
|
|
quantity upon a lesser, and the more quickly the smaller it is. The
|
|
elements of bodies must therefore be subject to destruction and
|
|
generation.
|
|
|
|
Since they are generated, they must be generated either from
|
|
something incorporeal or from a body, and if from a body, either
|
|
from one another or from something else. The theory which generates
|
|
them from something incorporeal requires an extra-corporeal void.
|
|
For everything that comes to be comes to be in something, and that
|
|
in which the generation takes place must either be incorporeal or
|
|
possess body; and if it has body, there will be two bodies in the same
|
|
place at the same time, viz. that which is coming to be and that which
|
|
was previously there, while if it is incorporeal, there must be an
|
|
extra-corporeal void. But we have already shown that this is
|
|
impossible. But, on the other hand, it is equally impossible that
|
|
the elements should be generated from some kind of body. That would
|
|
involve a body distinct from the elements and prior to them. But if
|
|
this body possesses weight or lightness, it will be one of the
|
|
elements; and if it has no tendency to movement, it will be an
|
|
immovable or mathematical entity, and therefore not in a place at all.
|
|
A place in which a thing is at rest is a place in which it might move,
|
|
either by constraint, i.e. unnaturally, or in the absence of
|
|
constraint, i.e. naturally. If, then, it is in a place and
|
|
somewhere, it will be one of the elements; and if it is not in a
|
|
place, nothing can come from it, since that which comes into being and
|
|
that out of which it comes must needs be together. The elements
|
|
therefore cannot be generated from something incorporeal nor from a
|
|
body which is not an element, and the only remaining alternative is
|
|
that they are generated from one another.
|
|
|
|
7
|
|
|
|
We must, therefore, turn to the question, what is the manner of
|
|
their generation from one another? Is it as Empedocles and
|
|
Democritus say, or as those who resolve bodies into planes say, or
|
|
is there yet another possibility? (1) What the followers of Empedocles
|
|
do, though without observing it themselves, is to reduce the
|
|
generation of elements out of one another to an illusion. They make it
|
|
a process of excretion from a body of what was in it all the time-as
|
|
though generation required a vessel rather than a material-so that
|
|
it involves no change of anything. And even if this were accepted,
|
|
there are other implications equally unsatisfactory. We do not
|
|
expect a mass of matter to be made heavier by compression. But they
|
|
will be bound to maintain this, if they say that water is a body
|
|
present in air and excreted from air, since air becomes heavier when
|
|
it turns into water. Again, when the mixed body is divided, they can
|
|
show no reason why one of the constituents must by itself take up more
|
|
room than the body did: but when water turns into air, the room
|
|
occupied is increased. The fact is that the finer body takes up more
|
|
room, as is obvious in any case of transformation. As the liquid is
|
|
converted into vapour or air the vessel which contains it is often
|
|
burst because it does not contain room enough. Now, if there is no
|
|
void at all, and if, as those who take this view say, there is no
|
|
expansion of bodies, the impossibility of this is manifest: and if
|
|
there is void and expansion, there is no accounting for the fact
|
|
that the body which results from division cfpies of necessity a
|
|
greater space. It is inevitable, too, that generation of one out of
|
|
another should come to a stop, since a finite quantum cannot contain
|
|
an infinity of finite quanta. When earth produces water something is
|
|
taken away from the earth, for the process is one of excretion. The
|
|
same thing happens again when the residue produces water. But this can
|
|
only go on for ever, if the finite body contains an infinity, which is
|
|
impossible. Therefore the generation of elements out of one another
|
|
will not always continue.
|
|
|
|
(2) We have now explained that the mutual transformations of the
|
|
elements cannot take place by means of excretion. The remaining
|
|
alternative is that they should be generated by changing into one
|
|
another. And this in one of two ways, either by change of shape, as
|
|
the same wax takes the shape both of a sphere and of a cube, or, as
|
|
some assert, by resolution into planes. (a) Generation by change of
|
|
shape would necessarily involve the assertion of atomic bodies. For if
|
|
the particles were divisible there would be a part of fire which was
|
|
not fire and a part of earth which was not earth, for the reason
|
|
that not every part of a pyramid is a pyramid nor of a cube a cube.
|
|
But if (b) the process is resolution into planes, the first difficulty
|
|
is that the elements cannot all be generated out of one another.
|
|
This they are obliged to assert, and do assert. It is absurd,
|
|
because it is unreasonable that one element alone should have no
|
|
part in the transformations, and also contrary to the observed data of
|
|
sense, according to which all alike change into one another. In fact
|
|
their explanation of the observations is not consistent with the
|
|
observations. And the reason is that their ultimate principles are
|
|
wrongly assumed: they had certain predetermined views, and were
|
|
resolved to bring everything into line with them. It seems that
|
|
perceptible things require perceptible principles, eternal things
|
|
eternal principles, corruptible things corruptible principles; and, in
|
|
general, every subject matter principles homogeneous with itself.
|
|
But they, owing to their love for their principles, fall into the
|
|
attitude of men who undertake the defence of a position in argument.
