mirror of
https://github.com/opsxcq/mirror-textfiles.com.git
synced 2025-09-01 00:51:52 +02:00
3101 lines
177 KiB
Plaintext
3101 lines
177 KiB
Plaintext
350 BC
|
|
|
|
ON THE SOUL
|
|
|
|
by Aristotle
|
|
|
|
translated by J. A. Smith
|
|
|
|
Book I
|
|
|
|
1
|
|
|
|
HOLDING as we do that, while knowledge of any kind is a thing to
|
|
be honoured and prized, one kind of it may, either by reason of its
|
|
greater exactness or of a higher dignity and greater wonderfulness
|
|
in its objects, be more honourable and precious than another, on
|
|
both accounts we should naturally be led to place in the front rank
|
|
the study of the soul. The knowledge of the soul admittedly
|
|
contributes greatly to the advance of truth in general, and, above
|
|
all, to our understanding of Nature, for the soul is in some sense the
|
|
principle of animal life. Our aim is to grasp and understand, first
|
|
its essential nature, and secondly its properties; of these some are
|
|
taught to be affections proper to the soul itself, while others are
|
|
considered to attach to the animal owing to the presence within it
|
|
of soul.
|
|
|
|
To attain any assured knowledge about the soul is one of the most
|
|
difficult things in the world. As the form of question which here
|
|
presents itself, viz. the question 'What is it?', recurs in other
|
|
fields, it might be supposed that there was some single method of
|
|
inquiry applicable to all objects whose essential nature (as we are
|
|
endeavouring to ascertain there is for derived properties the single
|
|
method of demonstration); in that case what we should have to seek for
|
|
would be this unique method. But if there is no such single and
|
|
general method for solving the question of essence, our task becomes
|
|
still more difficult; in the case of each different subject we shall
|
|
have to determine the appropriate process of investigation. If to this
|
|
there be a clear answer, e.g. that the process is demonstration or
|
|
division, or some known method, difficulties and hesitations still
|
|
beset us-with what facts shall we begin the inquiry? For the facts
|
|
which form the starting-points in different subjects must be
|
|
different, as e.g. in the case of numbers and surfaces.
|
|
|
|
First, no doubt, it is necessary to determine in which of the
|
|
summa genera soul lies, what it is; is it 'a this-somewhat, 'a
|
|
substance, or is it a quale or a quantum, or some other of the
|
|
remaining kinds of predicates which we have distinguished? Further,
|
|
does soul belong to the class of potential existents, or is it not
|
|
rather an actuality? Our answer to this question is of the greatest
|
|
importance.
|
|
|
|
We must consider also whether soul is divisible or is without parts,
|
|
and whether it is everywhere homogeneous or not; and if not
|
|
homogeneous, whether its various forms are different specifically or
|
|
generically: up to the present time those who have discussed and
|
|
investigated soul seem to have confined themselves to the human
|
|
soul. We must be careful not to ignore the question whether soul can
|
|
be defined in a single unambiguous formula, as is the case with
|
|
animal, or whether we must not give a separate formula for each of it,
|
|
as we do for horse, dog, man, god (in the latter case the
|
|
'universal' animal-and so too every other 'common predicate'-being
|
|
treated either as nothing at all or as a later product). Further, if
|
|
what exists is not a plurality of souls, but a plurality of parts of
|
|
one soul, which ought we to investigate first, the whole soul or its
|
|
parts? (It is also a difficult problem to decide which of these
|
|
parts are in nature distinct from one another.) Again, which ought
|
|
we to investigate first, these parts or their functions, mind or
|
|
thinking, the faculty or the act of sensation, and so on? If the
|
|
investigation of the functions precedes that of the parts, the further
|
|
question suggests itself: ought we not before either to consider the
|
|
correlative objects, e.g. of sense or thought? It seems not only
|
|
useful for the discovery of the causes of the derived properties of
|
|
substances to be acquainted with the essential nature of those
|
|
substances (as in mathematics it is useful for the understanding of
|
|
the property of the equality of the interior angles of a triangle to
|
|
two right angles to know the essential nature of the straight and
|
|
the curved or of the line and the plane) but also conversely, for
|
|
the knowledge of the essential nature of a substance is largely
|
|
promoted by an acquaintance with its properties: for, when we are able
|
|
to give an account conformable to experience of all or most of the
|
|
properties of a substance, we shall be in the most favourable position
|
|
to say something worth saying about the essential nature of that
|
|
subject; in all demonstration a definition of the essence is
|
|
required as a starting-point, so that definitions which do not
|
|
enable us to discover the derived properties, or which fail to
|
|
facilitate even a conjecture about them, must obviously, one and
|
|
all, be dialectical and futile.
|
|
|
|
A further problem presented by the affections of soul is this: are
|
|
they all affections of the complex of body and soul, or is there any
|
|
one among them peculiar to the soul by itself? To determine this is
|
|
indispensable but difficult. If we consider the majority of them,
|
|
there seems to be no case in which the soul can act or be acted upon
|
|
without involving the body; e.g. anger, courage, appetite, and
|
|
sensation generally. Thinking seems the most probable exception; but
|
|
if this too proves to be a form of imagination or to be impossible
|
|
without imagination, it too requires a body as a condition of its
|
|
existence. If there is any way of acting or being acted upon proper to
|
|
soul, soul will be capable of separate existence; if there is none,
|
|
its separate existence is impossible. In the latter case, it will be
|
|
like what is straight, which has many properties arising from the
|
|
straightness in it, e.g. that of touching a bronze sphere at a
|
|
point, though straightness divorced from the other constituents of the
|
|
straight thing cannot touch it in this way; it cannot be so divorced
|
|
at all, since it is always found in a body. It therefore seems that
|
|
all the affections of soul involve a body-passion, gentleness, fear,
|
|
pity, courage, joy, loving, and hating; in all these there is a
|
|
concurrent affection of the body. In support of this we may point to
|
|
the fact that, while sometimes on the occasion of violent and striking
|
|
occurrences there is no excitement or fear felt, on others faint and
|
|
feeble stimulations produce these emotions, viz. when the body is
|
|
already in a state of tension resembling its condition when we are
|
|
angry. Here is a still clearer case: in the absence of any external
|
|
cause of terror we find ourselves experiencing the feelings of a man
|
|
in terror. From all this it is obvious that the affections of soul are
|
|
enmattered formulable essences.
|
|
|
|
Consequently their definitions ought to correspond, e.g. anger
|
|
should be defined as a certain mode of movement of such and such a
|
|
body (or part or faculty of a body) by this or that cause and for this
|
|
or that end. That is precisely why the study of the soul must fall
|
|
within the science of Nature, at least so far as in its affections
|
|
it manifests this double character. Hence a physicist would define
|
|
an affection of soul differently from a dialectician; the latter would
|
|
define e.g. anger as the appetite for returning pain for pain, or
|
|
something like that, while the former would define it as a boiling
|
|
of the blood or warm substance surround the heart. The latter
|
|
assigns the material conditions, the former the form or formulable
|
|
essence; for what he states is the formulable essence of the fact,
|
|
though for its actual existence there must be embodiment of it in a
|
|
material such as is described by the other. Thus the essence of a
|
|
house is assigned in such a formula as 'a shelter against
|
|
destruction by wind, rain, and heat'; the physicist would describe
|
|
it as 'stones, bricks, and timbers'; but there is a third possible
|
|
description which would say that it was that form in that material
|
|
with that purpose or end. Which, then, among these is entitled to be
|
|
regarded as the genuine physicist? The one who confines himself to the
|
|
material, or the one who restricts himself to the formulable essence
|
|
alone? Is it not rather the one who combines both in a single formula?
|
|
If this is so, how are we to characterize the other two? Must we not
|
|
say that there is no type of thinker who concerns himself with those
|
|
qualities or attributes of the material which are in fact
|
|
inseparable from the material, and without attempting even in
|
|
thought to separate them? The physicist is he who concerns himself
|
|
with all the properties active and passive of bodies or materials thus
|
|
or thus defined; attributes not considered as being of this
|
|
character he leaves to others, in certain cases it may be to a
|
|
specialist, e.g. a carpenter or a physician, in others (a) where
|
|
they are inseparable in fact, but are separable from any particular
|
|
kind of body by an effort of abstraction, to the mathematician, (b)
|
|
where they are separate both in fact and in thought from body
|
|
altogether, to the First Philosopher or metaphysician. But we must
|
|
return from this digression, and repeat that the affections of soul
|
|
are inseparable from the material substratum of animal life, to
|
|
which we have seen that such affections, e.g. passion and fear,
|
|
attach, and have not the same mode of being as a line or a plane.
|
|
|
|
2
|
|
|
|
For our study of soul it is necessary, while formulating the
|
|
problems of which in our further advance we are to find the solutions,
|
|
to call into council the views of those of our predecessors who have
|
|
declared any opinion on this subject, in order that we may profit by
|
|
whatever is sound in their suggestions and avoid their errors.
|
|
|
|
The starting-point of our inquiry is an exposition of those
|
|
characteristics which have chiefly been held to belong to soul in
|
|
its very nature. Two characteristic marks have above all others been
|
|
recognized as distinguishing that which has soul in it from that which
|
|
has not-movement and sensation. It may be said that these two are what
|
|
our predecessors have fixed upon as characteristic of soul.
|
|
|
|
Some say that what originates movement is both pre-eminently and
|
|
primarily soul; believing that what is not itself moved cannot
|
|
originate movement in another, they arrived at the view that soul
|
|
belongs to the class of things in movement. This is what led
|
|
Democritus to say that soul is a sort of fire or hot substance; his
|
|
'forms' or atoms are infinite in number; those which are spherical
|
|
he calls fire and soul, and compares them to the motes in the air
|
|
which we see in shafts of light coming through windows; the mixture of
|
|
seeds of all sorts he calls the elements of the whole of Nature
|
|
(Leucippus gives a similar account); the spherical atoms are
|
|
identified with soul because atoms of that shape are most adapted to
|
|
permeate everywhere, and to set all the others moving by being
|
|
themselves in movement. This implies the view that soul is identical
|
|
with what produces movement in animals. That is why, further, they
|
|
regard respiration as the characteristic mark of life; as the
|
|
environment compresses the bodies of animals, and tends to extrude
|
|
those atoms which impart movement to them, because they themselves are
|
|
never at rest, there must be a reinforcement of these by similar atoms
|
|
coming in from without in the act of respiration; for they prevent the
|
|
extrusion of those which are already within by counteracting the
|
|
compressing and consolidating force of the environment; and animals
|
|
continue to live only so long as they are able to maintain this
|
|
resistance.
|
|
|
|
The doctrine of the Pythagoreans seems to rest upon the same
|
|
ideas; some of them declared the motes in air, others what moved them,
|
|
to be soul. These motes were referred to because they are seen
|
|
always in movement, even in a complete calm.
|
|
|
|
The same tendency is shown by those who define soul as that which
|
|
moves itself; all seem to hold the view that movement is what is
|
|
closest to the nature of soul, and that while all else is moved by
|
|
soul, it alone moves itself. This belief arises from their never
|
|
seeing anything originating movement which is not first itself moved.
|
|
|
|
Similarly also Anaxagoras (and whoever agrees with him in saying
|
|
that mind set the whole in movement) declares the moving cause of
|
|
things to be soul. His position must, however, be distinguished from
|
|
that of Democritus. Democritus roundly identifies soul and mind, for
|
|
he identifies what appears with what is true-that is why he commends
|
|
Homer for the phrase 'Hector lay with thought distraught'; he does not
|
|
employ mind as a special faculty dealing with truth, but identifies
|
|
soul and mind. What Anaxagoras says about them is more obscure; in
|
|
many places he tells us that the cause of beauty and order is mind,
|
|
elsewhere that it is soul; it is found, he says, in all animals, great
|
|
and small, high and low, but mind (in the sense of intelligence)
|
|
appears not to belong alike to all animals, and indeed not even to all
|
|
human beings.
|
|
|
|
All those, then, who had special regard to the fact that what has
|
|
soul in it is moved, adopted the view that soul is to be identified
|
|
with what is eminently originative of movement. All, on the other
|
|
hand, who looked to the fact that what has soul in it knows or
|
|
perceives what is, identify soul with the principle or principles of
|
|
Nature, according as they admit several such principles or one only.
|
|
Thus Empedocles declares that it is formed out of all his elements,
|
|
each of them also being soul; his words are:
|
|
|
|
For 'tis by Earth we see Earth, by Water Water,
|
|
|
|
By Ether Ether divine, by Fire destructive Fire,
|
|
|
|
By Love Love, and Hate by cruel Hate.
|
|
|
|
In the same way Plato in the Timaeus fashions soul out of his
|
|
elements; for like, he holds, is known by like, and things are
|
|
formed out of the principles or elements, so that soul must be so too.
|
|
Similarly also in his lectures 'On Philosophy' it was set forth that
|
|
the Animal-itself is compounded of the Idea itself of the One together
|
|
with the primary length, breadth, and depth, everything else, the
|
|
objects of its perception, being similarly constituted. Again he
|
|
puts his view in yet other terms: Mind is the monad, science or
|
|
knowledge the dyad (because it goes undeviatingly from one point to
|
|
another), opinion the number of the plane, sensation the number of the
|
|
solid; the numbers are by him expressly identified with the Forms
|
|
themselves or principles, and are formed out of the elements; now
|
|
things are apprehended either by mind or science or opinion or
|
|
sensation, and these same numbers are the Forms of things.
|
|
|
|
Some thinkers, accepting both premisses, viz. that the soul is
|
|
both originative of movement and cognitive, have compounded it of both
|
|
and declared the soul to be a self-moving number.
|
|
|
|
As to the nature and number of the first principles opinions differ.
|
|
The difference is greatest between those who regard them as
|
|
corporeal and those who regard them as incorporeal, and from both
|
|
dissent those who make a blend and draw their principles from both
|
|
sources. The number of principles is also in dispute; some admit one
|
|
only, others assert several. There is a consequent diversity in
|
|
their several accounts of soul; they assume, naturally enough, that
|
|
what is in its own nature originative of movement must be among what
|
|
is primordial. That has led some to regard it as fire, for fire is the
|
|
subtlest of the elements and nearest to incorporeality; further, in
|
|
the most primary sense, fire both is moved and originates movement
|
|
in all the others.
|
|
|
|
Democritus has expressed himself more ingeniously than the rest on
|
|
the grounds for ascribing each of these two characters to soul; soul
|
|
and mind are, he says, one and the same thing, and this thing must
|
|
be one of the primary and indivisible bodies, and its power of
|
|
originating movement must be due to its fineness of grain and the
|
|
shape of its atoms; he says that of all the shapes the spherical is
|
|
the most mobile, and that this is the shape of the particles of fire
|
|
and mind.
|
|
|
|
Anaxagoras, as we said above, seems to distinguish between soul
|
|
and mind, but in practice he treats them as a single substance, except
|
|
that it is mind that he specially posits as the principle of all
|
|
things; at any rate what he says is that mind alone of all that is
|
|
simple, unmixed, and pure. He assigns both characteristics, knowing
|
|
and origination of movement, to the same principle, when he says
|
|
that it was mind that set the whole in movement.
|
|
|
|
Thales, too, to judge from what is recorded about him, seems to have
|
|
held soul to be a motive force, since he said that the magnet has a
|
|
soul in it because it moves the iron.
|
|
|
|
Diogenes (and others) held the soul to be air because he believed
|
|
air to be finest in grain and a first principle; therein lay the
|
|
grounds of the soul's powers of knowing and originating movement. As
|
|
the primordial principle from which all other things are derived, it
|
|
is cognitive; as finest in grain, it has the power to originate
|
|
movement.
|
|
|
|
Heraclitus too says that the first principle-the 'warm exhalation'
|
|
of which, according to him, everything else is composed-is soul;
|
|
further, that this exhalation is most incorporeal and in ceaseless
|
|
flux; that what is in movement requires that what knows it should be
|
|
in movement; and that all that is has its being essentially in
|
|
movement (herein agreeing with the majority).
|
|
|
|
Alcmaeon also seems to have held a similar view about soul; he
|
|
says that it is immortal because it resembles 'the immortals,' and
|
|
that this immortality belongs to it in virtue of its ceaseless
|
|
movement; for all the 'things divine,' moon, sun, the planets, and the
|
|
whole heavens, are in perpetual movement.
|
|
|
|
of More superficial writers, some, e.g. Hippo, have pronounced it to
|
|
be water; they seem to have argued from the fact that the seed of
|
|
all animals is fluid, for Hippo tries to refute those who say that the
|
|
soul is blood, on the ground that the seed, which is the primordial
|
|
soul, is not blood.
|
|
|
|
Another group (Critias, for example) did hold it to be blood; they
|
|
take perception to be the most characteristic attribute of soul, and
|
|
hold that perceptiveness is due to the nature of blood.
|
|
|
|
Each of the elements has thus found its partisan, except earth-earth
|
|
has found no supporter unless we count as such those who have declared
|
|
soul to be, or to be compounded of, all the elements. All, then, it
|
|
may be said, characterize the soul by three marks, Movement,
|
|
Sensation, Incorporeality, and each of these is traced back to the
|
|
first principles. That is why (with one exception) all those who
|
|
define the soul by its power of knowing make it either an element or
|
|
constructed out of the elements. The language they all use is similar;
|
|
like, they say, is known by like; as the soul knows everything, they
|
|
construct it out of all the principles. Hence all those who admit
|
|
but one cause or element, make the soul also one (e.g. fire or air),
|
|
while those who admit a multiplicity of principles make the soul
|
|
also multiple. The exception is Anaxagoras; he alone says that mind is
|
|
impassible and has nothing in common with anything else. But, if
|
|
this is so, how or in virtue of what cause can it know? That
|
|
Anaxagoras has not explained, nor can any answer be inferred from
|
|
his words. All who acknowledge pairs of opposites among their
|
|
principles, construct the soul also out of these contraries, while
|
|
those who admit as principles only one contrary of each pair, e.g.
|
|
either hot or cold, likewise make the soul some one of these. That
|
|
is why, also, they allow themselves to be guided by the names; those
|
|
who identify soul with the hot argue that sen (to live) is derived
|
|
from sein (to boil), while those who identify it with the cold say
|
|
that soul (psuche) is so called from the process of respiration and
|
|
(katapsuxis). Such are the traditional opinions concerning soul,
|
|
together with the grounds on which they are maintained.
|
|
|
|
3
|
|
|
|
We must begin our examination with movement; for doubtless, not only
|
|
is it false that the essence of soul is correctly described by those
|
|
who say that it is what moves (or is capable of moving) itself, but it
|
|
is an impossibility that movement should be even an attribute of it.
|
|
|
|
We have already pointed out that there is no necessity that what
|
|
originates movement should itself be moved. There are two senses in
|
|
which anything may be moved-either (a) indirectly, owing to
|
|
something other than itself, or (b) directly, owing to itself.
|
|
Things are 'indirectly moved' which are moved as being contained in
|
|
something which is moved, e.g. sailors in a ship, for they are moved
|
|
in a different sense from that in which the ship is moved; the ship is
|
|
'directly moved', they are 'indirectly moved', because they are in a
|
|
moving vessel. This is clear if we consider their limbs; the
|
|
movement proper to the legs (and so to man) is walking, and in this
|
|
case the sailors tare not walking. Recognizing the double sense of
|
|
'being moved', what we have to consider now is whether the soul is
|
|
'directly moved' and participates in such direct movement.
|
|
|
|
There are four species of movement-locomotion, alteration,
|
|
diminution, growth; consequently if the soul is moved, it must be
|
|
moved with one or several or all of these species of movement. Now
|
|
if its movement is not incidental, there must be a movement natural to
|
|
it, and, if so, as all the species enumerated involve place, place
|
|
must be natural to it. But if the essence of soul be to move itself,
|
|
its being moved cannot be incidental to-as it is to what is white or
|
|
three cubits long; they too can be moved, but only incidentally-what
|
|
is moved is that of which 'white' and 'three cubits long' are the
|
|
attributes, the body in which they inhere; hence they have no place:
|
|
but if the soul naturally partakes in movement, it follows that it
|
|
must have a place.
|
|
|
|
Further, if there be a movement natural to the soul, there must be a
|
|
counter-movement unnatural to it, and conversely. The same applies
|
|
to rest as well as to movement; for the terminus ad quem of a
|
|
thing's natural movement is the place of its natural rest, and
|
|
similarly the terminus ad quem of its enforced movement is the place
|
|
of its enforced rest. But what meaning can be attached to enforced
|
|
movements or rests of the soul, it is difficult even to imagine.
|
|
|
|
Further, if the natural movement of the soul be upward, the soul
|
|
must be fire; if downward, it must be earth; for upward and downward
|
|
movements are the definitory characteristics of these bodies. The same
|
|
reasoning applies to the intermediate movements, termini, and
|
|
bodies. Further, since the soul is observed to originate movement in
|
|
the body, it is reasonable to suppose that it transmits to the body
|
|
the movements by which it itself is moved, and so, reversing the
|
|
order, we may infer from the movements of the body back to similar
|
|
movements of the soul. Now the body is moved from place to place
|
|
with movements of locomotion. Hence it would follow that the soul
|
|
too must in accordance with the body change either its place as a
|
|
whole or the relative places of its parts. This carries with it the
|
|
possibility that the soul might even quit its body and re-enter it,
|
|
and with this would be involved the possibility of a resurrection of
|
|
animals from the dead. But, it may be contended, the soul can be moved
|
|
indirectly by something else; for an animal can be pushed out of its
|
|
course. Yes, but that to whose essence belongs the power of being
|
|
moved by itself, cannot be moved by something else except
|
|
incidentally, just as what is good by or in itself cannot owe its
|
|
goodness to something external to it or to some end to which it is a
|
|
means.
|
|
|
|
If the soul is moved, the most probable view is that what moves it
|
|
is sensible things.
|
|
|
|
We must note also that, if the soul moves itself, it must be the
|
|
mover itself that is moved, so that it follows that if movement is
|
|
in every case a displacement of that which is in movement, in that
|
|
respect in which it is said to be moved, the movement of the soul must
|
|
be a departure from its essential nature, at least if its
|
|
self-movement is essential to it, not incidental.
|
|
|
|
Some go so far as to hold that the movements which the soul
|
|
imparts to the body in which it is are the same in kind as those
|
|
with which it itself is moved. An example of this is Democritus, who
|
|
uses language like that of the comic dramatist Philippus, who accounts
|
|
for the movements that Daedalus imparted to his wooden Aphrodite by
|
|
saying that he poured quicksilver into it; similarly Democritus says
|
|
that the spherical atoms which according to him constitute soul, owing
|
|
to their own ceaseless movements draw the whole body after them and so
|
|
produce its movements. We must urge the question whether it is these
|
|
very same atoms which produce rest also-how they could do so, it is
|
|
difficult and even impossible to say. And, in general, we may object
|
|
that it is not in this way that the soul appears to originate movement
|
|
in animals-it is through intention or process of thinking.
|
|
|
|
It is in the same fashion that the Timaeus also tries to give a
|
|
physical account of how the soul moves its body; the soul, it is there
|
|
said, is in movement, and so owing to their mutual implication moves
|
|
the body also. After compounding the soul-substance out of the
|
|
elements and dividing it in accordance with the harmonic numbers, in
|
|
order that it may possess a connate sensibility for 'harmony' and that
|
|
the whole may move in movements well attuned, the Demiurge bent the
|
|
straight line into a circle; this single circle he divided into two
|
|
circles united at two common points; one of these he subdivided into
|
|
seven circles. All this implies that the movements of the soul are
|
|
identified with the local movements of the heavens.
|
|
|
|
Now, in the first place, it is a mistake to say that the soul is a
|
|
spatial magnitude. It is evident that Plato means the soul of the
|
|
whole to be like the sort of soul which is called mind not like the
|
|
sensitive or the desiderative soul, for the movements of neither of
|
|
these are circular. Now mind is one and continuous in the sense in
|
|
which the process of thinking is so, and thinking is identical with
|
|
the thoughts which are its parts; these have a serial unity like
|
|
that of number, not a unity like that of a spatial magnitude. Hence
|
|
mind cannot have that kind of unity either; mind is either without
|
|
parts or is continuous in some other way than that which characterizes
|
|
a spatial magnitude. How, indeed, if it were a spatial magnitude,
|
|
could mind possibly think? Will it think with any one indifferently of
|
|
its parts? In this case, the 'part' must be understood either in the
|
|
sense of a spatial magnitude or in the sense of a point (if a point
|
|
can be called a part of a spatial magnitude). If we accept the
|
|
latter alternative, the points being infinite in number, obviously the
|
|
mind can never exhaustively traverse them; if the former, the mind
|
|
must think the same thing over and over again, indeed an infinite
|
|
number of times (whereas it is manifestly possible to think a thing
|
|
once only). If contact of any part whatsoever of itself with the
|
|
object is all that is required, why need mind move in a circle, or
|
|
indeed possess magnitude at all? On the other hand, if contact with
|
|
the whole circle is necessary, what meaning can be given to the
|
|
contact of the parts? Further, how could what has no parts think
|
|
what has parts, or what has parts think what has none? We must
|
|
identify the circle referred to with mind; for it is mind whose
|
|
movement is thinking, and it is the circle whose movement is
|
|
revolution, so that if thinking is a movement of revolution, the
|
|
circle which has this characteristic movement must be mind.
|
|
|
|
If the circular movement is eternal, there must be something which
|
|
mind is always thinking-what can this be? For all practical
|
|
processes of thinking have limits-they all go on for the sake of
|
|
something outside the process, and all theoretical processes come to a
|
|
close in the same way as the phrases in speech which express processes
|
|
and results of thinking. Every such linguistic phrase is either
|
|
definitory or demonstrative. Demonstration has both a starting-point
|
|
and may be said to end in a conclusion or inferred result; even if the
|
|
process never reaches final completion, at any rate it never returns
|
|
upon itself again to its starting-point, it goes on assuming a fresh
|
|
middle term or a fresh extreme, and moves straight forward, but
|
|
circular movement returns to its starting-point. Definitions, too, are
|
|
closed groups of terms.
|
|
|
|
Further, if the same revolution is repeated, mind must repeatedly
|
|
think the same object.
|
|
|
|
Further, thinking has more resemblance to a coming to rest or arrest
|
|
than to a movement; the same may be said of inferring.
|
|
|
|
It might also be urged that what is difficult and enforced is
|
|
incompatible with blessedness; if the movement of the soul is not of
|
|
its essence, movement of the soul must be contrary to its nature. It
|
|
must also be painful for the soul to be inextricably bound up with the
|
|
body; nay more, if, as is frequently said and widely accepted, it is
|
|
better for mind not to be embodied, the union must be for it
|
|
undesirable.
|
|
|
|
Further, the cause of the revolution of the heavens is left obscure.
|
|
It is not the essence of soul which is the cause of this circular
|
|
movement-that movement is only incidental to soul-nor is, a
|
|
fortiori, the body its cause. Again, it is not even asserted that it
|
|
is better that soul should be so moved; and yet the reason for which
|
|
God caused the soul to move in a circle can only have been that
|
|
movement was better for it than rest, and movement of this kind better
|
|
than any other. But since this sort of consideration is more
|
|
appropriate to another field of speculation, let us dismiss it for the
|
|
present.
|
|
|
|
The view we have just been examining, in company with most
|
|
theories about the soul, involves the following absurdity: they all
|
|
join the soul to a body, or place it in a body, without adding any
|
|
specification of the reason of their union, or of the bodily
|
|
conditions required for it. Yet such explanation can scarcely be
|
|
omitted; for some community of nature is presupposed by the fact
|
|
that the one acts and the other is acted upon, the one moves and the
|
|
other is moved; interaction always implies a special nature in the two
|
|
interagents. All, however, that these thinkers do is to describe the
|
|
specific characteristics of the soul; they do not try to determine
|
|
anything about the body which is to contain it, as if it were
|
|
possible, as in the Pythagorean myths, that any soul could be
|
|
clothed upon with any body-an absurd view, for each body seems to have
|
|
a form and shape of its own. It is as absurd as to say that the art of
|
|
carpentry could embody itself in flutes; each art must use its
|
|
tools, each soul its body.
|
|
|
|
4
|
|
|
|
There is yet another theory about soul, which has commended itself
|
|
to many as no less probable than any of those we have hitherto
|
|
mentioned, and has rendered public account of itself in the court of
|
|
popular discussion. Its supporters say that the soul is a kind of
|
|
harmony, for (a) harmony is a blend or composition of contraries,
|
|
and (b) the body is compounded out of contraries. Harmony, however, is
|
|
a certain proportion or composition of the constituents blended, and
|
|
soul can be neither the one nor the other of these. Further, the power
|
|
of originating movement cannot belong to a harmony, while almost all
|
|
concur in regarding this as a principal attribute of soul. It is
|
|
more appropriate to call health (or generally one of the good states
|
|
of the body) a harmony than to predicate it of the soul. The absurdity
|
|
becomes most apparent when we try to attribute the active and
|
|
passive affections of the soul to a harmony; the necessary
|
|
readjustment of their conceptions is difficult. Further, in using
|
|
the word 'harmony' we have one or other of two cases in our mind;
|
|
the most proper sense is in relation to spatial magnitudes which
|
|
have motion and position, where harmony means the disposition and
|
|
cohesion of their parts in such a manner as to prevent the
|
|
introduction into the whole of anything homogeneous with it, and the
|
|
secondary sense, derived from the former, is that in which it means
|
|
the ratio between the constituents so blended; in neither of these
|
|
senses is it plausible to predicate it of soul. That soul is a harmony
|
|
in the sense of the mode of composition of the parts of the body is
|
|
a view easily refutable; for there are many composite parts and
|
|
those variously compounded; of what bodily part is mind or the
|
|
sensitive or the appetitive faculty the mode of composition? And
|
|
what is the mode of composition which constitutes each of them? It
|
|
is equally absurd to identify the soul with the ratio of the
|
|
mixture; for the mixture which makes flesh has a different ratio
|
|
between the elements from that which makes bone. The consequence of
|
|
this view will therefore be that distributed throughout the whole body
|
|
there will be many souls, since every one of the bodily parts is a
|
|
different mixture of the elements, and the ratio of mixture is in each
|
|
case a harmony, i.e. a soul.
|
|
|
|
From Empedocles at any rate we might demand an answer to the
|
|
following question for he says that each of the parts of the body is
|
|
what it is in virtue of a ratio between the elements: is the soul
|
|
identical with this ratio, or is it not rather something over and
|
|
above this which is formed in the parts? Is love the cause of any
|
|
and every mixture, or only of those that are in the right ratio? Is
|
|
love this ratio itself, or is love something over and above this? Such
|
|
are the problems raised by this account. But, on the other hand, if
|
|
the soul is different from the mixture, why does it disappear at one
|
|
and the same moment with that relation between the elements which
|
|
constitutes flesh or the other parts of the animal body? Further, if
|
|
the soul is not identical with the ratio of mixture, and it is
|
|
consequently not the case that each of the parts has a soul, what is
|
|
that which perishes when the soul quits the body?
|
|
|
|
That the soul cannot either be a harmony, or be moved in a circle,
|
|
is clear from what we have said. Yet that it can be moved incidentally
|
|
is, as we said above, possible, and even that in a sense it can move
|
|
itself, i.e. in the sense that the vehicle in which it is can be
|
|
moved, and moved by it; in no other sense can the soul be moved in
|
|
space.
|
|
|
|
More legitimate doubts might remain as to its movement in view of
|
|
the following facts. We speak of the soul as being pained or
|
|
pleased, being bold or fearful, being angry, perceiving, thinking. All
|
|
these are regarded as modes of movement, and hence it might be
|
|
inferred that the soul is moved. This, however, does not necessarily
|
|
follow. We may admit to the full that being pained or pleased, or
|
|
thinking, are movements (each of them a 'being moved'), and that the
|
|
movement is originated by the soul. For example we may regard anger or
|
|
fear as such and such movements of the heart, and thinking as such and
|
|
such another movement of that organ, or of some other; these
|
|
modifications may arise either from changes of place in certain
|
|
parts or from qualitative alterations (the special nature of the parts
|
|
and the special modes of their changes being for our present purpose
|
|
irrelevant). Yet to say that it is the soul which is angry is as
|
|
inexact as it would be to say that it is the soul that weaves webs
|
|
or builds houses. It is doubtless better to avoid saying that the soul
|
|
pities or learns or thinks and rather to say that it is the man who
|
|
does this with his soul. What we mean is not that the movement is in
|
|
the soul, but that sometimes it terminates in the soul and sometimes
|
|
starts from it, sensation e.g. coming from without inwards, and
|
|
reminiscence starting from the soul and terminating with the
|
|
movements, actual or residual, in the sense organs.
|
|
|
|
The case of mind is different; it seems to be an independent
|
|
substance implanted within the soul and to be incapable of being
|
|
destroyed. If it could be destroyed at all, it would be under the
|
|
blunting influence of old age. What really happens in respect of
|
|
mind in old age is, however, exactly parallel to what happens in the
|
|
case of the sense organs; if the old man could recover the proper kind
|
|
of eye, he would see just as well as the young man. The incapacity
|
|
of old age is due to an affection not of the soul but of its
|
|
vehicle, as occurs in drunkenness or disease. Thus it is that in old
|
|
age the activity of mind or intellectual apprehension declines only
|
|
through the decay of some other inward part; mind itself is
|
|
impassible. Thinking, loving, and hating are affections not of mind,
|
|
but of that which has mind, so far as it has it. That is why, when
|
|
this vehicle decays, memory and love cease; they were activities not
|
|
of mind, but of the composite which has perished; mind is, no doubt,
|
|
something more divine and impassible. That the soul cannot be moved is
|
|
therefore clear from what we have said, and if it cannot be moved at
|
|
all, manifestly it cannot be moved by itself.
|
|
|
|
Of all the opinions we have enumerated, by far the most unreasonable
|
|
is that which declares the soul to be a self-moving number; it
|
|
involves in the first place all the impossibilities which follow
|
|
from regarding the soul as moved, and in the second special
|
|
absurdities which follow from calling it a number. How we to imagine a
|
|
unit being moved? By what agency? What sort of movement can be
|
|
attributed to what is without parts or internal differences? If the
|
|
unit is both originative of movement and itself capable of being
|
|
moved, it must contain difference.
|
|
|
|
Further, since they say a moving line generates a surface and a
|
|
moving point a line, the movements of the psychic units must be
|
|
lines (for a point is a unit having position, and the number of the
|
|
soul is, of course, somewhere and has position).
|
|
|
|
Again, if from a number a number or a unit is subtracted, the
|
|
remainder is another number; but plants and many animals when
|
|
divided continue to live, and each segment is thought to retain the
|
|
same kind of soul.
|
|
|
|
It must be all the same whether we speak of units or corpuscles; for
|
|
if the spherical atoms of Democritus became points, nothing being
|
|
retained but their being a quantum, there must remain in each a moving
|
|
and a moved part, just as there is in what is continuous; what happens
|
|
has nothing to do with the size of the atoms, it depends solely upon
|
|
their being a quantum. That is why there must be something to
|
|
originate movement in the units. If in the animal what originates
|
|
movement is the soul, so also must it be in the case of the number, so
|
|
that not the mover and the moved together, but the mover only, will be
|
|
the soul. But how is it possible for one of the units to fulfil this
|
|
function of originating movement? There must be some difference
|
|
between such a unit and all the other units, and what difference can
|
|
there be between one placed unit and another except a difference of
|
|
position? If then, on the other hand, these psychic units within the
|
|
body are different from the points of the body, there will be two sets
|
|
of units both occupying the same place; for each unit will occupy a
|
|
point. And yet, if there can be two, why cannot there be an infinite
|
|
number? For if things can occupy an indivisible lace, they must
|
|
themselves be indivisible. If, on the other hand, the points of the
|
|
body are identical with the units whose number is the soul, or if
|
|
the number of the points in the body is the soul, why have not all
|
|
bodies souls? For all bodies contain points or an infinity of points.
|
|
|
|
Further, how is it possible for these points to be isolated or
|
|
separated from their bodies, seeing that lines cannot be resolved into
|
|
points?
|
|
|
|
5
|
|
|
|
The result is, as we have said, that this view, while on the one
|
|
side identical with that of those who maintain that soul is a subtle
|
|
kind of body, is on the other entangled in the absurdity peculiar to
|
|
Democritus' way of describing the manner in which movement is
|
|
originated by soul. For if the soul is present throughout the whole
|
|
percipient body, there must, if the soul be a kind of body, be two
|
|
bodies in the same place; and for those who call it a number, there
|
|
must be many points at one point, or every body must have a soul,
|
|
unless the soul be a different sort of number-other, that is, than the
|
|
sum of the points existing in a body. Another consequence that follows
|
|
is that the animal must be moved by its number precisely in the way
|
|
that Democritus explained its being moved by his spherical psychic
|
|
atoms. What difference does it make whether we speak of small
|
|
spheres or of large units, or, quite simply, of units in movement? One
|
|
way or another, the movements of the animal must be due to their
|
|
movements. Hence those who combine movement and number in the same
|
|
subject lay themselves open to these and many other similar
|
|
absurdities. It is impossible not only that these characters should
|
|
give the definition of soul-it is impossible that they should even
|
|
be attributes of it. The point is clear if the attempt be made to
|
|
start from this as the account of soul and explain from it the
|
|
affections and actions of the soul, e.g. reasoning, sensation,
|
|
pleasure, pain, &c. For, to repeat what we have said earlier, movement
|
|
and number do not facilitate even conjecture about the derivative
|
|
properties of soul.
|
|
|
|
Such are the three ways in which soul has traditionally been
|
|
defined; one group of thinkers declared it to be that which is most
|
|
originative of movement because it moves itself, another group to be
|
|
the subtlest and most nearly incorporeal of all kinds of body. We have
|
|
now sufficiently set forth the difficulties and inconsistencies to
|
|
which these theories are exposed. It remains now to examine the
|
|
doctrine that soul is composed of the elements.
|
|
|
|
The reason assigned for this doctrine is that thus the soul may
|
|
perceive or come to know everything that is, but the theory
|
|
necessarily involves itself in many impossibilities. Its upholders
|
|
assume that like is known only by like, and imagine that by
|
|
declaring the soul to be composed of the elements they succeed in
|
|
identifying the soul with all the things it is capable of
|
|
apprehending. But the elements are not the only things it knows; there
|
|
are many others, or, more exactly, an infinite number of others,
|
|
formed out of the elements. Let us admit that the soul knows or
|
|
perceives the elements out of which each of these composites is made
|
|
up; but by what means will it know or perceive the composite whole,
|
|
e.g. what God, man, flesh, bone (or any other compound) is? For each
|
|
is, not merely the elements of which it is composed, but those
|
|
elements combined in a determinate mode or ratio, as Empedocles
|
|
himself says of bone,
|
|
|
|
The kindly Earth in its broad-bosomed moulds
|
|
|
|
Won of clear Water two parts out of eight,
|
|
|
|
And four of Fire; and so white bones were formed.