|
|
In the confidence that the principles are true they are ready to
|
|
accept any consequence of their application. As though some principles
|
|
did not require to be judged from their results, and particularly from
|
|
their final issue! And that issue, which in the case of productive
|
|
knowledge is the product, in the knowledge of nature is the
|
|
unimpeachable evidence of the senses as to each fact.
|
|
|
|
The result of their view is that earth has the best right to the
|
|
name element, and is alone indestructible; for that which is
|
|
indissoluble is indestructible and elementary, and earth alone
|
|
cannot be dissolved into any body but itself. Again, in the case of
|
|
those elements which do suffer dissolution, the 'suspension' of the
|
|
triangles is unsatisfactory. But this takes place whenever one is
|
|
dissolved into another, because of the numerical inequality of the
|
|
triangles which compose them. Further, those who hold these views must
|
|
needs suppose that generation does not start from a body. For what
|
|
is generated out of planes cannot be said to have been generated
|
|
from a body. And they must also assert that not all bodies are
|
|
divisible, coming thus into conflict with our most accurate
|
|
sciences, namely the mathematical, which assume that even the
|
|
intelligible is divisible, while they, in their anxiety to save
|
|
their hypothesis, cannot even admit this of every perceptible thing.
|
|
For any one who gives each element a shape of its own, and makes
|
|
this the ground of distinction between the substances, has to
|
|
attribute to them indivisibility; since division of a pyramid or a
|
|
sphere must leave somewhere at least a residue which is not sphere
|
|
or a pyramid. Either, then, a part of fire is not fire, so that
|
|
there is a body prior to the element-for every body is either an
|
|
element or composed of elements-or not every body is divisible.
|
|
|
|
8
|
|
|
|
In general, the attempt to give a shape to each of the simple bodies
|
|
is unsound, for the reason, first, that they will not succeed in
|
|
filling the whole. It is agreed that there are only three plane
|
|
figures which can fill a space, the triangle, the square, and the
|
|
hexagon, and only two solids, the pyramid and the cube. But the theory
|
|
needs more than these because the elements which it recognizes are
|
|
more in number. Secondly, it is manifest that the simple bodies are
|
|
often given a shape by the place in which they are included,
|
|
particularly water and air. In such a case the shape of the element
|
|
cannot persist; for, if it did, the contained mass would not be in
|
|
continuous contact with the containing body; while, if its shape is
|
|
changed, it will cease to be water, since the distinctive quality is
|
|
shape. Clearly, then, their shapes are not fixed. Indeed, nature
|
|
itself seems to offer corroboration of this theoretical conclusion.
|
|
Just as in other cases the substratum must be formless and
|
|
unshapen-for thus the 'all-receptive', as we read in the Timaeus, will
|
|
be best for modelling-so the elements should be conceived as a
|
|
material for composite things; and that is why they can put off
|
|
their qualitative distinctions and pass into one another. Further, how
|
|
can they account for the generation of flesh and bone or any other
|
|
continuous body? The elements alone cannot produce them because
|
|
their collocation cannot produce a continuum. Nor can the
|
|
composition of planes; for this produces the elements themselves,
|
|
not bodies made up of them. Any one then who insists upon an exact
|
|
statement of this kind of theory, instead of assenting after a passing
|
|
glance at it, will see that it removes generation from the world.
|
|
|
|
Further, the very properties, powers, and motions, to which they
|
|
paid particular attention in allotting shapes, show the shapes not
|
|
to be in accord with the bodies. Because fire is mobile and productive
|
|
of heat and combustion, some made it a sphere, others a pyramid. These
|
|
shapes, they thought, were the most mobile because they offer the
|
|
fewest points of contact and are the least stable of any; they were
|
|
also the most apt to produce warmth and combustion, because the one is
|
|
angular throughout while the other has the most acute angles, and
|
|
the angles, they say, produce warmth and combustion. Now, in the first
|
|
place, with regard to movement both are in error. These may be the
|
|
figures best adapted to movement; they are not, however, well
|
|
adapted to the movement of fire, which is an upward and rectilinear
|
|
movement, but rather to that form of circular movement which we call
|
|
rolling. Earth, again, they call a cube because it is stable and at
|
|
rest. But it rests only in its own place, not anywhere; from any other
|
|
it moves if nothing hinders, and fire and the other bodies do the
|
|
same. The obvious inference, therefore, is that fire and each
|
|
several element is in a foreign place a sphere or a pyramid, but in
|
|
its own a cube. Again, if the possession of angles makes a body
|
|
produce heat and combustion, every element produces heat, though one
|
|
may do so more than another. For they all possess angles, the
|
|
octahedron and dodecahedron as well as the pyramid; and Democritus
|
|
makes even the sphere a kind of angle, which cuts things because of
|
|
its mobility. The difference, then, will be one of degree: and this is
|
|
plainly false. They must also accept the inference that the
|
|
mathematical produce heat and combustion, since they too possess
|
|
angles and contain atomic spheres and pyramids, especially if there
|
|
are, as they allege, atomic figures. Anyhow if these functions