|
|
|
|
Nothing, therefore, will be gained by the presence of the elements
|
|
in the soul, unless there be also present there the various formulae
|
|
of proportion and the various compositions in accordance with them.
|
|
Each element will indeed know its fellow outside, but there will be no
|
|
knowledge of bone or man, unless they too are present in the
|
|
constitution of the soul. The impossibility of this needs no
|
|
pointing out; for who would suggest that stone or man could enter into
|
|
the constitution of the soul? The same applies to 'the good' and
|
|
'the not-good', and so on.
|
|
|
|
Further, the word 'is' has many meanings: it may be used of a 'this'
|
|
or substance, or of a quantum, or of a quale, or of any other of the
|
|
kinds of predicates we have distinguished. Does the soul consist of
|
|
all of these or not? It does not appear that all have common elements.
|
|
Is the soul formed out of those elements alone which enter into
|
|
substances? so how will it be able to know each of the other kinds
|
|
of thing? Will it be said that each kind of thing has elements or
|
|
principles of its own, and that the soul is formed out of the whole of
|
|
these? In that case, the soul must be a quantum and a quale and a
|
|
substance. But all that can be made out of the elements of a quantum
|
|
is a quantum, not a substance. These (and others like them) are the
|
|
consequences of the view that the soul is composed of all the
|
|
elements.
|
|
|
|
It is absurd, also, to say both (a) that like is not capable of
|
|
being affected by like, and (b) that like is perceived or known by
|
|
like, for perceiving, and also both thinking and knowing, are, on
|
|
their own assumption, ways of being affected or moved.
|
|
|
|
There are many puzzles and difficulties raised by saying, as
|
|
Empedocles does, that each set of things is known by means of its
|
|
corporeal elements and by reference to something in soul which is like
|
|
them, and additional testimony is furnished by this new consideration;
|
|
for all the parts of the animal body which consist wholly of earth
|
|
such as bones, sinews, and hair seem to be wholly insensitive and
|
|
consequently not perceptive even of objects earthy like themselves, as
|
|
they ought to have been.
|
|
|
|
Further, each of the principles will have far more ignorance than
|
|
knowledge, for though each of them will know one thing, there will
|
|
be many of which it will be ignorant. Empedocles at any rate must
|
|
conclude that his God is the least intelligent of all beings, for of
|
|
him alone is it true that there is one thing, Strife, which he does
|
|
not know, while there is nothing which mortal beings do not know,
|
|
for ere is nothing which does not enter into their composition.
|
|
|
|
In general, we may ask, Why has not everything a soul, since
|
|
everything either is an element, or is formed out of one or several or
|
|
all of the elements? Each must certainly know one or several or all.
|
|
|
|
The problem might also be raised, What is that which unifies the
|
|
elements into a soul? The elements correspond, it would appear, to the
|
|
matter; what unites them, whatever it is, is the supremely important
|
|
factor. But it is impossible that there should be something superior
|
|
to, and dominant over, the soul (and a fortiori over the mind); it
|
|
is reasonable to hold that mind is by nature most primordial and
|
|
dominant, while their statement that it is the elements which are
|
|
first of all that is.
|
|
|
|
All, both those who assert that the soul, because of its knowledge
|
|
or perception of what is compounded out of the elements, and is
|
|
those who assert that it is of all things the most originative of
|
|
movement, fail to take into consideration all kinds of soul. In fact
|
|
(1) not all beings that perceive can originate movement; there
|
|
appear to be certain animals which stationary, and yet local
|
|
movement is the only one, so it seems, which the soul originates in
|
|
animals. And (2) the same object-on holds against all those who
|
|
construct mind and the perceptive faculty out of the elements; for
|
|
it appears that plants live, and yet are not endowed with locomotion
|
|
or perception, while a large number of animals are without discourse
|
|
of reason. Even if these points were waived and mind admitted to be
|
|
a part of the soul (and so too the perceptive faculty), still, even
|
|
so, there would be kinds and parts of soul of which they had failed to
|
|
give any account.
|
|
|
|
The same objection lies against the view expressed in the 'Orphic'
|
|
poems: there it is said that the soul comes in from the whole when
|
|
breathing takes place, being borne in upon the winds. Now this
|
|
cannot take place in the case of plants, nor indeed in the case of
|
|
certain classes of animal, for not all classes of animal breathe. This
|
|
fact has escaped the notice of the holders of this view.
|
|
|
|
If we must construct the soul out of the elements, there is no
|
|
necessity to suppose that all the elements enter into its
|
|
construction; one element in each pair of contraries will suffice to
|
|
enable it to know both that element itself and its contrary. By
|
|
means of the straight line we know both itself and the curved-the
|
|
carpenter's rule enables us to test both-but what is curved does not
|
|
enable us to distinguish either itself or the straight. Certain
|
|
thinkers say that soul is intermingled in the whole universe, and it
|
|
is perhaps for that reason that Thales came to the opinion that all
|
|
things are full of gods. This presents some difficulties: Why does the
|
|
soul when it resides in air or fire not form an animal, while it
|
|
does so when it resides in mixtures of the elements, and that although
|
|
it is held to be of higher quality when contained in the former?
|
|
(One might add the question, why the soul in air is maintained to be
|
|
higher and more immortal than that in animals.) Both possible ways
|
|
of replying to the former question lead to absurdity or paradox; for
|
|
it is beyond paradox to say that fire or air is an animal, and it is
|
|
absurd to refuse the name of animal to what has soul in it. The
|
|
opinion that the elements have soul in them seems to have arisen
|
|
from the doctrine that a whole must be homogeneous with its parts.
|
|
If it is true that animals become animate by drawing into themselves a
|
|
portion of what surrounds them, the partisans of this view are bound
|
|
to say that the soul of the Whole too is homogeneous with all its
|
|
parts. If the air sucked in is homogeneous, but soul heterogeneous,
|
|
clearly while some part of soul will exist in the inbreathed air, some
|
|
other part will not. The soul must either be homogeneous, or such that
|
|
there are some parts of the Whole in which it is not to be found.
|
|
|
|
From what has been said it is now clear that knowing as an attribute
|
|
of soul cannot be explained by soul's being composed of the
|
|
elements, and that it is neither sound nor true to speak of soul as
|
|
moved. But since (a) knowing, perceiving, opining, and further (b)
|
|
desiring, wishing, and generally all other modes of appetition, belong
|
|
to soul, and (c) the local movements of animals, and (d) growth,
|
|
maturity, and decay are produced by the soul, we must ask whether each
|
|
of these is an attribute of the soul as a whole, i.e. whether it is
|
|
with the whole soul we think, perceive, move ourselves, act or are
|
|
acted upon, or whether each of them requires a different part of the
|
|
soul? So too with regard to life. Does it depend on one of the parts
|
|
of soul? Or is it dependent on more than one? Or on all? Or has it
|
|
some quite other cause?
|
|
|
|
Some hold that the soul is divisible, and that one part thinks,
|
|
another desires. If, then, its nature admits of its being divided,
|
|
what can it be that holds the parts together? Surely not the body;
|
|
on the contrary it seems rather to be the soul that holds the body
|
|
together; at any rate when the soul departs the body disintegrates and
|
|
decays. If, then, there is something else which makes the soul one,
|
|
this unifying agency would have the best right to the name of soul,
|
|
and we shall have to repeat for it the question: Is it one or
|
|
multipartite? If it is one, why not at once admit that 'the soul' is
|
|
one? If it has parts, once more the question must be put: What holds
|
|
its parts together, and so ad infinitum?
|
|
|
|
The question might also be raised about the parts of the soul:
|
|
What is the separate role of each in relation to the body? For, if the
|
|
whole soul holds together the whole body, we should expect each part
|
|
of the soul to hold together a part of the body. But this seems an
|
|
impossibility; it is difficult even to imagine what sort of bodily
|
|
part mind will hold together, or how it will do this.
|
|
|
|
It is a fact of observation that plants and certain insects go on
|
|
living when divided into segments; this means that each of the
|
|
segments has a soul in it identical in species, though not numerically
|
|
identical in the different segments, for both of the segments for a
|
|
time possess the power of sensation and local movement. That this does
|
|
not last is not surprising, for they no longer possess the organs
|
|
necessary for self-maintenance. But, all the same, in each of the
|
|
bodily parts there are present all the parts of soul, and the souls so
|
|
present are homogeneous with one another and with the whole; this
|
|
means that the several parts of the soul are indisseverable from one
|
|
another, although the whole soul is divisible. It seems also that
|
|
the principle found in plants is also a kind of soul; for this is
|
|
the only principle which is common to both animals and plants; and
|
|
this exists in isolation from the principle of sensation, though there
|
|
nothing which has the latter without the former.
|
|
|
|
Book II
|
|
|
|
1
|
|
|
|
LET the foregoing suffice as our account of the views concerning the
|
|
soul which have been handed on by our predecessors; let us now dismiss
|
|
them and make as it were a completely fresh start, endeavouring to
|
|
give a precise answer to the question, What is soul? i.e. to formulate
|
|
the most general possible definition of it.
|
|
|
|
We are in the habit of recognizing, as one determinate kind of
|
|
what is, substance, and that in several senses, (a) in the sense of
|
|
matter or that which in itself is not 'a this', and (b) in the sense
|
|
of form or essence, which is that precisely in virtue of which a thing
|
|
is called 'a this', and thirdly (c) in the sense of that which is
|
|
compounded of both (a) and (b). Now matter is potentiality, form
|
|
actuality; of the latter there are two grades related to one another
|
|
as e.g. knowledge to the exercise of knowledge.
|
|
|
|
Among substances are by general consent reckoned bodies and
|
|
especially natural bodies; for they are the principles of all other
|
|
bodies. Of natural bodies some have life in them, others not; by
|
|
life we mean self-nutrition and growth (with its correlative decay).
|
|
It follows that every natural body which has life in it is a substance
|
|
in the sense of a composite.
|
|
|
|
But since it is also a body of such and such a kind, viz. having
|
|
life, the body cannot be soul; the body is the subject or matter,
|
|
not what is attributed to it. Hence the soul must be a substance in
|
|
the sense of the form of a natural body having life potentially within
|
|
it. But substance is actuality, and thus soul is the actuality of a
|
|
body as above characterized. Now the word actuality has two senses
|
|
corresponding respectively to the possession of knowledge and the
|
|
actual exercise of knowledge. It is obvious that the soul is actuality
|
|
in the first sense, viz. that of knowledge as possessed, for both
|
|
sleeping and waking presuppose the existence of soul, and of these
|
|
waking corresponds to actual knowing, sleeping to knowledge
|
|
possessed but not employed, and, in the history of the individual,
|
|
knowledge comes before its employment or exercise.
|
|
|
|
That is why the soul is the first grade of actuality of a natural
|
|
body having life potentially in it. The body so described is a body
|
|
which is organized. The parts of plants in spite of their extreme
|
|
simplicity are 'organs'; e.g. the leaf serves to shelter the pericarp,
|
|
the pericarp to shelter the fruit, while the roots of plants are
|
|
analogous to the mouth of animals, both serving for the absorption
|
|
of food. If, then, we have to give a general formula applicable to all
|
|
kinds of soul, we must describe it as the first grade of actuality
|
|
of a natural organized body. That is why we can wholly dismiss as
|
|
unnecessary the question whether the soul and the body are one: it
|
|
is as meaningless as to ask whether the wax and the shape given to
|
|
it by the stamp are one, or generally the matter of a thing and that
|
|
of which it is the matter. Unity has many senses (as many as 'is'
|
|
has), but the most proper and fundamental sense of both is the
|
|
relation of an actuality to that of which it is the actuality. We have
|
|
now given an answer to the question, What is soul?-an answer which
|
|
applies to it in its full extent. It is substance in the sense which
|
|
corresponds to the definitive formula of a thing's essence. That means
|
|
that it is 'the essential whatness' of a body of the character just
|
|
assigned. Suppose that what is literally an 'organ', like an axe, were
|
|
a natural body, its 'essential whatness', would have been its essence,
|
|
and so its soul; if this disappeared from it, it would have ceased
|
|
to be an axe, except in name. As it is, it is just an axe; it wants
|
|
the character which is required to make its whatness or formulable
|
|
essence a soul; for that, it would have had to be a natural body of
|
|
a particular kind, viz. one having in itself the power of setting
|
|
itself in movement and arresting itself. Next, apply this doctrine
|
|
in the case of the 'parts' of the living body. Suppose that the eye
|
|
were an animal-sight would have been its soul, for sight is the
|
|
substance or essence of the eye which corresponds to the formula,
|
|
the eye being merely the matter of seeing; when seeing is removed
|
|
the eye is no longer an eye, except in name-it is no more a real eye
|
|
than the eye of a statue or of a painted figure. We must now extend
|
|
our consideration from the 'parts' to the whole living body; for
|
|
what the departmental sense is to the bodily part which is its
|
|
organ, that the whole faculty of sense is to the whole sensitive
|
|
body as such.
|
|
|
|
We must not understand by that which is 'potentially capable of
|
|
living' what has lost the soul it had, but only what still retains it;
|
|
but seeds and fruits are bodies which possess the qualification.
|
|
Consequently, while waking is actuality in a sense corresponding to
|
|
the cutting and the seeing, the soul is actuality in the sense
|
|
corresponding to the power of sight and the power in the tool; the
|
|
body corresponds to what exists in potentiality; as the pupil plus the
|
|
power of sight constitutes the eye, so the soul plus the body
|
|
constitutes the animal.
|
|
|
|
From this it indubitably follows that the soul is inseparable from
|
|
its body, or at any rate that certain parts of it are (if it has
|
|
parts) for the actuality of some of them is nothing but the
|
|
actualities of their bodily parts. Yet some may be separable because
|
|
they are not the actualities of any body at all. Further, we have no
|
|
light on the problem whether the soul may not be the actuality of
|
|
its body in the sense in which the sailor is the actuality of the
|
|
ship.
|
|
|
|
This must suffice as our sketch or outline determination of the
|
|
nature of soul.
|
|
|
|
2
|
|
|
|
Since what is clear or logically more evident emerges from what in
|
|
itself is confused but more observable by us, we must reconsider our
|
|
results from this point of view. For it is not enough for a definitive
|
|
formula to express as most now do the mere fact; it must include and
|
|
exhibit the ground also. At present definitions are given in a form
|
|
analogous to the conclusion of a syllogism; e.g. What is squaring? The
|
|
construction of an equilateral rectangle equal to a given oblong
|
|
rectangle. Such a definition is in form equivalent to a conclusion.
|
|
One that tells us that squaring is the discovery of a line which is
|
|
a mean proportional between the two unequal sides of the given
|
|
rectangle discloses the ground of what is defined.
|
|
|
|
We resume our inquiry from a fresh starting-point by calling
|
|
attention to the fact that what has soul in it differs from what has
|
|
not, in that the former displays life. Now this word has more than one
|
|
sense, and provided any one alone of these is found in a thing we
|
|
say that thing is living. Living, that is, may mean thinking or
|
|
perception or local movement and rest, or movement in the sense of
|
|
nutrition, decay and growth. Hence we think of plants also as
|
|
living, for they are observed to possess in themselves an
|
|
originative power through which they increase or decrease in all
|
|
spatial directions; they grow up and down, and everything that grows
|
|
increases its bulk alike in both directions or indeed in all, and
|
|
continues to live so long as it can absorb nutriment.
|
|
|
|
This power of self-nutrition can be isolated from the other powers
|
|
mentioned, but not they from it-in mortal beings at least. The fact is
|
|
obvious in plants; for it is the only psychic power they possess.
|
|
|
|
This is the originative power the possession of which leads us to
|
|
speak of things as living at all, but it is the possession of
|
|
sensation that leads us for the first time to speak of living things
|
|
as animals; for even those beings which possess no power of local
|
|
movement but do possess the power of sensation we call animals and not
|
|
merely living things.
|
|
|
|
The primary form of sense is touch, which belongs to all animals.
|
|
just as the power of self-nutrition can be isolated from touch and
|
|
sensation generally, so touch can be isolated from all other forms
|
|
of sense. (By the power of self-nutrition we mean that departmental
|
|
power of the soul which is common to plants and animals: all animals
|
|
whatsoever are observed to have the sense of touch.) What the
|
|
explanation of these two facts is, we must discuss later. At present
|
|
we must confine ourselves to saying that soul is the source of these
|
|
phenomena and is characterized by them, viz. by the powers of
|
|
self-nutrition, sensation, thinking, and motivity.
|
|
|
|
Is each of these a soul or a part of a soul? And if a part, a part
|
|
in what sense? A part merely distinguishable by definition or a part
|
|
distinct in local situation as well? In the case of certain of these
|
|
powers, the answers to these questions are easy, in the case of others
|
|
we are puzzled what to say. just as in the case of plants which when
|
|
divided are observed to continue to live though removed to a
|
|
distance from one another (thus showing that in their case the soul of
|
|
each individual plant before division was actually one, potentially
|
|
many), so we notice a similar result in other varieties of soul,
|
|
i.e. in insects which have been cut in two; each of the segments
|
|
possesses both sensation and local movement; and if sensation,
|
|
necessarily also imagination and appetition; for, where there is
|
|
sensation, there is also pleasure and pain, and, where these,
|
|
necessarily also desire.
|
|
|
|
We have no evidence as yet about mind or the power to think; it
|
|
seems to be a widely different kind of soul, differing as what is
|
|
eternal from what is perishable; it alone is capable of existence in
|
|
isolation from all other psychic powers. All the other parts of
|
|
soul, it is evident from what we have said, are, in spite of certain
|
|
statements to the contrary, incapable of separate existence though, of
|
|
course, distinguishable by definition. If opining is distinct from
|
|
perceiving, to be capable of opining and to be capable of perceiving
|
|
must be distinct, and so with all the other forms of living above
|
|
enumerated. Further, some animals possess all these parts of soul,
|
|
some certain of them only, others one only (this is what enables us to
|
|
classify animals); the cause must be considered later.' A similar
|
|
arrangement is found also within the field of the senses; some classes
|
|
of animals have all the senses, some only certain of them, others only
|
|
one, the most indispensable, touch.
|
|
|
|
Since the expression 'that whereby we live and perceive' has two
|
|
meanings, just like the expression 'that whereby we know'-that may
|
|
mean either (a) knowledge or (b) the soul, for we can speak of knowing
|
|
by or with either, and similarly that whereby we are in health may
|
|
be either (a) health or (b) the body or some part of the body; and
|
|
since of the two terms thus contrasted knowledge or health is the name
|
|
of a form, essence, or ratio, or if we so express it an actuality of a
|
|
recipient matter-knowledge of what is capable of knowing, health of
|
|
what is capable of being made healthy (for the operation of that which
|
|
is capable of originating change terminates and has its seat in what
|
|
is changed or altered); further, since it is the soul by or with which
|
|
primarily we live, perceive, and think:-it follows that the soul
|
|
must be a ratio or formulable essence, not a matter or subject. For,
|
|
as we said, word substance has three meanings form, matter, and the
|
|
complex of both and of these three what is called matter is
|
|
potentiality, what is called form actuality. Since then the complex
|
|
here is the living thing, the body cannot be the actuality of the
|
|
soul; it is the soul which is the actuality of a certain kind of body.
|
|
Hence the rightness of the view that the soul cannot be without a
|
|
body, while it csnnot he a body; it is not a body but something
|
|
relative to a body. That is why it is in a body, and a body of a
|
|
definite kind. It was a mistake, therefore, to do as former thinkers
|
|
did, merely to fit it into a body without adding a definite
|
|
specification of the kind or character of that body. Reflection
|
|
confirms the observed fact; the actuality of any given thing can
|
|
only be realized in what is already potentially that thing, i.e. in
|
|
a matter of its own appropriate to it. From all this it follows that
|
|
soul is an actuality or formulable essence of something that possesses
|
|
a potentiality of being besouled.