|
|
belong to some of these things and not to others, they should
|
|
explain the difference, instead of speaking in quite general terms
|
|
as they do. Again, combustion of a body produces fire, and fire is a
|
|
sphere or a pyramid. The body, then, is turned into spheres or
|
|
pyramids. Let us grant that these figures may reasonably be supposed
|
|
to cut and break up bodies as fire does; still it remains quite
|
|
inexplicable that a pyramid must needs produce pyramids or a sphere
|
|
spheres. One might as well postulate that a knife or a saw divides
|
|
things into knives or saws. It is also ridiculous to think only of
|
|
division when allotting fire its shape. Fire is generally thought of
|
|
as combining and connecting rather than as separating. For though it
|
|
separates bodies different in kind, it combines those which are the
|
|
same; and the combining is essential to it, the functions of
|
|
connecting and uniting being a mark of fire, while the separating is
|
|
incidental. For the expulsion of the foreign body is an incident in
|
|
the compacting of the homogeneous. In choosing the shape, then, they
|
|
should have thought either of both functions or preferably of the
|
|
combining function. In addition, since hot and cold are contrary
|
|
powers, it is impossible to allot any shape to the cold. For the shape
|
|
given must be the contrary of that given to the hot, but there is no
|
|
contrariety between figures. That is why they have all left the cold
|
|
out, though properly either all or none should have their
|
|
distinguishing figures. Some of them, however, do attempt to explain
|
|
this power, and they contradict themselves. A body of large particles,
|
|
they say, is cold because instead of penetrating through the
|
|
passages it crushes. Clearly, then, that which is hot is that which
|
|
penetrates these passages, or in other words that which has fine
|
|
particles. It results that hot and cold are distinguished not by the
|
|
figure but by the size of the particles. Again, if the pyramids are
|
|
unequal in size, the large ones will not be fire, and that figure will
|
|
produce not combustion but its contrary.
|
|
|
|
From what has been said it is clear that the difference of the
|
|
elements does not depend upon their shape. Now their most important
|
|
differences are those of property, function, and power; for every
|
|
natural body has, we maintain, its own functions, properties, and
|
|
powers. Our first business, then, will be to speak of these, and
|
|
that inquiry will enable us to explain the differences of each from
|
|
each.
|
|
|
|
Book IV
|
|
|
|
1
|
|
|
|
WE have now to consider the terms 'heavy' and 'light'. We must ask
|
|
what the bodies so called are, how they are constituted, and what is
|
|
the reason of their possessing these powers. The consideration of
|
|
these questions is a proper part of the theory of movement, since we
|
|
call things heavy and light because they have the power of being moved
|
|
naturally in a certain way. The activities corresponding to these
|
|
powers have not been given any name, unless it is thought that
|
|
'impetus' is such a name. But because the inquiry into nature is
|
|
concerned with movement, and these things have in themselves some
|
|
spark (as it were) of movement, all inquirers avail themselves of
|
|
these powers, though in all but a few cases without exact
|
|
discrimination. We must then first look at whatever others have
|
|
said, and formulate the questions which require settlement in the
|
|
interests of this inquiry, before we go on to state our own view of
|
|
the matter.
|
|
|
|
Language recognizes (a) an absolute, (b) a relative heavy and light.
|
|
Of two heavy things, such as wood and bronze, we say that the one is
|
|
relatively light, the other relatively heavy. Our predecessors have
|
|
not dealt at all with the absolute use, of the terms, but only with
|
|
the relative. I mean, they do not explain what the heavy is or what
|
|
the light is, but only the relative heaviness and lightness of
|
|
things possessing weight. This can be made clearer as follows. There
|
|
are things whose constant nature it is to move away from the centre,
|
|
while others move constantly towards the centre; and of these
|
|
movements that which is away from the centre I call upward movement
|
|
and that which is towards it I call downward movement. (The view,
|
|
urged by some, that there is no up and no down in the heaven, is
|
|
absurd. There can be, they say, no up and no down, since the
|
|
universe is similar every way, and from any point on the earth's
|
|
surface a man by advancing far enough will come to stand foot to
|
|
foot with himself. But the extremity of the whole, which we call
|
|
'above', is in position above and in nature primary. And since the
|
|
universe has an extremity and a centre, it must clearly have an up and
|
|
down. Common usage is thus correct, though inadequate. And the
|
|
reason of its inadequacy is that men think that the universe is not
|
|
similar every way. They recognize only the hemisphere which is over
|
|
us. But if they went on to think of the world as formed on this
|
|
pattern all round, with a centre identically related to each point
|
|
on the extremity, they would have to admit that the extremity was
|
|
above and the centre below.) By absolutely light, then, we mean that
|
|
which moves upward or to the extremity, and by absolutely heavy that
|
|
which moves downward or to the centre. By lighter or relatively
|
|
light we mean that one, of two bodies endowed with weight and equal in
|
|
bulk, which is exceeded by the other in the speed of its natural
|
|
downward movement.
|
|
|
|
2
|
|
|
|
Those of our predecessors who have entered upon this inquiry have
|
|
for the most part spoken of light and heavy things only in the sense
|
|
in which one of two things both endowed with weight is said to be
|
|
the lighter. And this treatment they consider a sufficient analysis
|
|
also of the notions of absolute heaviness, to which their account does
|
|
not apply. This, however, will become clearer as we advance. One use
|
|
of the terms 'lighter' and 'heavier' is that which is set forth in
|
|
writing in the Timaeus, that the body which is composed of the greater
|
|
number of identical parts is relatively heavy, while that which is
|
|
composed of a smaller number is relatively light. As a larger quantity
|
|
of lead or of bronze is heavier than a smaller-and this holds good
|
|
of all homogeneous masses, the superior weight always depending upon a
|
|
numerical superiority of equal parts-in precisely the same way, they
|
|
assert, lead is heavier than wood. For all bodies, in spite of the
|
|
general opinion to the contrary, are composed of identical parts and
|
|
of a single material. But this analysis says nothing of the absolutely
|
|
heavy and light. The facts are that fire is always light and moves
|
|
upward, while earth and all earthy things move downwards or towards
|
|
the centre. It cannot then be the fewness of the triangles (of
|
|
which, in their view, all these bodies are composed) which disposes
|
|
fire to move upward. If it were, the greater the quantity of fire
|
|
the slower it would move, owing to the increase of weight due to the
|
|
increased number of triangles. But the palpable fact, on the contrary,
|
|
is that the greater the quantity, the lighter the mass is and the
|
|
quicker its upward movement: and, similarly, in the reverse movement
|
|
from above downward, the small mass will move quicker and the large
|
|
slower. Further, since to be lighter is to have fewer of these
|
|
homogeneous parts and to be heavier is to have more, and air, water,
|
|
and fire are composed of the same triangles, the only difference being
|
|
in the number of such parts, which must therefore explain any
|
|
distinction of relatively light and heavy between these bodies, it
|
|
follows that there must be a certain quantum of air which is heavier
|
|
than water. But the facts are directly opposed to this. The larger the
|
|
quantity of air the more readily it moves upward, and any portion of
|
|
air without exception will rise up out of the water.
|
|
|
|
So much for one view of the distinction between light and heavy.
|
|
To others the analysis seems insufficient; and their views on the
|
|
subject, though they belong to an older generation than ours, have
|
|
an air of novelty. It is apparent that there are bodies which, when
|
|
smaller in bulk than others, yet exceed them in weight. It is
|
|
therefore obviously insufficient to say that bodies of equal weight
|
|
are composed of an equal number of primary parts: for that would
|
|
give equality of bulk. Those who maintain that the primary or atomic
|
|
parts, of which bodies endowed with weight are composed, are planes,
|
|
cannot so speak without absurdity; but those who regard them as solids
|
|
are in a better position to assert that of such bodies the larger is
|
|
the heavier. But since in composite bodies the weight obviously does
|
|
not correspond in this way to the bulk, the lesser bulk being often
|
|
superior in weight (as, for instance, if one be wool and the other
|
|
bronze), there are some who think and say that the cause is to be
|
|
found elsewhere. The void, they say, which is imprisoned in bodies,
|
|
lightens them and sometimes makes the larger body the lighter. The
|
|
reason is that there is more void. And this would also account for the
|
|
fact that a body composed of a number of solid parts equal to, or even
|
|
smaller than, that of another is sometimes larger in bulk than it.
|
|
In short, generally and in every case a body is relatively light
|
|
when it contains a relatively large amount of void. This is the way
|
|
they put it themselves, but their account requires an addition.
|
|
Relative lightness must depend not only on an excess of void, but also
|
|
an a defect of solid: for if the ratio of solid to void exceeds a
|
|
certain proportion, the relative lightness will disappear. Thus
|
|
fire, they say, is the lightest of things just for this reason that it
|
|
has the most void. But it would follow that a large mass of gold, as
|
|
containing more void than a small mass of fire, is lighter than it,
|
|
unless it also contains many times as much solid. The addition is
|
|
therefore necessary.
|
|
|
|
Of those who deny the existence of a void some, like Anaxagoras
|
|
and Empedocles, have not tried to analyse the notions of light and
|
|
heavy at all; and those who, while still denying the existence of a
|
|
void, have attempted this, have failed to explain why there are bodies
|
|
which are absolutely heavy and light, or in other words why some
|
|
move upward and others downward. The fact, again, that the body of
|
|
greater bulk is sometimes lighter than smaller bodies is one which
|
|
they have passed over in silence, and what they have said gives no
|
|
obvious suggestion for reconciling their views with the observed
|
|
facts.