|
|
|
|
3
|
|
|
|
Of the psychic powers above enumerated some kinds of living
|
|
things, as we have said, possess all, some less than all, others one
|
|
only. Those we have mentioned are the nutritive, the appetitive, the
|
|
sensory, the locomotive, and the power of thinking. Plants have none
|
|
but the first, the nutritive, while another order of living things has
|
|
this plus the sensory. If any order of living things has the
|
|
sensory, it must also have the appetitive; for appetite is the genus
|
|
of which desire, passion, and wish are the species; now all animals
|
|
have one sense at least, viz. touch, and whatever has a sense has
|
|
the capacity for pleasure and pain and therefore has pleasant and
|
|
painful objects present to it, and wherever these are present, there
|
|
is desire, for desire is just appetition of what is pleasant. Further,
|
|
all animals have the sense for food (for touch is the sense for food);
|
|
the food of all living things consists of what is dry, moist, hot,
|
|
cold, and these are the qualities apprehended by touch; all other
|
|
sensible qualities are apprehended by touch only indirectly. Sounds,
|
|
colours, and odours contribute nothing to nutriment; flavours fall
|
|
within the field of tangible qualities. Hunger and thirst are forms of
|
|
desire, hunger a desire for what is dry and hot, thirst a desire for
|
|
what is cold and moist; flavour is a sort of seasoning added to
|
|
both. We must later clear up these points, but at present it may be
|
|
enough to say that all animals that possess the sense of touch have
|
|
also appetition. The case of imagination is obscure; we must examine
|
|
it later. Certain kinds of animals possess in addition the power of
|
|
locomotion, and still another order of animate beings, i.e. man and
|
|
possibly another order like man or superior to him, the power of
|
|
thinking, i.e. mind. It is now evident that a single definition can be
|
|
given of soul only in the same sense as one can be given of figure.
|
|
For, as in that case there is no figure distinguishable and apart from
|
|
triangle, &c., so here there is no soul apart from the forms of soul
|
|
just enumerated. It is true that a highly general definition can be
|
|
given for figure which will fit all figures without expressing the
|
|
peculiar nature of any figure. So here in the case of soul and its
|
|
specific forms. Hence it is absurd in this and similar cases to demand
|
|
an absolutely general definition which will fail to express the
|
|
peculiar nature of anything that is, or again, omitting this, to
|
|
look for separate definitions corresponding to each infima species.
|
|
The cases of figure and soul are exactly parallel; for the particulars
|
|
subsumed under the common name in both cases-figures and living
|
|
beings-constitute a series, each successive term of which
|
|
potentially contains its predecessor, e.g. the square the triangle,
|
|
the sensory power the self-nutritive. Hence we must ask in the case of
|
|
each order of living things, What is its soul, i.e. What is the soul
|
|
of plant, animal, man? Why the terms are related in this serial way
|
|
must form the subject of later examination. But the facts are that the
|
|
power of perception is never found apart from the power of
|
|
self-nutrition, while-in plants-the latter is found isolated from
|
|
the former. Again, no sense is found apart from that of touch, while
|
|
touch is found by itself; many animals have neither sight, hearing,
|
|
nor smell. Again, among living things that possess sense some have the
|
|
power of locomotion, some not. Lastly, certain living beings-a small
|
|
minority-possess calculation and thought, for (among mortal beings)
|
|
those which possess calculation have all the other powers above
|
|
mentioned, while the converse does not hold-indeed some live by
|
|
imagination alone, while others have not even imagination. The mind
|
|
that knows with immediate intuition presents a different problem.
|
|
|
|
It is evident that the way to give the most adequate definition of
|
|
soul is to seek in the case of each of its forms for the most
|
|
appropriate definition.
|
|
|
|
4
|
|
|
|
It is necessary for the student of these forms of soul first to find
|
|
a definition of each, expressive of what it is, and then to
|
|
investigate its derivative properties, &c. But if we are to express
|
|
what each is, viz. what the thinking power is, or the perceptive, or
|
|
the nutritive, we must go farther back and first give an account of
|
|
thinking or perceiving, for in the order of investigation the question
|
|
of what an agent does precedes the question, what enables it to do
|
|
what it does. If this is correct, we must on the same ground go yet
|
|
another step farther back and have some clear view of the objects of
|
|
each; thus we must start with these objects, e.g. with food, with what
|
|
is perceptible, or with what is intelligible.
|
|
|
|
It follows that first of all we must treat of nutrition and
|
|
reproduction, for the nutritive soul is found along with all the
|
|
others and is the most primitive and widely distributed power of soul,
|
|
being indeed that one in virtue of which all are said to have life.
|
|
The acts in which it manifests itself are reproduction and the use
|
|
of food-reproduction, I say, because for any living thing that has
|
|
reached its normal development and which is unmutilated, and whose
|
|
mode of generation is not spontaneous, the most natural act is the
|
|
production of another like itself, an animal producing an animal, a
|
|
plant a plant, in order that, as far as its nature allows, it may
|
|
partake in the eternal and divine. That is the goal towards which
|
|
all things strive, that for the sake of which they do whatsoever their
|
|
nature renders possible. The phrase 'for the sake of which' is
|
|
ambiguous; it may mean either (a) the end to achieve which, or (b) the
|
|
being in whose interest, the act is done. Since then no living thing
|
|
is able to partake in what is eternal and divine by uninterrupted
|
|
continuance (for nothing perishable can for ever remain one and the
|
|
same), it tries to achieve that end in the only way possible to it,
|
|
and success is possible in varying degrees; so it remains not indeed
|
|
as the self-same individual but continues its existence in something
|
|
like itself-not numerically but specifically one.
|
|
|
|
The soul is the cause or source of the living body. The terms
|
|
cause and source have many senses. But the soul is the cause of its
|
|
body alike in all three senses which we explicitly recognize. It is
|
|
(a) the source or origin of movement, it is (b) the end, it is (c) the
|
|
essence of the whole living body.
|
|
|
|
That it is the last, is clear; for in everything the essence is
|
|
identical with the ground of its being, and here, in the case of
|
|
living things, their being is to live, and of their being and their
|
|
living the soul in them is the cause or source. Further, the actuality
|
|
of whatever is potential is identical with its formulable essence.
|
|
|
|
It is manifest that the soul is also the final cause of its body.
|
|
For Nature, like mind, always does whatever it does for the sake of
|
|
something, which something is its end. To that something corresponds
|
|
in the case of animals the soul and in this it follows the order of
|
|
nature; all natural bodies are organs of the soul. This is true of
|
|
those that enter into the constitution of plants as well as of those
|
|
which enter into that of animals. This shows that that the sake of
|
|
which they are is soul. We must here recall the two senses of 'that
|
|
for the sake of which', viz. (a) the end to achieve which, and (b) the
|
|
being in whose interest, anything is or is done.
|
|
|
|
We must maintain, further, that the soul is also the cause of the
|
|
living body as the original source of local movement. The power of
|
|
locomotion is not found, however, in all living things. But change
|
|
of quality and change of quantity are also due to the soul.
|
|
Sensation is held to be a qualitative alteration, and nothing except
|
|
what has soul in it is capable of sensation. The same holds of the
|
|
quantitative changes which constitute growth and decay; nothing
|
|
grows or decays naturally except what feeds itself, and nothing
|
|
feeds itself except what has a share of soul in it.
|
|
|
|
Empedocles is wrong in adding that growth in plants is to be
|
|
explained, the downward rooting by the natural tendency of earth to
|
|
travel downwards, and the upward branching by the similar natural
|
|
tendency of fire to travel upwards. For he misinterprets up and
|
|
down; up and down are not for all things what they are for the whole
|
|
Cosmos: if we are to distinguish and identify organs according to
|
|
their functions, the roots of plants are analogous to the head in
|
|
animals. Further, we must ask what is the force that holds together
|
|
the earth and the fire which tend to travel in contrary directions; if
|
|
there is no counteracting force, they will be torn asunder; if there
|
|
is, this must be the soul and the cause of nutrition and growth. By
|
|
some the element of fire is held to be the cause of nutrition and
|
|
growth, for it alone of the primary bodies or elements is observed
|
|
to feed and increase itself. Hence the suggestion that in both
|
|
plants and animals it is it which is the operative force. A concurrent
|
|
cause in a sense it certainly is, but not the principal cause, that is
|
|
rather the soul; for while the growth of fire goes on without limit so
|
|
long as there is a supply of fuel, in the case of all complex wholes
|
|
formed in the course of nature there is a limit or ratio which
|
|
determines their size and increase, and limit and ratio are marks of
|
|
soul but not of fire, and belong to the side of formulable essence
|
|
rather than that of matter.
|
|
|
|
Nutrition and reproduction are due to one and the same psychic
|
|
power. It is necessary first to give precision to our account of food,
|
|
for it is by this function of absorbing food that this psychic power
|
|
is distinguished from all the others. The current view is that what
|
|
serves as food to a living thing is what is contrary to it-not that in
|
|
every pair of contraries each is food to the other: to be food a
|
|
contrary must not only be transformable into the other and vice versa,
|
|
it must also in so doing increase the bulk of the other. Many a
|
|
contrary is transformed into its other and vice versa, where neither
|
|
is even a quantum and so cannot increase in bulk, e.g. an invalid into
|
|
a healthy subject. It is clear that not even those contraries which
|
|
satisfy both the conditions mentioned above are food to one another in
|
|
precisely the same sense; water may be said to feed fire, but not fire
|
|
water. Where the members of the pair are elementary bodies only one of
|
|
the contraries, it would appear, can be said to feed the other. But
|
|
there is a difficulty here. One set of thinkers assert that like
|
|
fed, as well as increased in amount, by like. Another set, as we
|
|
have said, maintain the very reverse, viz. that what feeds and what is
|
|
fed are contrary to one another; like, they argue, is incapable of
|
|
being affected by like; but food is changed in the process of
|
|
digestion, and change is always to what is opposite or to what is
|
|
intermediate. Further, food is acted upon by what is nourished by
|
|
it, not the other way round, as timber is worked by a carpenter and
|
|
not conversely; there is a change in the carpenter but it is merely
|
|
a change from not-working to working. In answering this problem it
|
|
makes all the difference whether we mean by 'the food' the
|
|
'finished' or the 'raw' product. If we use the word food of both, viz.
|
|
of the completely undigested and the completely digested matter, we
|
|
can justify both the rival accounts of it; taking food in the sense of
|
|
undigested matter, it is the contrary of what is fed by it, taking
|
|
it as digested it is like what is fed by it. Consequently it is
|
|
clear that in a certain sense we may say that both parties are
|
|
right, both wrong.
|
|
|
|
Since nothing except what is alive can be fed, what is fed is the
|
|
besouled body and just because it has soul in it. Hence food is
|
|
essentially related to what has soul in it. Food has a power which
|
|
is other than the power to increase the bulk of what is fed by it;
|
|
so far forth as what has soul in it is a quantum, food may increase
|
|
its quantity, but it is only so far as what has soul in it is a
|
|
'this-somewhat' or substance that food acts as food; in that case it
|
|
maintains the being of what is fed, and that continues to be what it
|
|
is so long as the process of nutrition continues. Further, it is the
|
|
agent in generation, i.e. not the generation of the individual fed but
|
|
the reproduction of another like it; the substance of the individual
|
|
fed is already in existence; the existence of no substance is a
|
|
self-generation but only a self-maintenance.
|
|
|
|
Hence the psychic power which we are now studying may be described
|
|
as that which tends to maintain whatever has this power in it of
|
|
continuing such as it was, and food helps it to do its work. That is
|
|
why, if deprived of food, it must cease to be.
|
|
|
|
The process of nutrition involves three factors, (a) what is fed,
|
|
(b) that wherewith it is fed, (c) what does the feeding; of these
|
|
(c) is the first soul, (a) the body which has that soul in it, (b) the
|
|
food. But since it is right to call things after the ends they
|
|
realize, and the end of this soul is to generate another being like
|
|
that in which it is, the first soul ought to be named the reproductive
|
|
soul. The expression (b) 'wherewith it is fed' is ambiguous just as is
|
|
the expression 'wherewith the ship is steered'; that may mean either
|
|
(i) the hand or (ii) the rudder, i.e. either (i) what is moved and
|
|
sets in movement, or (ii) what is merely moved. We can apply this
|
|
analogy here if we recall that all food must be capable of being
|
|
digested, and that what produces digestion is warmth; that is why
|
|
everything that has soul in it possesses warmth.
|
|
|
|
We have now given an outline account of the nature of food;
|
|
further details must be given in the appropriate place.
|
|
|
|
5
|
|
|
|
Having made these distinctions let us now speak of sensation in
|
|
the widest sense. Sensation depends, as we have said, on a process
|
|
of movement or affection from without, for it is held to be some
|
|
sort of change of quality. Now some thinkers assert that like is
|
|
affected only by like; in what sense this is possible and in what
|
|
sense impossible, we have explained in our general discussion of
|
|
acting and being acted upon.
|
|
|
|
Here arises a problem: why do we not perceive the senses
|
|
themselves as well as the external objects of sense, or why without
|
|
the stimulation of external objects do they not produce sensation,
|
|
seeing that they contain in themselves fire, earth, and all the
|
|
other elements, which are the direct or indirect objects is so of
|
|
sense? It is clear that what is sensitive is only potentially, not
|
|
actually. The power of sense is parallel to what is combustible, for
|
|
that never ignites itself spontaneously, but requires an agent which
|
|
has the power of starting ignition; otherwise it could have set itself
|
|
on fire, and would not have needed actual fire to set it ablaze.
|
|
|
|
In reply we must recall that we use the word 'perceive' in two ways,
|
|
for we say (a) that what has the power to hear or see, 'sees' or
|
|
'hears', even though it is at the moment asleep, and also (b) that
|
|
what is actually seeing or hearing, 'sees' or 'hears'. Hence 'sense'
|
|
too must have two meanings, sense potential, and sense actual.
|
|
Similarly 'to be a sentient' means either (a) to have a certain
|
|
power or (b) to manifest a certain activity. To begin with, for a
|
|
time, let us speak as if there were no difference between (i) being
|
|
moved or affected, and (ii) being active, for movement is a kind of
|
|
activity-an imperfect kind, as has elsewhere been explained.
|
|
Everything that is acted upon or moved is acted upon by an agent which
|
|
is actually at work. Hence it is that in one sense, as has already
|
|
been stated, what acts and what is acted upon are like, in another
|
|
unlike, i.e. prior to and during the change the two factors are
|
|
unlike, after it like.
|
|
|
|
But we must now distinguish not only between what is potential and
|
|
what is actual but also different senses in which things can be said
|
|
to be potential or actual; up to now we have been speaking as if
|
|
each of these phrases had only one sense. We can speak of something as
|
|
'a knower' either (a) as when we say that man is a knower, meaning
|
|
that man falls within the class of beings that know or have knowledge,
|
|
or (b) as when we are speaking of a man who possesses a knowledge of
|
|
grammar; each of these is so called as having in him a certain
|
|
potentiality, but there is a difference between their respective
|
|
potentialities, the one (a) being a potential knower, because his kind
|
|
or matter is such and such, the other (b), because he can in the
|
|
absence of any external counteracting cause realize his knowledge in
|
|
actual knowing at will. This implies a third meaning of 'a knower'
|
|
(c), one who is already realizing his knowledge-he is a knower in
|
|
actuality and in the most proper sense is knowing, e.g. this A. Both
|
|
the former are potential knowers, who realize their respective
|
|
potentialities, the one (a) by change of quality, i.e. repeated
|
|
transitions from one state to its opposite under instruction, the
|
|
other (b) by the transition from the inactive possession of sense or
|
|
grammar to their active exercise. The two kinds of transition are
|
|
distinct.
|
|
|
|
Also the expression 'to be acted upon' has more than one meaning; it
|
|
may mean either (a) the extinction of one of two contraries by the
|
|
other, or (b) the maintenance of what is potential by the agency of
|
|
what is actual and already like what is acted upon, with such likeness
|
|
as is compatible with one's being actual and the other potential.
|
|
For what possesses knowledge becomes an actual knower by a
|
|
transition which is either not an alteration of it at all (being in
|
|
reality a development into its true self or actuality) or at least
|
|
an alteration in a quite different sense from the usual meaning.
|
|
|
|
Hence it is wrong to speak of a wise man as being 'altered' when
|
|
he uses his wisdom, just as it would be absurd to speak of a builder
|
|
as being altered when he is using his skill in building a house.
|
|
|
|
What in the case of knowing or understanding leads from potentiality
|
|
to actuality ought not to be called teaching but something else.
|
|
That which starting with the power to know learns or acquires
|
|
knowledge through the agency of one who actually knows and has the
|
|
power of teaching either (a) ought not to be said 'to be acted upon'
|
|
at all or (b) we must recognize two senses of alteration, viz. (i) the
|
|
substitution of one quality for another, the first being the
|
|
contrary of the second, or (ii) the development of an existent quality
|
|
from potentiality in the direction of fixity or nature.
|
|
|
|
In the case of what is to possess sense, the first transition is due
|
|
to the action of the male parent and takes place before birth so
|
|
that at birth the living thing is, in respect of sensation, at the
|
|
stage which corresponds to the possession of knowledge. Actual
|
|
sensation corresponds to the stage of the exercise of knowledge. But
|
|
between the two cases compared there is a difference; the objects that
|
|
excite the sensory powers to activity, the seen, the heard, &c., are
|
|
outside. The ground of this difference is that what actual sensation
|
|
apprehends is individuals, while what knowledge apprehends is
|
|
universals, and these are in a sense within the soul. That is why a
|
|
man can exercise his knowledge when he wishes, but his sensation
|
|
does not depend upon himself a sensible object must be there. A
|
|
similar statement must be made about our knowledge of what is
|
|
sensible-on the same ground, viz. that the sensible objects are
|
|
individual and external.
|
|
|
|
A later more appropriate occasion may be found thoroughly to clear
|
|
up all this. At present it must be enough to recognize the
|
|
distinctions already drawn; a thing may be said to be potential in
|
|
either of two senses, (a) in the sense in which we might say of a
|
|
boy that he may become a general or (b) in the sense in which we might
|
|
say the same of an adult, and there are two corresponding senses of
|
|
the term 'a potential sentient'. There are no separate names for the
|
|
two stages of potentiality; we have pointed out that they are
|
|
different and how they are different. We cannot help using the
|
|
incorrect terms 'being acted upon or altered' of the two transitions
|
|
involved. As we have said, has the power of sensation is potentially
|
|
like what the perceived object is actually; that is, while at the
|
|
beginning of the process of its being acted upon the two interacting
|
|
factors are dissimilar, at the end the one acted upon is assimilated
|
|
to the other and is identical in quality with it.
|
|
|
|
6
|
|
|
|
In dealing with each of the senses we shall have first to speak of
|
|
the objects which are perceptible by each. The term 'object of
|
|
sense' covers three kinds of objects, two kinds of which are, in our
|
|
language, directly perceptible, while the remaining one is only
|
|
incidentally perceptible. Of the first two kinds one (a) consists of
|
|
what is perceptible by a single sense, the other (b) of what is
|
|
perceptible by any and all of the senses. I call by the name of
|
|
special object of this or that sense that which cannot be perceived by
|
|
any other sense than that one and in respect of which no error is
|
|
possible; in this sense colour is the special object of sight, sound
|
|
of hearing, flavour of taste. Touch, indeed, discriminates more than
|
|
one set of different qualities. Each sense has one kind of object
|
|
which it discerns, and never errs in reporting that what is before
|
|
it is colour or sound (though it may err as to what it is that is
|
|
coloured or where that is, or what it is that is sounding or where
|
|
that is.) Such objects are what we propose to call the special objects
|
|
of this or that sense.