|
|
|
|
But those who attribute the lightness of fire to its containing so
|
|
much void are necessarily involved in practically the same
|
|
difficulties. For though fire be supposed to contain less solid than
|
|
any other body, as well as more void, yet there will be a certain
|
|
quantum of fire in which the amount of solid or plenum is in excess of
|
|
the solids contained in some small quantity of earth. They may reply
|
|
that there is an excess of void also. But the question is, how will
|
|
they discriminate the absolutely heavy? Presumably, either by its
|
|
excess of solid or by its defect of void. On the former view there
|
|
could be an amount of earth so small as to contain less solid than a
|
|
large mass of fire. And similarly, if the distinction rests on the
|
|
amount of void, there will be a body, lighter than the absolutely
|
|
light, which nevertheless moves downward as constantly as the other
|
|
moves upward. But that cannot be so, since the absolutely light is
|
|
always lighter than bodies which have weight and move downward, while,
|
|
on the other hand, that which is lighter need not be light, because in
|
|
common speech we distinguish a lighter and a heavier (viz. water and
|
|
earth) among bodies endowed with weight. Again, the suggestion of a
|
|
certain ratio between the void and the solid in a body is no more
|
|
equal to solving the problem before us. The manner of speaking will
|
|
issue in a similar impossibility. For any two portions of fire,
|
|
small or great, will exhibit the same ratio of solid to void, but
|
|
the upward movement of the greater is quicker than that of the less,
|
|
just as the downward movement of a mass of gold or lead, or of any
|
|
other body endowed with weight, is quicker in proportion to its
|
|
size. This, however, should not be the case if the ratio is the ground
|
|
of distinction between heavy things and light. There is also an
|
|
absurdity in attributing the upward movement of bodies to a void which
|
|
does not itself move. If, however, it is the nature of a void to
|
|
move upward and of a plenum to move downward, and therefore each
|
|
causes a like movement in other things, there was no need to raise the
|
|
question why composite bodies are some light and some heavy; they
|
|
had only to explain why these two things are themselves light and
|
|
heavy respectively, and to give, further, the reason why the plenum
|
|
and the void are not eternally separated. It is also unreasonable to
|
|
imagine a place for the void, as if the void were not itself a kind of
|
|
place. But if the void is to move, it must have a place out of which
|
|
and into which the change carries it. Also what is the cause of its
|
|
movement? Not, surely, its voidness: for it is not the void only which
|
|
is moved, but also the solid.
|
|
|
|
Similar difficulties are involved in all other methods of
|
|
distinction, whether they account for the relative lightness and
|
|
heaviness of bodies by distinctions of size, or proceed on any other
|
|
principle, so long as they attribute to each the same matter, or
|
|
even if they recognize more than one matter, so long as that means
|
|
only a pair of contraries. If there is a single matter, as with
|
|
those who compose things of triangles, nothing can be absolutely heavy
|
|
or light: and if there is one matter and its contrary-the void, for
|
|
instance, and the plenum-no reason can be given for the relative
|
|
lightness and heaviness of the bodies intermediate between the
|
|
absolutely light and heavy when compared either with one another or
|
|
with these themselves. The view which bases the distinction upon
|
|
differences of size is more like a mere fiction than those
|
|
previously mentioned, but, in that it is able to make distinctions
|
|
between the four elements, it is in a stronger position for meeting
|
|
the foregoing difficulties. Since, however, it imagines that these
|
|
bodies which differ in size are all made of one substance, it implies,
|
|
equally with the view that there is but one matter, that there is
|
|
nothing absolutely light and nothing which moves upward (except as
|
|
being passed by other things or forced up by them); and since a
|
|
multitude of small atoms are heavier than a few large ones, it will
|
|
follow that much air or fire is heavier than a little water or
|
|
earth, which is impossible.
|
|
|
|
3
|
|
|
|
These, then, are the views which have been advanced by others and
|
|
the terms in which they state them. We may begin our own statement
|
|
by settling a question which to some has been the main
|
|
difficulty-the question why some bodies move always and naturally
|
|
upward and others downward, while others again move both upward and
|
|
downward. After that we will inquire into light and heavy and of the
|
|
various phenomena connected with them. The local movement of each body
|
|
into its own place must be regarded as similar to what happens in
|
|
connexion with other forms of generation and change. There are, in
|
|
fact, three kinds of movement, affecting respectively the size, the
|
|
form, and the place of a thing, and in each it is observable that
|
|
change proceeds from a contrary to a contrary or to something
|
|
intermediate: it is never the change of any chance subject in any
|
|
chance direction, nor, similarly, is the relation of the mover to
|
|
its object fortuitous: the thing altered is different from the thing
|
|
increased, and precisely the same difference holds between that
|
|
which produces alteration and that which produces increase. In the
|
|
same manner it must be thought that produces local motion and that
|
|
which is so moved are not fortuitously related. Now, that which
|
|
produces upward and downward movement is that which produces weight
|
|
and lightness, and that which is moved is that which is potentially
|
|
heavy or light, and the movement of each body to its own place is
|
|
motion towards its own form. (It is best to interpret in this sense
|
|
the common statement of the older writers that 'like moves to like'.