|
|
|
|
'Common sensibles' are movement, rest, number, figure, magnitude;
|
|
these are not peculiar to any one sense, but are common to all.
|
|
There are at any rate certain kinds of movement which are
|
|
perceptible both by touch and by sight.
|
|
|
|
We speak of an incidental object of sense where e.g. the white
|
|
object which we see is the son of Diares; here because 'being the
|
|
son of Diares' is incidental to the directly visible white patch we
|
|
speak of the son of Diares as being (incidentally) perceived or seen
|
|
by us. Because this is only incidentally an object of sense, it in
|
|
no way as such affects the senses. Of the two former kinds, both of
|
|
which are in their own nature perceptible by sense, the first
|
|
kind-that of special objects of the several senses-constitute the
|
|
objects of sense in the strictest sense of the term and it is to
|
|
them that in the nature of things the structure of each several
|
|
sense is adapted.
|
|
|
|
7
|
|
|
|
The object of sight is the visible, and what is visible is (a)
|
|
colour and (b) a certain kind of object which can be described in
|
|
words but which has no single name; what we mean by (b) will be
|
|
abundantly clear as we proceed. Whatever is visible is colour and
|
|
colour is what lies upon what is in its own nature visible; 'in its
|
|
own nature' here means not that visibility is involved in the
|
|
definition of what thus underlies colour, but that that substratum
|
|
contains in itself the cause of visibility. Every colour has in it the
|
|
power to set in movement what is actually transparent; that power
|
|
constitutes its very nature. That is why it is not visible except with
|
|
the help of light; it is only in light that the colour of a thing is
|
|
seen. Hence our first task is to explain what light is.
|
|
|
|
Now there clearly is something which is transparent, and by
|
|
'transparent' I mean what is visible, and yet not visible in itself,
|
|
but rather owing its visibility to the colour of something else; of
|
|
this character are air, water, and many solid bodies. Neither air
|
|
nor water is transparent because it is air or water; they are
|
|
transparent because each of them has contained in it a certain
|
|
substance which is the same in both and is also found in the eternal
|
|
body which constitutes the uppermost shell of the physical Cosmos.
|
|
Of this substance light is the activity-the activity of what is
|
|
transparent so far forth as it has in it the determinate power of
|
|
becoming transparent; where this power is present, there is also the
|
|
potentiality of the contrary, viz. darkness. Light is as it were the
|
|
proper colour of what is transparent, and exists whenever the
|
|
potentially transparent is excited to actuality by the influence of
|
|
fire or something resembling 'the uppermost body'; for fire too
|
|
contains something which is one and the same with the substance in
|
|
question.
|
|
|
|
We have now explained what the transparent is and what light is;
|
|
light is neither fire nor any kind whatsoever of body nor an efflux
|
|
from any kind of body (if it were, it would again itself be a kind
|
|
of body)-it is the presence of fire or something resembling fire in
|
|
what is transparent. It is certainly not a body, for two bodies cannot
|
|
be present in the same place. The opposite of light is darkness;
|
|
darkness is the absence from what is transparent of the
|
|
corresponding positive state above characterized; clearly therefore,
|
|
light is just the presence of that.
|
|
|
|
Empedocles (and with him all others who used the same forms of
|
|
expression) was wrong in speaking of light as 'travelling' or being at
|
|
a given moment between the earth and its envelope, its movement
|
|
being unobservable by us; that view is contrary both to the clear
|
|
evidence of argument and to the observed facts; if the distance
|
|
traversed were short, the movement might have been unobservable, but
|
|
where the distance is from extreme East to extreme West, the draught
|
|
upon our powers of belief is too great.
|
|
|
|
What is capable of taking on colour is what in itself is colourless,
|
|
as what can take on sound is what is soundless; what is colourless
|
|
includes (a) what is transparent and (b) what is invisible or scarcely
|
|
visible, i.e. what is 'dark'. The latter (b) is the same as what is
|
|
transparent, when it is potentially, not of course when it is actually
|
|
transparent; it is the same substance which is now darkness, now
|
|
light.
|
|
|
|
Not everything that is visible depends upon light for its
|
|
visibility. This is only true of the 'proper' colour of things. Some
|
|
objects of sight which in light are invisible, in darkness stimulate
|
|
the sense; that is, things that appear fiery or shining. This class of
|
|
objects has no simple common name, but instances of it are fungi,
|
|
flesh, heads, scales, and eyes of fish. In none of these is what is
|
|
seen their own proper' colour. Why we see these at all is another
|
|
question. At present what is obvious is that what is seen in light
|
|
is always colour. That is why without the help of light colour remains
|
|
invisible. Its being colour at all means precisely its having in it
|
|
the power to set in movement what is already actually transparent,
|
|
and, as we have seen, the actuality of what is transparent is just
|
|
light.
|
|
|
|
The following experiment makes the necessity of a medium clear. If
|
|
what has colour is placed in immediate contact with the eye, it cannot
|
|
be seen. Colour sets in movement not the sense organ but what is
|
|
transparent, e.g. the air, and that, extending continuously from the
|
|
object to the organ, sets the latter in movement. Democritus
|
|
misrepresents the facts when he expresses the opinion that if the
|
|
interspace were empty one could distinctly see an ant on the vault
|
|
of the sky; that is an impossibility. Seeing is due to an affection or
|
|
change of what has the perceptive faculty, and it cannot be affected
|
|
by the seen colour itself; it remains that it must be affected by what
|
|
comes between. Hence it is indispensable that there be something in
|
|
between-if there were nothing, so far from seeing with greater
|
|
distinctness, we should see nothing at all.
|
|
|
|
We have now explained the cause why colour cannot be seen
|
|
otherwise than in light. Fire on the other hand is seen both in
|
|
darkness and in light; this double possibility follows necessarily
|
|
from our theory, for it is just fire that makes what is potentially
|
|
transparent actually transparent.
|
|
|
|
The same account holds also of sound and smell; if the object of
|
|
either of these senses is in immediate contact with the organ no
|
|
sensation is produced. In both cases the object sets in movement
|
|
only what lies between, and this in turn sets the organ in movement:
|
|
if what sounds or smells is brought into immediate contact with the
|
|
organ, no sensation will be produced. The same, in spite of all
|
|
appearances, applies also to touch and taste; why there is this
|
|
apparent difference will be clear later. What comes between in the
|
|
case of sounds is air; the corresponding medium in the case of smell
|
|
has no name. But, corresponding to what is transparent in the case
|
|
of colour, there is a quality found both in air and water, which
|
|
serves as a medium for what has smell-I say 'in water' because animals
|
|
that live in water as well as those that live on land seem to
|
|
possess the sense of smell, and 'in air' because man and all other
|
|
land animals that breathe, perceive smells only when they breathe
|
|
air in. The explanation of this too will be given later.
|
|
|
|
8
|
|
|
|
Now let us, to begin with, make certain distinctions about sound and
|
|
hearing.
|
|
|
|
Sound may mean either of two things (a) actual, and (b) potential,
|
|
sound. There are certain things which, as we say, 'have no sound',
|
|
e.g. sponges or wool, others which have, e.g. bronze and in general
|
|
all things which are smooth and solid-the latter are said to have a
|
|
sound because they can make a sound, i.e. can generate actual sound
|
|
between themselves and the organ of hearing.
|
|
|
|
Actual sound requires for its occurrence (i, ii) two such bodies and
|
|
(iii) a space between them; for it is generated by an impact. Hence it
|
|
is impossible for one body only to generate a sound-there must be a
|
|
body impinging and a body impinged upon; what sounds does so by
|
|
striking against something else, and this is impossible without a
|
|
movement from place to place.
|
|
|
|
As we have said, not all bodies can by impact on one another produce
|
|
sound; impact on wool makes no sound, while the impact on bronze or
|
|
any body which is smooth and hollow does. Bronze gives out a sound
|
|
when struck because it is smooth; bodies which are hollow owing to
|
|
reflection repeat the original impact over and over again, the body
|
|
originally set in movement being unable to escape from the concavity.
|
|
|
|
Further, we must remark that sound is heard both in air and in
|
|
water, though less distinctly in the latter. Yet neither air nor water
|
|
is the principal cause of sound. What is required for the production
|
|
of sound is an impact of two solids against one another and against
|
|
the air. The latter condition is satisfied when the air impinged
|
|
upon does not retreat before the blow, i.e. is not dissipated by it.
|
|
|
|
That is why it must be struck with a sudden sharp blow, if it is
|
|
to sound-the movement of the whip must outrun the dispersion of the
|
|
air, just as one might get in a stroke at a heap or whirl of sand as
|
|
it was traveling rapidly past.
|
|
|
|
An echo occurs, when, a mass of air having been unified, bounded,
|
|
and prevented from dissipation by the containing walls of a vessel,
|
|
the air originally struck by the impinging body and set in movement by
|
|
it rebounds from this mass of air like a ball from a wall. It is
|
|
probable that in all generation of sound echo takes place, though it
|
|
is frequently only indistinctly heard. What happens here must be
|
|
analogous to what happens in the case of light; light is always
|
|
reflected-otherwise it would not be diffused and outside what was
|
|
directly illuminated by the sun there would be blank darkness; but
|
|
this reflected light is not always strong enough, as it is when it
|
|
is reflected from water, bronze, and other smooth bodies, to cast a
|
|
shadow, which is the distinguishing mark by which we recognize light.
|
|
|
|
It is rightly said that an empty space plays the chief part in the
|
|
production of hearing, for what people mean by 'the vacuum' is the
|
|
air, which is what causes hearing, when that air is set in movement as
|
|
one continuous mass; but owing to its friability it emits no sound,
|
|
being dissipated by impinging upon any surface which is not smooth.
|
|
When the surface on which it impinges is quite smooth, what is
|
|
produced by the original impact is a united mass, a result due to
|
|
the smoothness of the surface with which the air is in contact at
|
|
the other end.
|
|
|
|
What has the power of producing sound is what has the power of
|
|
setting in movement a single mass of air which is continuous from
|
|
the impinging body up to the organ of hearing. The organ of hearing is
|
|
physically united with air, and because it is in air, the air inside
|
|
is moved concurrently with the air outside. Hence animals do not
|
|
hear with all parts of their bodies, nor do all parts admit of the
|
|
entrance of air; for even the part which can be moved and can sound
|
|
has not air everywhere in it. Air in itself is, owing to its
|
|
friability, quite soundless; only when its dissipation is prevented is
|
|
its movement sound. The air in the ear is built into a chamber just to
|
|
prevent this dissipating movement, in order that the animal may
|
|
accurately apprehend all varieties of the movements of the air
|
|
outside. That is why we hear also in water, viz. because the water
|
|
cannot get into the air chamber or even, owing to the spirals, into
|
|
the outer ear. If this does happen, hearing ceases, as it also does if
|
|
the tympanic membrane is damaged, just as sight ceases if the membrane
|
|
covering the pupil is damaged. It is also a test of deafness whether
|
|
the ear does or does not reverberate like a horn; the air inside the
|
|
ear has always a movement of its own, but the sound we hear is
|
|
always the sounding of something else, not of the organ itself. That
|
|
is why we say that we hear with what is empty and echoes, viz. because
|
|
what we hear with is a chamber which contains a bounded mass of air.
|
|
|
|
Which is it that 'sounds', the striking body or the struck? Is not
|
|
the answer 'it is both, but each in a different way'? Sound is a
|
|
movement of what can rebound from a smooth surface when struck against
|
|
it. As we have explained' not everything sounds when it strikes or
|
|
is struck, e.g. if one needle is struck against another, neither emits
|
|
any sound. In order, therefore, that sound may be generated, what is
|
|
struck must be smooth, to enable the air to rebound and be shaken
|
|
off from it in one piece.
|
|
|
|
The distinctions between different sounding bodies show themselves
|
|
only in actual sound; as without the help of light colours remain
|
|
invisible, so without the help of actual sound the distinctions
|
|
between acute and grave sounds remain inaudible. Acute and grave are
|
|
here metaphors, transferred from their proper sphere, viz. that of
|
|
touch, where they mean respectively (a) what moves the sense much in a
|
|
short time, (b) what moves the sense little in a long time. Not that
|
|
what is sharp really moves fast, and what is grave, slowly, but that
|
|
the difference in the qualities of the one and the other movement is
|
|
due to their respective speeds. There seems to be a sort of
|
|
parallelism between what is acute or grave to hearing and what is
|
|
sharp or blunt to touch; what is sharp as it were stabs, while what is
|
|
blunt pushes, the one producing its effect in a short, the other in
|
|
a long time, so that the one is quick, the other slow.
|
|
|
|
Let the foregoing suffice as an analysis of sound. Voice is a kind
|
|
of sound characteristic of what has soul in it; nothing that is
|
|
without soul utters voice, it being only by a metaphor that we speak
|
|
of the voice of the flute or the lyre or generally of what (being
|
|
without soul) possesses the power of producing a succession of notes
|
|
which differ in length and pitch and timbre. The metaphor is based
|
|
on the fact that all these differences are found also in voice. Many
|
|
animals are voiceless, e.g. all non-sanuineous animals and among
|
|
sanguineous animals fish. This is just what we should expect, since
|
|
voice is a certain movement of air. The fish, like those in the
|
|
Achelous, which are said to have voice, really make the sounds with
|
|
their gills or some similar organ. Voice is the sound made by an
|
|
animal, and that with a special organ. As we saw, everything that
|
|
makes a sound does so by the impact of something (a) against something
|
|
else, (b) across a space, (c) filled with air; hence it is only to
|
|
be expected that no animals utter voice except those which take in
|
|
air. Once air is inbreathed, Nature uses it for two different
|
|
purposes, as the tongue is used both for tasting and for articulating;
|
|
in that case of the two functions tasting is necessary for the
|
|
animal's existence (hence it is found more widely distributed),
|
|
while articulate speech is a luxury subserving its possessor's
|
|
well-being; similarly in the former case Nature employs the breath
|
|
both as an indispensable means to the regulation of the inner
|
|
temperature of the living body and also as the matter of articulate
|
|
voice, in the interests of its possessor's well-being. Why its
|
|
former use is indispensable must be discussed elsewhere.
|
|
|
|
The organ of respiration is the windpipe, and the organ to which
|
|
this is related as means to end is the lungs. The latter is the part
|
|
of the body by which the temperature of land animals is raised above
|
|
that of all others. But what primarily requires the air drawn in by
|
|
respiration is not only this but the region surrounding the heart.
|
|
That is why when animals breathe the air must penetrate inwards.
|
|
|
|
Voice then is the impact of the inbreathed air against the
|
|
'windpipe', and the agent that produces the impact is the soul
|
|
resident in these parts of the body. Not every sound, as we said, made
|
|
by an animal is voice (even with the tongue we may merely make a sound
|
|
which is not voice, or without the tongue as in coughing); what
|
|
produces the impact must have soul in it and must be accompanied by an
|
|
act of imagination, for voice is a sound with a meaning, and is not
|
|
merely the result of any impact of the breath as in coughing; in voice
|
|
the breath in the windpipe is used as an instrument to knock with
|
|
against the walls of the windpipe. This is confirmed by our
|
|
inability to speak when we are breathing either out or in-we can
|
|
only do so by holding our breath; we make the movements with the
|
|
breath so checked. It is clear also why fish are voiceless; they
|
|
have no windpipe. And they have no windpipe because they do not
|
|
breathe or take in air. Why they do not is a question belonging to
|
|
another inquiry.
|
|
|
|
9
|
|
|
|
Smell and its object are much less easy to determine than what we
|
|
have hitherto discussed; the distinguishing characteristic of the
|
|
object of smell is less obvious than those of sound or colour. The
|
|
ground of this is that our power of smell is less discriminating and
|
|
in general inferior to that of many species of animals; men have a
|
|
poor sense of smell and our apprehension of its proper objects is
|
|
inseparably bound up with and so confused by pleasure and pain,
|
|
which shows that in us the organ is inaccurate. It is probable that
|
|
there is a parallel failure in the perception of colour by animals
|
|
that have hard eyes: probably they discriminate differences of
|
|
colour only by the presence or absence of what excites fear, and
|
|
that it is thus that human beings distinguish smells. It seems that
|
|
there is an analogy between smell and taste, and that the species of
|
|
tastes run parallel to those of smells-the only difference being
|
|
that our sense of taste is more discriminating than our sense of
|
|
smell, because the former is a modification of touch, which reaches in
|
|
man the maximum of discriminative accuracy. While in respect of all
|
|
the other senses we fall below many species of animals, in respect
|
|
of touch we far excel all other species in exactness of
|
|
discrimination. That is why man is the most intelligent of all
|
|
animals. This is confirmed by the fact that it is to differences in
|
|
the organ of touch and to nothing else that the differences between
|
|
man and man in respect of natural endowment are due; men whose flesh
|
|
is hard are ill-endowed by nature, men whose flesh is soft,
|
|
wellendowed.
|
|
|
|
As flavours may be divided into (a) sweet, (b) bitter, so with
|
|
smells. In some things the flavour and the smell have the same
|
|
quality, i.e. both are sweet or both bitter, in others they diverge.
|
|
Similarly a smell, like a flavour, may be pungent, astringent, acid,
|
|
or succulent. But, as we said, because smells are much less easy to
|
|
discriminate than flavours, the names of these varieties are applied
|
|
to smells only metaphorically; for example 'sweet' is extended from
|
|
the taste to the smell of saffron or honey, 'pungent' to that of
|
|
thyme, and so on.
|
|
|
|
In the same sense in which hearing has for its object both the
|
|
audible and the inaudible, sight both the visible and the invisible,
|
|
smell has for its object both the odorous and the inodorous.
|
|
'Inodorous' may be either (a) what has no smell at all, or (b) what
|
|
has a small or feeble smell. The same ambiguity lurks in the word
|
|
'tasteless'.
|
|
|
|
Smelling, like the operation of the senses previously examined,
|
|
takes place through a medium, i.e. through air or water-I add water,
|
|
because water-animals too (both sanguineous and non-sanguineous)
|
|
seem to smell just as much as land-animals; at any rate some of them
|
|
make directly for their food from a distance if it has any scent. That
|
|
is why the following facts constitute a problem for us. All animals
|
|
smell in the same way, but man smells only when he inhales; if he
|
|
exhales or holds his breath, he ceases to smell, no difference being
|
|
made whether the odorous object is distant or near, or even placed
|
|
inside the nose and actually on the wall of the nostril; it is a
|
|
disability common to all the senses not to perceive what is in
|
|
immediate contact with the organ of sense, but our failure to
|
|
apprehend what is odorous without the help of inhalation is peculiar
|
|
(the fact is obvious on making the experiment). Now since bloodless
|
|
animals do not breathe, they must, it might be argued, have some novel
|
|
sense not reckoned among the usual five. Our reply must be that this
|
|
is impossible, since it is scent that is perceived; a sense that
|
|
apprehends what is odorous and what has a good or bad odour cannot
|
|
be anything but smell. Further, they are observed to be
|
|
deleteriously effected by the same strong odours as man is, e.g.