|
|
For the words are not in every sense true to fact. If one were to
|
|
remove the earth to where the moon now is, the various fragments of
|
|
earth would each move not towards it but to the place in which it
|
|
now is. In general, when a number of similar and undifferentiated
|
|
bodies are moved with the same motion this result is necessarily
|
|
produced, viz. that the place which is the natural goal of the
|
|
movement of each single part is also that of the whole. But since
|
|
the place of a thing is the boundary of that which contains it, and
|
|
the continent of all things that move upward or downward is the
|
|
extremity and the centre, and this boundary comes to be, in a sense,
|
|
the form of that which is contained, it is to its like that a body
|
|
moves when it moves to its own place. For the successive members of
|
|
the scries are like one another: water, I mean, is like air and air
|
|
like fire, and between intermediates the relation may be converted,
|
|
though not between them and the extremes; thus air is like water,
|
|
but water is like earth: for the relation of each outer body to that
|
|
which is next within it is that of form to matter.) Thus to ask why
|
|
fire moves upward and earth downward is the same as to ask why the
|
|
healable, when moved and changed qua healable, attains health and
|
|
not whiteness; and similar questions might be asked concerning any
|
|
other subject of aletion. Of course the subject of increase, when
|
|
changed qua increasable, attains not health but a superior size. The
|
|
same applies in the other cases. One thing changes in quality, another
|
|
in quantity: and so in place, a light thing goes upward, a heavy thing
|
|
downward. The only difference is that in the last case, viz. that of
|
|
the heavy and the light, the bodies are thought to have a spring of
|
|
change within themselves, while the subjects of healing and increase
|
|
are thought to be moved purely from without. Sometimes, however,
|
|
even they change of themselves, ie. in response to a slight external
|
|
movement reach health or increase, as the case may be. And since the
|
|
same thing which is healable is also receptive of disease, it
|
|
depends on whether it is moved qua healable or qua liable to disease
|
|
whether the motion is towards health or towards disease. But the
|
|
reason why the heavy and the light appear more than these things to
|
|
contain within themselves the source of their movements is that
|
|
their matter is nearest to being. This is indicated by the fact that
|
|
locomotion belongs to bodies only when isolated from other bodies, and
|
|
is generated last of the several kinds of movement; in order of
|
|
being then it will be first. Now whenever air comes into being out
|
|
of water, light out of heavy, it goes to the upper place. It is
|
|
forthwith light: becoming is at an end, and in that place it has
|
|
being. Obviously, then, it is a potentiality, which, in its passage to
|
|
actuality, comes into that place and quantity and quality which belong
|
|
to its actuality. And the same fact explains why what is already
|
|
actually fire or earth moves, when nothing obstructs it, towards its
|
|
own place. For motion is equally immediate in the case of nutriment,
|
|
when nothing hinders, and in the case of the thing healed, when
|
|
nothing stays the healing. But the movement is also due to the
|
|
original creative force and to that which removes the hindrance or off
|
|
which the moving thing rebounded, as was explained in our opening
|
|
discussions, where we tried to show how none of these things moves
|
|
itself. The reason of the various motions of the various bodies, and
|
|
the meaning of the motion of a body to its own place, have now been
|
|
explained.
|
|
|
|
4
|
|
|
|
We have now to speak of the distinctive properties of these bodies
|
|
and of the various phenomena connected with them. In accordance with
|
|
general conviction we may distinguish the absolutely heavy, as that
|
|
which sinks to the bottom of all things, from the absolutely light,
|
|
which is that which rises to the surface of all things. I use the term
|
|
'absolutely', in view of the generic character of 'light' and 'heavy',
|
|
in order to confine the application to bodies which do not combine
|
|
lightness and heaviness. It is apparent, I mean, that fire, in
|
|
whatever quantity, so long as there is no external obstacle moves
|
|
upward, and earth downward; and, if the quantity is increased, the
|
|
movement is the same, though swifter. But the heaviness and
|
|
lightness of bodies which combine these qualities is different from
|
|
this, since while they rise to the surface of some bodies they sink to
|
|
the bottom of others. Such are air and water. Neither of them is
|
|
absolutely either light or heavy. Both are lighter than earth-for
|
|
any portion of either rises to the surface of it-but heavier than
|
|
fire, since a portion of either, whatever its quantity, sinks to the
|
|
bottom of fire; compared together, however, the one has absolute
|
|
weight, the other absolute lightness, since air in any quantity
|
|
rises to the surface of water, while water in any quantity sinks to
|
|
the bottom of air. Now other bodies are severally light and heavy, and
|
|
evidently in them the attributes are due to the difference of their
|
|
uncompounded parts: that is to say, according as the one or the
|
|
other happens to preponderate the bodies will be heavy and light
|
|
respectively. Therefore we need only speak of these parts, since
|
|
they are primary and all else consequential: and in so doing we
|
|
shall be following the advice which we gave to those whose attribute
|
|
heaviness to the presence of plenum and lightness to that of void.
|
|
It is due to the properties of the elementary bodies that a body which
|
|
is regarded as light in one place is regarded as heavy in another, and
|
|
vice versa. In air, for instance, a talent's weight of wood is heavier
|
|
than a mina of lead, but in water the wood is the lighter. The
|
|
reason is that all the elements except fire have weight and all but
|
|
earth lightness. Earth, then, and bodies in which earth preponderates,
|
|
must needs have weight everywhere, while water is heavy anywhere but
|
|
in earth, and air is heavy when not in water or earth. In its own
|
|
place each of these bodies has weight except fire, even air. Of this
|
|
we have evidence in the fact that a bladder when inflated weighs
|
|
more than when empty. A body, then, in which air preponderates over
|
|
earth and water, may well be lighter than something in water and yet
|
|
heavier than it in air, since such a body does not rise in air but
|
|
rises to the surface in water.