|
|
bitumen, sulphur, and the like. These animals must be able to smell
|
|
without being able to breathe. The probable explanation is that in man
|
|
the organ of smell has a certain superiority over that in all other
|
|
animals just as his eyes have over those of hard-eyed animals. Man's
|
|
eyes have in the eyelids a kind of shelter or envelope, which must
|
|
be shifted or drawn back in order that we may see, while hardeyed
|
|
animals have nothing of the kind, but at once see whatever presents
|
|
itself in the transparent medium. Similarly in certain species of
|
|
animals the organ of smell is like the eye of hard-eyed animals,
|
|
uncurtained, while in others which take in air it probably has a
|
|
curtain over it, which is drawn back in inhalation, owing to the
|
|
dilating of the veins or pores. That explains also why such animals
|
|
cannot smell under water; to smell they must first inhale, and that
|
|
they cannot do under water.
|
|
|
|
Smells come from what is dry as flavours from what is moist.
|
|
Consequently the organ of smell is potentially dry.
|
|
|
|
10
|
|
|
|
What can be tasted is always something that can be touched, and just
|
|
for that reason it cannot be perceived through an interposed foreign
|
|
body, for touch means the absence of any intervening body. Further,
|
|
the flavoured and tasteable body is suspended in a liquid matter,
|
|
and this is tangible. Hence, if we lived in water, we should
|
|
perceive a sweet object introduced into the water, but the water would
|
|
not be the medium through which we perceived; our perception would
|
|
be due to the solution of the sweet substance in what we imbibed, just
|
|
as if it were mixed with some drink. There is no parallel here to
|
|
the perception of colour, which is due neither to any blending of
|
|
anything with anything, nor to any efflux of anything from anything.
|
|
In the case of taste, there is nothing corresponding to the medium
|
|
in the case of the senses previously discussed; but as the object of
|
|
sight is colour, so the object of taste is flavour. But nothing
|
|
excites a perception of flavour without the help of liquid; what
|
|
acts upon the sense of taste must be either actually or potentially
|
|
liquid like what is saline; it must be both (a) itself easily
|
|
dissolved, and (b) capable of dissolving along with itself the tongue.
|
|
Taste apprehends both (a) what has taste and (b) what has no taste, if
|
|
we mean by (b) what has only a slight or feeble flavour or what
|
|
tends to destroy the sense of taste. In this it is exactly parallel to
|
|
sight, which apprehends both what is visible and what is invisible
|
|
(for darkness is invisible and yet is discriminated by sight; so is,
|
|
in a different way, what is over brilliant), and to hearing, which
|
|
apprehends both sound and silence, of which the one is audible and the
|
|
other inaudible, and also over-loud sound. This corresponds in the
|
|
case of hearing to over-bright light in the case of sight. As a
|
|
faint sound is 'inaudible', so in a sense is a loud or violent
|
|
sound. The word 'invisible' and similar privative terms cover not only
|
|
(a) what is simply without some power, but also (b) what is adapted by
|
|
nature to have it but has not it or has it only in a very low
|
|
degree, as when we say that a species of swallow is 'footless' or that
|
|
a variety of fruit is 'stoneless'. So too taste has as its object both
|
|
what can be tasted and the tasteless-the latter in the sense of what
|
|
has little flavour or a bad flavour or one destructive of taste. The
|
|
difference between what is tasteless and what is not seems to rest
|
|
ultimately on that between what is drinkable and what is undrinkable
|
|
both are tasteable, but the latter is bad and tends to destroy
|
|
taste, while the former is the normal stimulus of taste. What is
|
|
drinkable is the common object of both touch and taste.
|
|
|
|
Since what can be tasted is liquid, the organ for its perception
|
|
cannot be either (a) actually liquid or (b) incapable of becoming
|
|
liquid. Tasting means a being affected by what can be tasted as
|
|
such; hence the organ of taste must be liquefied, and so to start with
|
|
must be non-liquid but capable of liquefaction without loss of its
|
|
distinctive nature. This is confirmed by the fact that the tongue
|
|
cannot taste either when it is too dry or when it is too moist; in the
|
|
latter case what occurs is due to a contact with the pre-existent
|
|
moisture in the tongue itself, when after a foretaste of some strong
|
|
flavour we try to taste another flavour; it is in this way that sick
|
|
persons find everything they taste bitter, viz. because, when they
|
|
taste, their tongues are overflowing with bitter moisture.
|
|
|
|
The species of flavour are, as in the case of colour, (a) simple,
|
|
i.e. the two contraries, the sweet and the bitter, (b) secondary, viz.
|
|
(i) on the side of the sweet, the succulent, (ii) on the side of the
|
|
bitter, the saline, (iii) between these come the pungent, the harsh,
|
|
the astringent, and the acid; these pretty well exhaust the
|
|
varieties of flavour. It follows that what has the power of tasting is
|
|
what is potentially of that kind, and that what is tasteable is what
|
|
has the power of making it actually what it itself already is.
|
|
|
|
11
|
|
|
|
Whatever can be said of what is tangible, can be said of touch,
|
|
and vice versa; if touch is not a single sense but a group of
|
|
senses, there must be several kinds of what is tangible. It is a
|
|
problem whether touch is a single sense or a group of senses. It is
|
|
also a problem, what is the organ of touch; is it or is it not the
|
|
flesh (including what in certain animals is homologous with flesh)? On
|
|
the second view, flesh is 'the medium' of touch, the real organ
|
|
being situated farther inward. The problem arises because the field of
|
|
each sense is according to the accepted view determined as the range
|
|
between a single pair of contraries, white and black for sight,
|
|
acute and grave for hearing, bitter and sweet for taste; but in the
|
|
field of what is tangible we find several such pairs, hot cold, dry
|
|
moist, hard soft, &c. This problem finds a partial solution, when it
|
|
is recalled that in the case of the other senses more than one pair of
|
|
contraries are to be met with, e.g. in sound not only acute and
|
|
grave but loud and soft, smooth and rough, &c.; there are similar
|
|
contrasts in the field of colour. Nevertheless we are unable clearly
|
|
to detect in the case of touch what the single subject is which
|
|
underlies the contrasted qualities and corresponds to sound in the
|
|
case of hearing.
|
|
|
|
To the question whether the organ of touch lies inward or not
|
|
(i.e. whether we need look any farther than the flesh), no
|
|
indication in favour of the second answer can be drawn from the fact
|
|
that if the object comes into contact with the flesh it is at once
|
|
perceived. For even under present conditions if the experiment is made
|
|
of making a web and stretching it tight over the flesh, as soon as
|
|
this web is touched the sensation is reported in the same manner as
|
|
before, yet it is clear that the or is gan is not in this membrane. If
|
|
the membrane could be grown on to the flesh, the report would travel
|
|
still quicker. The flesh plays in touch very much the same part as
|
|
would be played in the other senses by an air-envelope growing round
|
|
our body; had we such an envelope attached to us we should have
|
|
supposed that it was by a single organ that we perceived sounds,
|
|
colours, and smells, and we should have taken sight, hearing, and
|
|
smell to be a single sense. But as it is, because that through which
|
|
the different movements are transmitted is not naturally attached to
|
|
our bodies, the difference of the various sense-organs is too plain to
|
|
miss. But in the case of touch the obscurity remains.
|
|
|
|
There must be such a naturally attached 'medium' as flesh, for no
|
|
living body could be constructed of air or water; it must be something
|
|
solid. Consequently it must be composed of earth along with these,
|
|
which is just what flesh and its analogue in animals which have no
|
|
true flesh tend to be. Hence of necessity the medium through which are
|
|
transmitted the manifoldly contrasted tactual qualities must be a body
|
|
naturally attached to the organism. That they are manifold is clear
|
|
when we consider touching with the tongue; we apprehend at the
|
|
tongue all tangible qualities as well as flavour. Suppose all the rest
|
|
of our flesh was, like the tongue, sensitive to flavour, we should
|
|
have identified the sense of taste and the sense of touch; what
|
|
saves us from this identification is the fact that touch and taste are
|
|
not always found together in the same part of the body. The
|
|
following problem might be raised. Let us assume that every body has
|
|
depth, i.e. has three dimensions, and that if two bodies have a
|
|
third body between them they cannot be in contact with one another;
|
|
let us remember that what is liquid is a body and must be or contain
|
|
water, and that if two bodies touch one another under water, their
|
|
touching surfaces cannot be dry, but must have water between, viz. the
|
|
water which wets their bounding surfaces; from all this it follows
|
|
that in water two bodies cannot be in contact with one another. The
|
|
same holds of two bodies in air-air being to bodies in air precisely
|
|
what water is to bodies in water-but the facts are not so evident to
|
|
our observation, because we live in air, just as animals that live
|
|
in water would not notice that the things which touch one another in
|
|
water have wet surfaces. The problem, then, is: does the perception of
|
|
all objects of sense take place in the same way, or does it not,
|
|
e.g. taste and touch requiring contact (as they are commonly thought
|
|
to do), while all other senses perceive over a distance? The
|
|
distinction is unsound; we perceive what is hard or soft, as well as
|
|
the objects of hearing, sight, and smell, through a 'medium', only
|
|
that the latter are perceived over a greater distance than the former;
|
|
that is why the facts escape our notice. For we do perceive everything
|
|
through a medium; but in these cases the fact escapes us. Yet, to
|
|
repeat what we said before, if the medium for touch were a membrane
|
|
separating us from the object without our observing its existence,
|
|
we should be relatively to it in the same condition as we are now to
|
|
air or water in which we are immersed; in their case we fancy we can
|
|
touch objects, nothing coming in between us and them. But there
|
|
remains this difference between what can be touched and what can be
|
|
seen or can sound; in the latter two cases we perceive because the
|
|
medium produces a certain effect upon us, whereas in the perception of
|
|
objects of touch we are affected not by but along with the medium;
|
|
it is as if a man were struck through his shield, where the shock is
|
|
not first given to the shield and passed on to the man, but the
|
|
concussion of both is simultaneous.
|
|
|
|
In general, flesh and the tongue are related to the real organs of
|
|
touch and taste, as air and water are to those of sight, hearing,
|
|
and smell. Hence in neither the one case nor the other can there be
|
|
any perception of an object if it is placed immediately upon the
|
|
organ, e.g. if a white object is placed on the surface of the eye.
|
|
This again shows that what has the power of perceiving the tangible is
|
|
seated inside. Only so would there be a complete analogy with all
|
|
the other senses. In their case if you place the object on the organ
|
|
it is not perceived, here if you place it on the flesh it is
|
|
perceived; therefore flesh is not the organ but the medium of touch.
|
|
|
|
What can be touched are distinctive qualities of body as body; by
|
|
such differences I mean those which characterize the elements, viz,
|
|
hot cold, dry moist, of which we have spoken earlier in our treatise
|
|
on the elements. The organ for the perception of these is that of
|
|
touch-that part of the body in which primarily the sense of touch
|
|
resides. This is that part which is potentially such as its object
|
|
is actually: for all sense-perception is a process of being so
|
|
affected; so that that which makes something such as it itself
|
|
actually is makes the other such because the other is already
|
|
potentially such. That is why when an object of touch is equally hot
|
|
and cold or hard and soft we cannot perceive; what we perceive must
|
|
have a degree of the sensible quality lying beyond the neutral
|
|
point. This implies that the sense itself is a 'mean' between any
|
|
two opposite qualities which determine the field of that sense. It
|
|
is to this that it owes its power of discerning the objects in that
|
|
field. What is 'in the middle' is fitted to discern; relatively to
|
|
either extreme it can put itself in the place of the other. As what is
|
|
to perceive both white and black must, to begin with, be actually
|
|
neither but potentially either (and so with all the other
|
|
sense-organs), so the organ of touch must be neither hot nor cold.
|
|
|
|
Further, as in a sense sight had for its object both what was
|
|
visible and what was invisible (and there was a parallel truth about
|
|
all the other senses discussed), so touch has for its object both what
|
|
is tangible and what is intangible. Here by 'intangible' is meant
|
|
(a) what like air possesses some quality of tangible things in a
|
|
very slight degree and (b) what possesses it in an excessive degree,
|
|
as destructive things do.
|
|
|
|
We have now given an outline account of each of the several senses.
|
|
|
|
12
|
|
|
|
The following results applying to any and every sense may now be
|
|
formulated.
|
|
|
|
(A) By a 'sense' is meant what has the power of receiving into
|
|
itself the sensible forms of things without the matter. This must be
|
|
conceived of as taking place in the way in which a piece of wax
|
|
takes on the impress of a signet-ring without the iron or gold; we say
|
|
that what produces the impression is a signet of bronze or gold, but
|
|
its particular metallic constitution makes no difference: in a similar
|
|
way the sense is affected by what is coloured or flavoured or
|
|
sounding, but it is indifferent what in each case the substance is;
|
|
what alone matters is what quality it has, i.e. in what ratio its
|
|
constituents are combined.
|
|
|
|
(B) By 'an organ of sense' is meant that in which ultimately such
|
|
a power is seated.
|
|
|
|
The sense and its organ are the same in fact, but their essence is
|
|
not the same. What perceives is, of course, a spatial magnitude, but
|
|
we must not admit that either the having the power to perceive or
|
|
the sense itself is a magnitude; what they are is a certain ratio or
|
|
power in a magnitude. This enables us to explain why objects of
|
|
sense which possess one of two opposite sensible qualities in a degree
|
|
largely in excess of the other opposite destroy the organs of sense;
|
|
if the movement set up by an object is too strong for the organ, the
|
|
equipoise of contrary qualities in the organ, which just is its
|
|
sensory power, is disturbed; it is precisely as concord and tone are
|
|
destroyed by too violently twanging the strings of a lyre. This
|
|
explains also why plants cannot perceive. in spite of their having a
|
|
portion of soul in them and obviously being affected by tangible
|
|
objects themselves; for undoubtedly their temperature can be lowered
|
|
or raised. The explanation is that they have no mean of contrary
|
|
qualities, and so no principle in them capable of taking on the
|
|
forms of sensible objects without their matter; in the case of
|
|
plants the affection is an affection by form-and-matter together.
|
|
The problem might be raised: Can what cannot smell be said to be
|
|
affected by smells or what cannot see by colours, and so on? It
|
|
might be said that a smell is just what can be smelt, and if it
|
|
produces any effect it can only be so as to make something smell it,
|
|
and it might be argued that what cannot smell cannot be affected by
|
|
smells and further that what can smell can be affected by it only in
|
|
so far as it has in it the power to smell (similarly with the proper
|
|
objects of all the other senses). Indeed that this is so is made quite
|
|
evident as follows. Light or darkness, sounds and smells leave
|
|
bodies quite unaffected; what does affect bodies is not these but
|
|
the bodies which are their vehicles, e.g. what splits the trunk of a
|
|
tree is not the sound of the thunder but the air which accompanies
|
|
thunder. Yes, but, it may be objected, bodies are affected by what
|
|
is tangible and by flavours. If not, by what are things that are
|
|
without soul affected, i.e. altered in quality? Must we not, then,
|
|
admit that the objects of the other senses also may affect them? Is
|
|
not the true account this, that all bodies are capable of being
|
|
affected by smells and sounds, but that some on being acted upon,
|
|
having no boundaries of their own, disintegrate, as in the instance of
|
|
air, which does become odorous, showing that some effect is produced
|
|
on it by what is odorous? But smelling is more than such an
|
|
affection by what is odorous-what more? Is not the answer that,
|
|
while the air owing to the momentary duration of the action upon it of
|
|
what is odorous does itself become perceptible to the sense of
|
|
smell, smelling is an observing of the result produced?
|
|
|
|
Book III
|
|
|
|
1
|
|
|
|
THAT there is no sixth sense in addition to the five
|
|
enumerated-sight, hearing, smell, taste, touch-may be established by
|
|
the following considerations:
|
|
|
|
If we have actually sensation of everything of which touch can
|
|
give us sensation (for all the qualities of the tangible qua
|
|
tangible are perceived by us through touch); and if absence of a sense
|
|
necessarily involves absence of a sense-organ; and if (1) all
|
|
objects that we perceive by immediate contact with them are
|
|
perceptible by touch, which sense we actually possess, and (2) all
|
|
objects that we perceive through media, i.e. without immediate
|
|
contact, are perceptible by or through the simple elements, e.g. air
|
|
and water (and this is so arranged that (a) if more than one kind of
|
|
sensible object is perceivable through a single medium, the
|
|
possessor of a sense-organ homogeneous with that medium has the
|
|
power of perceiving both kinds of objects; for example, if the
|
|
sense-organ is made of air, and air is a medium both for sound and for
|
|
colour; and that (b) if more than one medium can transmit the same
|
|
kind of sensible objects, as e.g. water as well as air can transmit
|
|
colour, both being transparent, then the possessor of either alone
|
|
will be able to perceive the kind of objects transmissible through
|
|
both); and if of the simple elements two only, air and water, go to
|
|
form sense-organs (for the pupil is made of water, the organ of
|
|
hearing is made of air, and the organ of smell of one or other of
|
|
these two, while fire is found either in none or in all-warmth being
|
|
an essential condition of all sensibility-and earth either in none or,
|
|
if anywhere, specially mingled with the components of the organ of
|
|
touch; wherefore it would remain that there can be no sense-organ
|
|
formed of anything except water and air); and if these sense-organs
|
|
are actually found in certain animals;-then all the possible senses
|
|
are possessed by those animals that are not imperfect or mutilated
|
|
(for even the mole is observed to have eyes beneath its skin); so
|
|
that, if there is no fifth element and no property other than those
|
|
which belong to the four elements of our world, no sense can be
|
|
wanting to such animals.
|
|
|
|
Further, there cannot be a special sense-organ for the common
|
|
sensibles either, i.e. the objects which we perceive incidentally
|
|
through this or that special sense, e.g. movement, rest, figure,
|
|
magnitude, number, unity; for all these we perceive by movement,
|
|
e.g. magnitude by movement, and therefore also figure (for figure is a
|
|
species of magnitude), what is at rest by the absence of movement:
|
|
number is perceived by the negation of continuity, and by the
|
|
special sensibles; for each sense perceives one class of sensible
|
|
objects. So that it is clearly impossible that there should be a
|
|
special sense for any one of the common sensibles, e.g. movement; for,
|
|
if that were so, our perception of it would be exactly parallel to our
|
|
present perception of what is sweet by vision. That is so because we
|
|
have a sense for each of the two qualities, in virtue of which when
|
|
they happen to meet in one sensible object we are aware of both
|
|
contemporaneously. If it were not like this our perception of the
|
|
common qualities would always be incidental, i.e. as is the perception
|
|
of Cleon's son, where we perceive him not as Cleon's son but as white,
|
|
and the white thing which we really perceive happens to be Cleon's
|
|
son.
|
|
|
|
But in the case of the common sensibles there is already in us a
|
|
general sensibility which enables us to perceive them directly;
|
|
there is therefore no special sense required for their perception:
|
|
if there were, our perception of them would have been exactly like
|
|
what has been above described.
|
|
|
|
The senses perceive each other's special objects incidentally; not
|
|
because the percipient sense is this or that special sense, but
|
|
because all form a unity: this incidental perception takes place
|
|
whenever sense is directed at one and the same moment to two disparate
|
|
qualities in one and the same object, e.g. to the bitterness and the
|
|
yellowness of bile, the assertion of the identity of both cannot be
|
|
the act of either of the senses; hence the illusion of sense, e.g. the
|
|
belief that if a thing is yellow it is bile.
|
|
|
|
It might be asked why we have more senses than one. Is it to prevent
|
|
a failure to apprehend the common sensibles, e.g. movement, magnitude,
|
|
and number, which go along with the special sensibles? Had we no sense
|
|
but sight, and that sense no object but white, they would have
|
|
tended to escape our notice and everything would have merged for us
|
|
into an indistinguishable identity because of the concomitance of
|
|
colour and magnitude. As it is, the fact that the common sensibles are
|
|
given in the objects of more than one sense reveals their
|
|
distinction from each and all of the special sensibles.