|
|
|
|
The following account will make it plain that there is an absolutely
|
|
light and an absolutely heavy body. And by absolutely light I mean one
|
|
which of its own nature always moves upward, by absolutely heavy one
|
|
which of its own nature always moves downward, if no obstacle is in
|
|
the way. There are, I say, these two kinds of body, and it is not
|
|
the case, as some maintain, that all bodies have weight. Different
|
|
views are in fact agreed that there is a heavy body, which moves
|
|
uniformly towards the centre. But is also similarly a light body.
|
|
For we see with our eyes, as we said before, that earthy things sink
|
|
to the bottom of all things and move towards the centre. But the
|
|
centre is a fixed point. If therefore there is some body which rises
|
|
to the surface of all things-and we observe fire to move upward even
|
|
in air itself, while the air remains at rest-clearly this body is
|
|
moving towards the extremity. It cannot then have any weight. If it
|
|
had, there would be another body in which it sank: and if that had
|
|
weight, there would be yet another which moved to the extremity and
|
|
thus rose to the surface of all moving things. In fact, however, we
|
|
have no evidence of such a body. Fire, then, has no weight. Neither
|
|
has earth any lightness, since it sinks to the bottom of all things,
|
|
and that which sinks moves to the centre. That there is a centre
|
|
towards which the motion of heavy things, and away from which that
|
|
of light things is directed, is manifest in many ways. First,
|
|
because no movement can continue to infinity. For what cannot be can
|
|
no more come-to-be than be, and movement is a coming to-be in one
|
|
place from another. Secondly, like the upward movement of fire, the
|
|
downward movement of earth and all heavy things makes equal angles
|
|
on every side with the earth's surface: it must therefore be
|
|
directed towards the centre. Whether it is really the centre of the
|
|
earth and not rather that of the whole to which it moves, may be
|
|
left to another inquiry, since these are coincident. But since that
|
|
which sinks to the bottom of all things moves to the centre,
|
|
necessarily that which rises to the surface moves to the extremity
|
|
of the region in which the movement of these bodies takes place. For
|
|
the centre is opposed as contrary to the extremity, as that which
|
|
sinks is opposed to that which rises to the surface. This also gives a
|
|
reasonable ground for the duality of heavy and light in the spatial
|
|
duality centre and extremity. Now there is also the intermediate
|
|
region to which each name is given in opposition to the other extreme.
|
|
For that which is intermediate between the two is in a sense both
|
|
extremity and centre. For this reason there is another heavy and
|
|
light; namely, water and air. But in our view the continent pertains
|
|
to form and the contained to matter: and this distinction is present
|
|
in every genus. Alike in the sphere of quality and in that of quantity
|
|
there is that which corresponds rather to form and that which
|
|
corresponds to matter. In the same way, among spatial distinctions,
|
|
the above belongs to the determinate, the below to matter. The same
|
|
holds, consequently, also of the matter itself of that which is
|
|
heavy and light: as potentially possessing the one character, it is
|
|
matter for the heavy, and as potentially possessing the other, for the
|
|
light. It is the same matter, but its being is different, as that
|
|
which is receptive of disease is the same as that which is receptive
|
|
of health, though in being different from it, and therefore
|
|
diseasedness is different from healthiness.
|
|
|
|
5
|
|
|
|
A thing then which has the one kind of matter is light and always
|
|
moves upward, while a thing which has the opposite matter is heavy and
|
|
always moves downward. Bodies composed of kinds of matter different
|
|
from these but having relatively to each other the character which
|
|
these have absolutely, possess both the upward and the downward
|
|
motion. Hence air and water each have both lightness and weight, and
|
|
water sinks to the bottom of all things except earth, while air
|
|
rises to the surface of all things except fire. But since there is one
|
|
body only which rises to the surface of all things and one only
|
|
which sinks to the bottom of all things, there must needs be two other
|
|
bodies which sink in some bodies and rise to the surface of others.
|
|
The kinds of matter, then, must be as numerous as these bodies, i.e.
|
|
four, but though they are four there must be a common matter of
|
|
all-particularly if they pass into one another-which in each is in
|
|
being different. There is no reason why there should not be one or
|
|
more intermediates between the contraries, as in the case of colour;
|
|
for 'intermediate' and 'mean' are capable of more than one
|
|
application.
|
|
|
|
Now in its own place every body endowed with both weight and
|
|
lightness has weightwhereas earth has weight everywhere-but they
|
|
only have lightness among bodies to whose surface they rise. Hence
|
|
when a support is withdrawn such a body moves downward until it
|
|
reaches the body next below it, air to the place of water and water to
|
|
that of earth. But if the fire above air is removed, it will not
|
|
move upward to the place of fire, except by constraint; and in that
|
|
way water also may be drawn up, when the upward movement of air
|
|
which has had a common surface with it is swift enough to overpower
|
|
the downward impulse of the water. Nor does water move upward to the
|
|
place of air, except in the manner just described. Earth is not so
|
|
affected at all, because a common surface is not possible to it. Hence
|
|
water is drawn up into the vessel to which fire is applied, but not
|
|
earth. As earth fails to move upward, so fire fails to move downward
|
|
when air is withdrawn from beneath it: for fire has no weight even
|
|
in its own place, as earth has no lightness. The other two move
|
|
downward when the body beneath is withdrawn because, while the
|
|
absolutely heavy is that which sinks to the bottom of all things,
|
|
the relatively heavy sinks to its own place or to the surface of the
|
|
body in which it rises, since it is similar in matter to it.
|
|
|
|
It is plain that one must suppose as many distinct species of matter
|
|
as there are bodies. For if, first, there is a single matter of all
|
|
things, as, for instance, the void or the plenum or extension or the
|
|
triangles, either all things will move upward or all things will
|
|
move downward, and the second motion will be abolished. And so, either
|
|
there will be no absolutely light body, if superiority of weight is
|
|
due to superior size or number of the constituent bodies or to the
|
|
fullness of the body: but the contrary is a matter of observation, and
|
|
it has been shown that the downward and upward movements are equally
|
|
constant and universal: or, if the matter in question is the void or
|
|
something similar, which moves uniformly upward, there will be nothing
|
|
to move uniformly downward. Further, it will follow that the
|
|
intermediate bodies move downward in some cases quicker than earth:
|
|
for air in sufficiently large quantity will contain a larger number of
|
|
triangles or solids or particles. It is, however, manifest that no
|
|
portion of air whatever moves downward. And the same reasoning applies
|
|
to lightness, if that is supposed to depend on superiority of quantity
|
|
of matter. But if, secondly, the kinds of matter are two, it will be
|
|
difficult to make the intermediate bodies behave as air and water
|
|
behave. Suppose, for example, that the two asserted are void and
|
|
plenum. Fire, then, as moving upward, will be void, earth, as moving
|
|
downward, plenum; and in air, it will be said, fire preponderates,
|
|
in water, earth. There will then be a quantity of water containing
|
|
more fire than a little air, and a large amount of air will contain
|
|
more earth than a little water: consequently we shall have to say that
|
|
air in a certain quantity moves downward more quickly than a little
|
|
water. But such a thing has never been observed anywhere. Necessarily,
|
|
then, as fire goes up because it has something, e.g. void, which other
|
|
things do not have, and earth goes downward because it has plenum,
|
|
so air goes to its own place above water because it has something
|
|
else, and water goes downward because of some special kind of body.
|
|
But if the two bodies are one matter, or two matters both present in
|
|
each, there will be a certain quantity of each at which water will
|
|
excel a little air in the upward movement and air excel water in the
|
|
downward movement, as we have already often said.
|
|
|
|
6
|
|
|
|
The shape of bodies will not account for their moving upward or
|
|
downward in general, though it will account for their moving faster or
|
|
slower. The reasons for this are not difficult to see. For the problem
|
|
thus raised is why a flat piece of iron or lead floats upon water,
|
|
while smaller and less heavy things, so long as they are round or
|
|
long-a needle, for instance-sink down; and sometimes a thing floats
|
|
because it is small, as with gold dust and the various earthy and
|
|
dusty materials which throng the air. With regard to these
|
|
questions, it is wrong to accept the explanation offered by
|
|
Democritus. He says that the warm bodies moving up out of the water
|
|
hold up heavy bodies which are broad, while the narrow ones fall
|
|
through, because the bodies which offer this resistance are not
|
|
numerous. But this would be even more likely to happen in air-an
|
|
objection which he himself raises. His reply to the objection is
|
|
feeble. In the air, he says, the 'drive' (meaning by drive the
|
|
movement of the upward moving bodies) is not uniform in direction. But
|
|
since some continua are easily divided and others less easily, and
|
|
things which produce division differ similarly in the case with
|
|
which they produce it, the explanation must be found in this fact.
|
|
It is the easily bounded, in proportion as it is easily bounded, which
|
|
is easily divided; and air is more so than water, water than earth.
|
|
Further, the smaller the quantity in each kind, the more easily it
|
|
is divided and disrupted. Thus the reason why broad things keep
|
|
their place is because they cover so wide a surface and the greater
|
|
quantity is less easily disrupted. Bodies of the opposite shape sink
|
|
down because they occupy so little of the surface, which is
|
|
therefore easily parted. And these considerations apply with far
|
|
greater force to air, since it is so much more easily divided than
|
|
water. But since there are two factors, the force responsible for
|
|
the downward motion of the heavy body and the disruption-resisting
|
|
force of the continuous surface, there must be some ratio between
|
|
the two. For in proportion as the force applied by the heavy thing
|
|
towards disruption and division exceeds that which resides in the
|
|
continuum, the quicker will it force its way down; only if the force
|
|
of the heavy thing is the weaker, will it ride upon the surface.
|
|
|
|
We have now finished our examination of the heavy and the light
|
|
and of the phenomena connected with them.
|
|
|
|
THE END
|
|
.
|