|
|
|
|
2
|
|
|
|
Since it is through sense that we are aware that we are seeing or
|
|
hearing, it must be either by sight that we are aware of seeing, or by
|
|
some sense other than sight. But the sense that gives us this new
|
|
sensation must perceive both sight and its object, viz. colour: so
|
|
that either (1) there will be two senses both percipient of the same
|
|
sensible object, or (2) the sense must be percipient of itself.
|
|
Further, even if the sense which perceives sight were different from
|
|
sight, we must either fall into an infinite regress, or we must
|
|
somewhere assume a sense which is aware of itself. If so, we ought
|
|
to do this in the first case.
|
|
|
|
This presents a difficulty: if to perceive by sight is just to
|
|
see, and what is seen is colour (or the coloured), then if we are to
|
|
see that which sees, that which sees originally must be coloured. It
|
|
is clear therefore that 'to perceive by sight' has more than one
|
|
meaning; for even when we are not seeing, it is by sight that we
|
|
discriminate darkness from light, though not in the same way as we
|
|
distinguish one colour from another. Further, in a sense even that
|
|
which sees is coloured; for in each case the sense-organ is capable of
|
|
receiving the sensible object without its matter. That is why even
|
|
when the sensible objects are gone the sensings and imaginings
|
|
continue to exist in the sense-organs.
|
|
|
|
The activity of the sensible object and that of the percipient sense
|
|
is one and the same activity, and yet the distinction between their
|
|
being remains. Take as illustration actual sound and actual hearing: a
|
|
man may have hearing and yet not be hearing, and that which has a
|
|
sound is not always sounding. But when that which can hear is actively
|
|
hearing and which can sound is sounding, then the actual hearing and
|
|
the actual sound are merged in one (these one might call
|
|
respectively hearkening and sounding).
|
|
|
|
If it is true that the movement, both the acting and the being acted
|
|
upon, is to be found in that which is acted upon, both the sound and
|
|
the hearing so far as it is actual must be found in that which has the
|
|
faculty of hearing; for it is in the passive factor that the actuality
|
|
of the active or motive factor is realized; that is why that which
|
|
causes movement may be at rest. Now the actuality of that which can
|
|
sound is just sound or sounding, and the actuality of that which can
|
|
hear is hearing or hearkening; 'sound' and 'hearing' are both
|
|
ambiguous. The same account applies to the other senses and their
|
|
objects. For as the-acting-and-being-acted-upon is to be found in
|
|
the passive, not in the active factor, so also the actuality of the
|
|
sensible object and that of the sensitive subject are both realized in
|
|
the latter. But while in some cases each aspect of the total actuality
|
|
has a distinct name, e.g. sounding and hearkening, in some one or
|
|
other is nameless, e.g. the actuality of sight is called seeing, but
|
|
the actuality of colour has no name: the actuality of the faculty of
|
|
taste is called tasting, but the actuality of flavour has no name.
|
|
Since the actualities of the sensible object and of the sensitive
|
|
faculty are one actuality in spite of the difference between their
|
|
modes of being, actual hearing and actual sounding appear and
|
|
disappear from existence at one and the same moment, and so actual
|
|
savour and actual tasting, &c., while as potentialities one of them
|
|
may exist without the other. The earlier students of nature were
|
|
mistaken in their view that without sight there was no white or black,
|
|
without taste no savour. This statement of theirs is partly true,
|
|
partly false: 'sense' and 'the sensible object' are ambiguous terms,
|
|
i.e. may denote either potentialities or actualities: the statement is
|
|
true of the latter, false of the former. This ambiguity they wholly
|
|
failed to notice.
|
|
|
|
If voice always implies a concord, and if the voice and the
|
|
hearing of it are in one sense one and the same, and if concord always
|
|
implies a ratio, hearing as well as what is heard must be a ratio.
|
|
That is why the excess of either the sharp or the flat destroys the
|
|
hearing. (So also in the case of savours excess destroys the sense
|
|
of taste, and in the case of colours excessive brightness or
|
|
darkness destroys the sight, and in the case of smell excess of
|
|
strength whether in the direction of sweetness or bitterness is
|
|
destructive.) This shows that the sense is a ratio.
|
|
|
|
That is also why the objects of sense are (1) pleasant when the
|
|
sensible extremes such as acid or sweet or salt being pure and unmixed
|
|
are brought into the proper ratio; then they are pleasant: and in
|
|
general what is blended is more pleasant than the sharp or the flat
|
|
alone; or, to touch, that which is capable of being either warmed or
|
|
chilled: the sense and the ratio are identical: while (2) in excess
|
|
the sensible extremes are painful or destructive.
|
|
|
|
Each sense then is relative to its particular group of sensible
|
|
qualities: it is found in a sense-organ as such and discriminates
|
|
the differences which exist within that group; e.g. sight
|
|
discriminates white and black, taste sweet and bitter, and so in all
|
|
cases. Since we also discriminate white from sweet, and indeed each
|
|
sensible quality from every other, with what do we perceive that
|
|
they are different? It must be by sense; for what is before us is
|
|
sensible objects. (Hence it is also obvious that the flesh cannot be
|
|
the ultimate sense-organ: if it were, the discriminating power could
|
|
not do its work without immediate contact with the object.)
|
|
|
|
Therefore (1) discrimination between white and sweet cannot be
|
|
effected by two agencies which remain separate; both the qualities
|
|
discriminated must be present to something that is one and single.
|
|
On any other supposition even if I perceived sweet and you perceived
|
|
white, the difference between them would be apparent. What says that
|
|
two things are different must be one; for sweet is different from
|
|
white. Therefore what asserts this difference must be
|
|
self-identical, and as what asserts, so also what thinks or perceives.
|
|
That it is not possible by means of two agencies which remain separate
|
|
to discriminate two objects which are separate, is therefore
|
|
obvious; and that (it is not possible to do this in separate movements
|
|
of time may be seen' if we look at it as follows. For as what
|
|
asserts the difference between the good and the bad is one and the
|
|
same, so also the time at which it asserts the one to be different and
|
|
the other to be different is not accidental to the assertion (as it is
|
|
for instance when I now assert a difference but do not assert that
|
|
there is now a difference); it asserts thus-both now and that the
|
|
objects are different now; the objects therefore must be present at
|
|
one and the same moment. Both the discriminating power and the time of
|
|
its exercise must be one and undivided.
|
|
|
|
But, it may be objected, it is impossible that what is
|
|
self-identical should be moved at me and the same time with contrary
|
|
movements in so far as it is undivided, and in an undivided moment
|
|
of time. For if what is sweet be the quality perceived, it moves the
|
|
sense or thought in this determinate way, while what is bitter moves
|
|
it in a contrary way, and what is white in a different way. Is it
|
|
the case then that what discriminates, though both numerically one and
|
|
indivisible, is at the same time divided in its being? In one sense,
|
|
it is what is divided that perceives two separate objects at once, but
|
|
in another sense it does so qua undivided; for it is divisible in
|
|
its being but spatially and numerically undivided. is not this
|
|
impossible? For while it is true that what is self-identical and
|
|
undivided may be both contraries at once potentially, it cannot be
|
|
self-identical in its being-it must lose its unity by being put into
|
|
activity. It is not possible to be at once white and black, and
|
|
therefore it must also be impossible for a thing to be affected at one
|
|
and the same moment by the forms of both, assuming it to be the case
|
|
that sensation and thinking are properly so described.
|
|
|
|
The answer is that just as what is called a 'point' is, as being
|
|
at once one and two, properly said to be divisible, so here, that
|
|
which discriminates is qua undivided one, and active in a single
|
|
moment of time, while so far forth as it is divisible it twice over
|
|
uses the same dot at one and the same time. So far forth then as it
|
|
takes the limit as two' it discriminates two separate objects with
|
|
what in a sense is divided: while so far as it takes it as one, it
|
|
does so with what is one and occupies in its activity a single
|
|
moment of time.
|
|
|
|
About the principle in virtue of which we say that animals are
|
|
percipient, let this discussion suffice.
|
|
|
|
3
|
|
|
|
There are two distinctive peculiarities by reference to which we
|
|
characterize the soul (1) local movement and (2) thinking,
|
|
discriminating, and perceiving. Thinking both speculative and
|
|
practical is regarded as akin to a form of perceiving; for in the
|
|
one as well as the other the soul discriminates and is cognizant of
|
|
something which is. Indeed the ancients go so far as to identify
|
|
thinking and perceiving; e.g. Empedocles says 'For 'tis in respect
|
|
of what is present that man's wit is increased', and again 'Whence
|
|
it befalls them from time to time to think diverse thoughts', and
|
|
Homer's phrase 'For suchlike is man's mind' means the same. They all
|
|
look upon thinking as a bodily process like perceiving, and hold
|
|
that like is known as well as perceived by like, as I explained at the
|
|
beginning of our discussion. Yet they ought at the same time to have
|
|
accounted for error also; for it is more intimately connected with
|
|
animal existence and the soul continues longer in the state of error
|
|
than in that of truth. They cannot escape the dilemma: either (1)
|
|
whatever seems is true (and there are some who accept this) or (2)
|
|
error is contact with the unlike; for that is the opposite of the
|
|
knowing of like by like.
|
|
|
|
But it is a received principle that error as well as knowledge in
|
|
respect to contraries is one and the same.
|
|
|
|
That perceiving and practical thinking are not identical is
|
|
therefore obvious; for the former is universal in the animal world,
|
|
the latter is found in only a small division of it. Further,
|
|
speculative thinking is also distinct from perceiving-I mean that in
|
|
which we find rightness and wrongness-rightness in prudence,
|
|
knowledge, true opinion, wrongness in their opposites; for
|
|
perception of the special objects of sense is always free from
|
|
error, and is found in all animals, while it is possible to think
|
|
falsely as well as truly, and thought is found only where there is
|
|
discourse of reason as well as sensibility. For imagination is
|
|
different from either perceiving or discursive thinking, though it
|
|
is not found without sensation, or judgement without it. That this
|
|
activity is not the same kind of thinking as judgement is obvious. For
|
|
imagining lies within our own power whenever we wish (e.g. we can call
|
|
up a picture, as in the practice of mnemonics by the use of mental
|
|
images), but in forming opinions we are not free: we cannot escape the
|
|
alternative of falsehood or truth. Further, when we think something to
|
|
be fearful or threatening, emotion is immediately produced, and so too
|
|
with what is encouraging; but when we merely imagine we remain as
|
|
unaffected as persons who are looking at a painting of some dreadful
|
|
or encouraging scene. Again within the field of judgement itself we
|
|
find varieties, knowledge, opinion, prudence, and their opposites;
|
|
of the differences between these I must speak elsewhere.
|
|
|
|
Thinking is different from perceiving and is held to be in part
|
|
imagination, in part judgement: we must therefore first mark off the
|
|
sphere of imagination and then speak of judgement. If then imagination
|
|
is that in virtue of which an image arises for us, excluding
|
|
metaphorical uses of the term, is it a single faculty or disposition
|
|
relative to images, in virtue of which we discriminate and are
|
|
either in error or not? The faculties in virtue of which we do this
|
|
are sense, opinion, science, intelligence.
|
|
|
|
That imagination is not sense is clear from the following
|
|
considerations: Sense is either a faculty or an activity, e.g. sight
|
|
or seeing: imagination takes place in the absence of both, as e.g.
|
|
in dreams. (Again, sense is always present, imagination not. If actual
|
|
imagination and actual sensation were the same, imagination would be
|
|
found in all the brutes: this is held not to be the case; e.g. it is
|
|
not found in ants or bees or grubs. (Again, sensations are always
|
|
true, imaginations are for the most part false. (Once more, even in
|
|
ordinary speech, we do not, when sense functions precisely with regard
|
|
to its object, say that we imagine it to be a man, but rather when
|
|
there is some failure of accuracy in its exercise. And as we were
|
|
saying before, visions appear to us even when our eyes are shut.
|
|
Neither is imagination any of the things that are never in error: e.g.
|
|
knowledge or intelligence; for imagination may be false.
|
|
|
|
It remains therefore to see if it is opinion, for opinion may be
|
|
either true or false.
|
|
|
|
But opinion involves belief (for without belief in what we opine
|
|
we cannot have an opinion), and in the brutes though we often find
|
|
imagination we never find belief. Further, every opinion is
|
|
accompanied by belief, belief by conviction, and conviction by
|
|
discourse of reason: while there are some of the brutes in which we
|
|
find imagination, without discourse of reason. It is clear then that
|
|
imagination cannot, again, be (1) opinion plus sensation, or (2)
|
|
opinion mediated by sensation, or (3) a blend of opinion and
|
|
sensation; this is impossible both for these reasons and because the
|
|
content of the supposed opinion cannot be different from that of the
|
|
sensation (I mean that imagination must be the blending of the
|
|
perception of white with the opinion that it is white: it could
|
|
scarcely be a blend of the opinion that it is good with the perception
|
|
that it is white): to imagine is therefore (on this view) identical
|
|
with the thinking of exactly the same as what one in the strictest
|
|
sense perceives. But what we imagine is sometimes false though our
|
|
contemporaneous judgement about it is true; e.g. we imagine the sun to
|
|
be a foot in diameter though we are convinced that it is larger than
|
|
the inhabited part of the earth, and the following dilemma presents
|
|
itself. Either (a while the fact has not changed and the (observer has
|
|
neither forgotten nor lost belief in the true opinion which he had,
|
|
that opinion has disappeared, or (b) if he retains it then his opinion
|
|
is at once true and false. A true opinion, however, becomes false only
|
|
when the fact alters without being noticed.
|
|
|
|
Imagination is therefore neither any one of the states enumerated,
|
|
nor compounded out of them.
|
|
|
|
But since when one thing has been set in motion another thing may be
|
|
moved by it, and imagination is held to be a movement and to be
|
|
impossible without sensation, i.e. to occur in beings that are
|
|
percipient and to have for its content what can be perceived, and
|
|
since movement may be produced by actual sensation and that movement
|
|
is necessarily similar in character to the sensation itself, this
|
|
movement must be (1) necessarily (a) incapable of existing apart
|
|
from sensation, (b) incapable of existing except when we perceive,
|
|
(such that in virtue of its possession that in which it is found may
|
|
present various phenomena both active and passive, and (such that it
|
|
may be either true or false.
|
|
|
|
The reason of the last characteristic is as follows. Perception
|
|
(1) of the special objects of sense is never in error or admits the
|
|
least possible amount of falsehood. (2) That of the concomitance of
|
|
the objects concomitant with the sensible qualities comes next: in
|
|
this case certainly we may be deceived; for while the perception
|
|
that there is white before us cannot be false, the perception that
|
|
what is white is this or that may be false. (3) Third comes the
|
|
perception of the universal attributes which accompany the concomitant
|
|
objects to which the special sensibles attach (I mean e.g. of movement
|
|
and magnitude); it is in respect of these that the greatest amount
|
|
of sense-illusion is possible.
|
|
|
|
The motion which is due to the activity of sense in these three
|
|
modes of its exercise will differ from the activity of sense; (1)
|
|
the first kind of derived motion is free from error while the
|
|
sensation is present; (2) and (3) the others may be erroneous
|
|
whether it is present or absent, especially when the object of
|
|
perception is far off. If then imagination presents no other
|
|
features than those enumerated and is what we have described, then
|
|
imagination must be a movement resulting from an actual exercise of
|
|
a power of sense.
|
|
|
|
As sight is the most highly developed sense, the name Phantasia
|
|
(imagination) has been formed from Phaos (light) because it is not
|
|
possible to see without light.
|
|
|
|
And because imaginations remain in the organs of sense and
|
|
resemble sensations, animals in their actions are largely guided by
|
|
them, some (i.e. the brutes) because of the non-existence in them of
|
|
mind, others (i.e. men) because of the temporary eclipse in them of
|
|
mind by feeling or disease or sleep.
|
|
|
|
About imagination, what it is and why it exists, let so much
|
|
suffice.
|
|
|
|
4
|
|
|
|
Turning now to the part of the soul with which the soul knows and
|
|
thinks (whether this is separable from the others in definition
|
|
only, or spatially as well) we have to inquire (1) what differentiates
|
|
this part, and (2) how thinking can take place.
|
|
|
|
If thinking is like perceiving, it must be either a process in which
|
|
the soul is acted upon by what is capable of being thought, or a
|
|
process different from but analogous to that. The thinking part of the
|
|
soul must therefore be, while impassible, capable of receiving the
|
|
form of an object; that is, must be potentially identical in character
|
|
with its object without being the object. Mind must be related to what
|
|
is thinkable, as sense is to what is sensible.
|
|
|
|
Therefore, since everything is a possible object of thought, mind in
|
|
order, as Anaxagoras says, to dominate, that is, to know, must be pure
|
|
from all admixture; for the co-presence of what is alien to its nature
|
|
is a hindrance and a block: it follows that it too, like the sensitive
|
|
part, can have no nature of its own, other than that of having a
|
|
certain capacity. Thus that in the soul which is called mind (by
|
|
mind I mean that whereby the soul thinks and judges) is, before it
|
|
thinks, not actually any real thing. For this reason it cannot
|
|
reasonably be regarded as blended with the body: if so, it would
|
|
acquire some quality, e.g. warmth or cold, or even have an organ
|
|
like the sensitive faculty: as it is, it has none. It was a good
|
|
idea to call the soul 'the place of forms', though (1) this
|
|
description holds only of the intellective soul, and (2) even this
|
|
is the forms only potentially, not actually.
|
|
|
|
Observation of the sense-organs and their employment reveals a
|
|
distinction between the impassibility of the sensitive and that of the
|
|
intellective faculty. After strong stimulation of a sense we are
|
|
less able to exercise it than before, as e.g. in the case of a loud
|
|
sound we cannot hear easily immediately after, or in the case of a
|
|
bright colour or a powerful odour we cannot see or smell, but in the
|
|
case of mind thought about an object that is highly intelligible
|
|
renders it more and not less able afterwards to think objects that are
|
|
less intelligible: the reason is that while the faculty of sensation
|
|
is dependent upon the body, mind is separable from it.
|
|
|
|
Once the mind has become each set of its possible objects, as a
|
|
man of science has, when this phrase is used of one who is actually
|
|
a man of science (this happens when he is now able to exercise the
|
|
power on his own initiative), its condition is still one of
|
|
potentiality, but in a different sense from the potentiality which
|
|
preceded the acquisition of knowledge by learning or discovery: the
|
|
mind too is then able to think itself.
|
|
|
|
Since we can distinguish between a spatial magnitude and what it
|
|
is to be such, and between water and what it is to be water, and so in
|
|
many other cases (though not in all; for in certain cases the thing
|
|
and its form are identical), flesh and what it is to be flesh are
|
|
discriminated either by different faculties, or by the same faculty in
|
|
two different states: for flesh necessarily involves matter and is
|
|
like what is snub-nosed, a this in a this. Now it is by means of the
|
|
sensitive faculty that we discriminate the hot and the cold, i.e.
|
|
the factors which combined in a certain ratio constitute flesh: the
|
|
essential character of flesh is apprehended by something different
|
|
either wholly separate from the sensitive faculty or related to it
|
|
as a bent line to the same line when it has been straightened out.
|
|
|
|
Again in the case of abstract objects what is straight is
|
|
analogous to what is snub-nosed; for it necessarily implies a
|
|
continuum as its matter: its constitutive essence is different, if
|
|
we may distinguish between straightness and what is straight: let us
|
|
take it to be two-ness. It must be apprehended, therefore, by a
|
|
different power or by the same power in a different state. To sum
|
|
up, in so far as the realities it knows are capable of being separated
|
|
from their matter, so it is also with the powers of mind.
|
|
|
|
The problem might be suggested: if thinking is a passive
|
|
affection, then if mind is simple and impassible and has nothing in
|
|
common with anything else, as Anaxagoras says, how can it come to
|
|
think at all? For interaction between two factors is held to require a
|
|
precedent community of nature between the factors. Again it might be
|
|
asked, is mind a possible object of thought to itself? For if mind
|
|
is thinkable per se and what is thinkable is in kind one and the same,
|
|
then either (a) mind will belong to everything, or (b) mind will
|
|
contain some element common to it with all other realities which makes
|
|
them all thinkable.
|
|
|
|
(1) Have not we already disposed of the difficulty about interaction
|
|
involving a common element, when we said that mind is in a sense
|
|
potentially whatever is thinkable, though actually it is nothing until
|
|
it has thought? What it thinks must be in it just as characters may be
|
|
said to be on a writingtablet on which as yet nothing actually
|
|
stands written: this is exactly what happens with mind.
|
|
|
|
(Mind is itself thinkable in exactly the same way as its objects
|
|
are. For (a) in the case of objects which involve no matter, what
|
|
thinks and what is thought are identical; for speculative knowledge
|
|
and its object are identical. (Why mind is not always thinking we must
|
|
consider later.) (b) In the case of those which contain matter each of
|
|
the objects of thought is only potentially present. It follows that
|
|
while they will not have mind in them (for mind is a potentiality of
|
|
them only in so far as they are capable of being disengaged from
|
|
matter) mind may yet be thinkable.
|
|
|
|
5
|
|
|
|
Since in every class of things, as in nature as a whole, we find two
|
|
factors involved, (1) a matter which is potentially all the
|
|
particulars included in the class, (2) a cause which is productive
|
|
in the sense that it makes them all (the latter standing to the
|
|
former, as e.g. an art to its material), these distinct elements
|
|
must likewise be found within the soul.
|
|
|
|
And in fact mind as we have described it is what it is what it is by
|
|
virtue of becoming all things, while there is another which is what it
|
|
is by virtue of making all things: this is a sort of positive state
|
|
like light; for in a sense light makes potential colours into actual
|
|
colours.
|
|
|
|
Mind in this sense of it is separable, impassible, unmixed, since it
|
|
is in its essential nature activity (for always the active is superior
|
|
to the passive factor, the originating force to the matter which it
|
|
forms).
|
|
|
|
Actual knowledge is identical with its object: in the individual,
|
|
potential knowledge is in time prior to actual knowledge, but in the
|
|
universe as a whole it is not prior even in time. Mind is not at one
|
|
time knowing and at another not. When mind is set free from its
|
|
present conditions it appears as just what it is and nothing more:
|
|
this alone is immortal and eternal (we do not, however, remember its
|
|
former activity because, while mind in this sense is impassible,
|
|
mind as passive is destructible), and without it nothing thinks.
|
|
|
|
6
|
|
|
|
The thinking then of the simple objects of thought is found in those
|
|
cases where falsehood is impossible: where the alternative of true
|
|
or false applies, there we always find a putting together of objects
|
|
of thought in a quasi-unity. As Empedocles said that 'where heads of
|
|
many a creature sprouted without necks' they afterwards by Love's
|
|
power were combined, so here too objects of thought which were given
|
|
separate are combined, e.g. 'incommensurate' and 'diagonal': if the
|
|
combination be of objects past or future the combination of thought
|
|
includes in its content the date. For falsehood always involves a
|
|
synthesis; for even if you assert that what is white is not white
|
|
you have included not white in a synthesis. It is possible also to
|
|
call all these cases division as well as combination. However that may
|
|
be, there is not only the true or false assertion that Cleon is
|
|
white but also the true or false assertion that he was or will he
|
|
white. In each and every case that which unifies is mind.
|
|
|
|
Since the word 'simple' has two senses, i.e. may mean either (a)
|
|
'not capable of being divided' or (b) 'not actually divided', there is
|
|
nothing to prevent mind from knowing what is undivided, e.g. when it
|
|
apprehends a length (which is actually undivided) and that in an
|
|
undivided time; for the time is divided or undivided in the same
|
|
manner as the line. It is not possible, then, to tell what part of the
|
|
line it was apprehending in each half of the time: the object has no
|
|
actual parts until it has been divided: if in thought you think each
|
|
half separately, then by the same act you divide the time also, the
|
|
half-lines becoming as it were new wholes of length. But if you
|
|
think it as a whole consisting of these two possible parts, then
|
|
also you think it in a time which corresponds to both parts
|
|
together. (But what is not quantitatively but qualitatively simple
|
|
is thought in a simple time and by a simple act of the soul.)
|
|
|
|
But that which mind thinks and the time in which it thinks are in
|
|
this case divisible only incidentally and not as such. For in them too
|
|
there is something indivisible (though, it may be, not isolable) which
|
|
gives unity to the time and the whole of length; and this is found
|
|
equally in every continuum whether temporal or spatial.
|
|
|
|
Points and similar instances of things that divide, themselves being
|
|
indivisible, are realized in consciousness in the same manner as
|
|
privations.
|
|
|
|
A similar account may be given of all other cases, e.g. how evil
|
|
or black is cognized; they are cognized, in a sense, by means of their
|
|
contraries. That which cognizes must have an element of potentiality
|
|
in its being, and one of the contraries must be in it. But if there is
|
|
anything that has no contrary, then it knows itself and is actually
|
|
and possesses independent existence.
|
|
|
|
Assertion is the saying of something concerning something, e.g.
|
|
affirmation, and is in every case either true or false: this is not
|
|
always the case with mind: the thinking of the definition in the sense
|
|
of the constitutive essence is never in error nor is it the
|
|
assertion of something concerning something, but, just as while the
|
|
seeing of the special object of sight can never be in error, the
|
|
belief that the white object seen is a man may be mistaken, so too
|
|
in the case of objects which are without matter.
|
|
|
|
7
|
|
|
|
Actual knowledge is identical with its object: potential knowledge
|
|
in the individual is in time prior to actual knowledge but in the
|
|
universe it has no priority even in time; for all things that come
|
|
into being arise from what actually is. In the case of sense clearly
|
|
the sensitive faculty already was potentially what the object makes it
|
|
to be actually; the faculty is not affected or altered. This must
|
|
therefore be a different kind from movement; for movement is, as we
|
|
saw, an activity of what is imperfect, activity in the unqualified
|
|
sense, i.e. that of what has been perfected, is different from
|
|
movement.
|
|
|
|
To perceive then is like bare asserting or knowing; but when the
|
|
object is pleasant or painful, the soul makes a quasi-affirmation or
|
|
negation, and pursues or avoids the object. To feel pleasure or pain
|
|
is to act with the sensitive mean towards what is good or bad as such.
|
|
Both avoidance and appetite when actual are identical with this: the
|
|
faculty of appetite and avoidance are not different, either from one
|
|
another or from the faculty of sense-perception; but their being is
|
|
different.
|
|
|
|
To the thinking soul images serve as if they were contents of
|
|
perception (and when it asserts or denies them to be good or bad it
|
|
avoids or pursues them). That is why the soul never thinks without
|
|
an image. The process is like that in which the air modifies the pupil
|
|
in this or that way and the pupil transmits the modification to some
|
|
third thing (and similarly in hearing), while the ultimate point of
|
|
arrival is one, a single mean, with different manners of being.
|
|
|
|
With what part of itself the soul discriminates sweet from hot I
|
|
have explained before and must now describe again as follows: That
|
|
with which it does so is a sort of unity, but in the way just
|
|
mentioned, i.e. as a connecting term. And the two faculties it
|
|
connects, being one by analogy and numerically, are each to each as
|
|
the qualities discerned are to one another (for what difference does
|
|
it make whether we raise the problem of discrimination between
|
|
disparates or between contraries, e.g. white and black?). Let then C
|
|
be to D as is to B: it follows alternando that C: A:: D: B. If then
|
|
C and D belong to one subject, the case will be the same with them
|
|
as with and B; and B form a single identity with different modes of
|
|
being; so too will the former pair. The same reasoning holds if be
|
|
sweet and B white.
|
|
|
|
The faculty of thinking then thinks the forms in the images, and
|
|
as in the former case what is to be pursued or avoided is marked out
|
|
for it, so where there is no sensation and it is engaged upon the
|
|
images it is moved to pursuit or avoidance. E.g.. perceiving by
|
|
sense that the beacon is fire, it recognizes in virtue of the
|
|
general faculty of sense that it signifies an enemy, because it sees
|
|
it moving; but sometimes by means of the images or thoughts which
|
|
are within the soul, just as if it were seeing, it calculates and
|
|
deliberates what is to come by reference to what is present; and
|
|
when it makes a pronouncement, as in the case of sensation it
|
|
pronounces the object to be pleasant or painful, in this case it
|
|
avoids or persues and so generally in cases of action.
|
|
|
|
That too which involves no action, i.e. that which is true or false,
|
|
is in the same province with what is good or bad: yet they differ in
|
|
this, that the one set imply and the other do not a reference to a
|
|
particular person.
|
|
|
|
The so-called abstract objects the mind thinks just as, if one had
|
|
thought of the snubnosed not as snub-nosed but as hollow, one would
|
|
have thought of an actuality without the flesh in which it is
|
|
embodied: it is thus that the mind when it is thinking the objects
|
|
of Mathematics thinks as separate elements which do not exist
|
|
separate. In every case the mind which is actively thinking is the
|
|
objects which it thinks. Whether it is possible for it while not
|
|
existing separate from spatial conditions to think anything that is
|
|
separate, or not, we must consider later.
|
|
|
|
8
|
|
|
|
Let us now summarize our results about soul, and repeat that the
|
|
soul is in a way all existing things; for existing things are either
|
|
sensible or thinkable, and knowledge is in a way what is knowable, and
|
|
sensation is in a way what is sensible: in what way we must inquire.
|
|
|
|
Knowledge and sensation are divided to correspond with the
|
|
realities, potential knowledge and sensation answering to
|
|
potentialities, actual knowledge and sensation to actualities.
|
|
Within the soul the faculties of knowledge and sensation are
|
|
potentially these objects, the one what is knowable, the other what is
|
|
sensible. They must be either the things themselves or their forms.
|
|
The former alternative is of course impossible: it is not the stone
|
|
which is present in the soul but its form.
|
|
|
|
It follows that the soul is analogous to the hand; for as the hand
|
|
is a tool of tools, so the mind is the form of forms and sense the
|
|
form of sensible things.
|
|
|
|
Since according to common agreement there is nothing outside and
|
|
separate in existence from sensible spatial magnitudes, the objects of
|
|
thought are in the sensible forms, viz. both the abstract objects
|
|
and all the states and affections of sensible things. Hence (1) no one
|
|
can learn or understand anything in the absence of sense, and (when
|
|
the mind is actively aware of anything it is necessarily aware of it
|
|
along with an image; for images are like sensuous contents except in
|
|
that they contain no matter.
|
|
|
|
Imagination is different from assertion and denial; for what is true
|
|
or false involves a synthesis of concepts. In what will the primary
|
|
concepts differ from images? Must we not say that neither these nor
|
|
even our other concepts are images, though they necessarily involve
|
|
them?
|
|
|
|
9
|
|
|
|
The soul of animals is characterized by two faculties, (a) the
|
|
faculty of discrimination which is the work of thought and sense,
|
|
and (b) the faculty of originating local movement. Sense and mind we
|
|
have now sufficiently examined. Let us next consider what it is in the
|
|
soul which originates movement. Is it a single part of the soul
|
|
separate either spatially or in definition? Or is it the soul as a
|
|
whole? If it is a part, is that part different from those usually
|
|
distinguished or already mentioned by us, or is it one of them? The
|
|
problem at once presents itself, in what sense we are to speak of
|
|
parts of the soul, or how many we should distinguish. For in a sense
|
|
there is an infinity of parts: it is not enough to distinguish, with
|
|
some thinkers, the calculative, the passionate, and the
|
|
desiderative, or with others the rational and the irrational; for if
|
|
we take the dividing lines followed by these thinkers we shall find
|
|
parts far more distinctly separated from one another than these,
|
|
namely those we have just mentioned: (1) the nutritive, which
|
|
belongs both to plants and to all animals, and (2) the sensitive,
|
|
which cannot easily be classed as either irrational or rational;
|
|
further (3) the imaginative, which is, in its being, different from
|
|
all, while it is very hard to say with which of the others it is the
|
|
same or not the same, supposing we determine to posit separate parts
|
|
in the soul; and lastly (4) the appetitive, which would seem to be
|
|
distinct both in definition and in power from all hitherto enumerated.
|
|
|
|
It is absurd to break up the last-mentioned faculty: as these
|
|
thinkers do, for wish is found in the calculative part and desire
|
|
and passion in the irrational; and if the soul is tripartite
|
|
appetite will be found in all three parts. Turning our attention to
|
|
the present object of discussion, let us ask what that is which
|
|
originates local movement of the animal.
|
|
|
|
The movement of growth and decay, being found in all living
|
|
things, must be attributed to the faculty of reproduction and
|
|
nutrition, which is common to all: inspiration and expiration, sleep
|
|
and waking, we must consider later: these too present much difficulty:
|
|
at present we must consider local movement, asking what it is that
|
|
originates forward movement in the animal.
|
|
|
|
That it is not the nutritive faculty is obvious; for this kind of
|
|
movement is always for an end and is accompanied either by imagination
|
|
or by appetite; for no animal moves except by compulsion unless it has
|
|
an impulse towards or away from an object. Further, if it were the
|
|
nutritive faculty, even plants would have been capable of
|
|
originating such movement and would have possessed the organs
|
|
necessary to carry it out. Similarly it cannot be the sensitive
|
|
faculty either; for there are many animals which have sensibility
|
|
but remain fast and immovable throughout their lives.
|
|
|
|
If then Nature never makes anything without a purpose and never
|
|
leaves out what is necessary (except in the case of mutilated or
|
|
imperfect growths; and that here we have neither mutilation nor
|
|
imperfection may be argued from the facts that such animals (a) can
|
|
reproduce their species and (b) rise to completeness of nature and
|
|
decay to an end), it follows that, had they been capable of
|
|
originating forward movement, they would have possessed the organs
|
|
necessary for that purpose. Further, neither can the calculative
|
|
faculty or what is called 'mind' be the cause of such movement; for
|
|
mind as speculative never thinks what is practicable, it never says
|
|
anything about an object to be avoided or pursued, while this movement
|
|
is always in something which is avoiding or pursuing an object. No,
|
|
not even when it is aware of such an object does it at once enjoin
|
|
pursuit or avoidance of it; e.g. the mind often thinks of something
|
|
terrifying or pleasant without enjoining the emotion of fear. It is
|
|
the heart that is moved (or in the case of a pleasant object some
|
|
other part). Further, even when the mind does command and thought bids
|
|
us pursue or avoid something, sometimes no movement is produced; we
|
|
act in accordance with desire, as in the case of moral weakness.
|
|
And, generally, we observe that the possessor of medical knowledge
|
|
is not necessarily healing, which shows that something else is
|
|
required to produce action in accordance with knowledge; the knowledge
|
|
alone is not the cause. Lastly, appetite too is incompetent to account
|
|
fully for movement; for those who successfully resist temptation
|
|
have appetite and desire and yet follow mind and refuse to enact
|
|
that for which they have appetite.
|
|
|
|
10
|
|
|
|
These two at all events appear to be sources of movement: appetite
|
|
and mind (if one may venture to regard imagination as a kind of
|
|
thinking; for many men follow their imaginations contrary to
|
|
knowledge, and in all animals other than man there is no thinking or
|
|
calculation but only imagination).
|
|
|
|
Both of these then are capable of originating local movement, mind
|
|
and appetite: (1) mind, that is, which calculates means to an end,
|
|
i.e. mind practical (it differs from mind speculative in the character
|
|
of its end); while (2) appetite is in every form of it relative to
|
|
an end: for that which is the object of appetite is the stimulant of
|
|
mind practical; and that which is last in the process of thinking is
|
|
the beginning of the action. It follows that there is a
|
|
justification for regarding these two as the sources of movement, i.e.
|
|
appetite and practical thought; for the object of appetite starts a
|
|
movement and as a result of that thought gives rise to movement, the
|
|
object of appetite being it a source of stimulation. So too when
|
|
imagination originates movement, it necessarily involves appetite.
|
|
|
|
That which moves therefore is a single faculty and the faculty of
|
|
appetite; for if there had been two sources of movement-mind and
|
|
appetite-they would have produced movement in virtue of some common
|
|
character. As it is, mind is never found producing movement without
|
|
appetite (for wish is a form of appetite; and when movement is
|
|
produced according to calculation it is also according to wish), but
|
|
appetite can originate movement contrary to calculation, for desire is
|
|
a form of appetite. Now mind is always right, but appetite and
|
|
imagination may be either right or wrong. That is why, though in any
|
|
case it is the object of appetite which originates movement, this
|
|
object may be either the real or the apparent good. To produce
|
|
movement the object must be more than this: it must be good that can
|
|
be brought into being by action; and only what can be otherwise than
|
|
as it is can thus be brought into being. That then such a power in the
|
|
soul as has been described, i.e. that called appetite, originates
|
|
movement is clear. Those who distinguish parts in the soul, if they
|
|
distinguish and divide in accordance with differences of power, find
|
|
themselves with a very large number of parts, a nutritive, a
|
|
sensitive, an intellective, a deliberative, and now an appetitive
|
|
part; for these are more different from one another than the faculties
|
|
of desire and passion.
|
|
|
|
Since appetites run counter to one another, which happens when a
|
|
principle of reason and a desire are contrary and is possible only
|
|
in beings with a sense of time (for while mind bids us hold back
|
|
because of what is future, desire is influenced by what is just at
|
|
hand: a pleasant object which is just at hand presents itself as
|
|
both pleasant and good, without condition in either case, because of
|
|
want of foresight into what is farther away in time), it follows
|
|
that while that which originates movement must be specifically one,
|
|
viz. the faculty of appetite as such (or rather farthest back of all
|
|
the object of that faculty; for it is it that itself remaining unmoved
|
|
originates the movement by being apprehended in thought or
|
|
imagination), the things that originate movement are numerically many.
|
|
|
|
All movement involves three factors, (1) that which originates the
|
|
movement, (2) that by means of which it originates it, and (3) that
|
|
which is moved. The expression 'that which originates the movement' is
|
|
ambiguous: it may mean either (a) something which itself is unmoved or
|
|
(b) that which at once moves and is moved. Here that which moves
|
|
without itself being moved is the realizable good, that which at
|
|
once moves and is moved is the faculty of appetite (for that which
|
|
is influenced by appetite so far as it is actually so influenced is
|
|
set in movement, and appetite in the sense of actual appetite is a
|
|
kind of movement), while that which is in motion is the animal. The
|
|
instrument which appetite employs to produce movement is no longer
|
|
psychical but bodily: hence the examination of it falls within the
|
|
province of the functions common to body and soul. To state the matter
|
|
summarily at present, that which is the instrument in the production
|
|
of movement is to be found where a beginning and an end coincide as
|
|
e.g. in a ball and socket joint; for there the convex and the
|
|
concave sides are respectively an end and a beginning (that is why
|
|
while the one remains at rest, the other is moved): they are
|
|
separate in definition but not separable spatially. For everything
|
|
is moved by pushing and pulling. Hence just as in the case of a wheel,
|
|
so here there must be a point which remains at rest, and from that
|
|
point the movement must originate.
|
|
|
|
To sum up, then, and repeat what I have said, inasmuch as an
|
|
animal is capable of appetite it is capable of self-movement; it is
|
|
not capable of appetite without possessing imagination; and all
|
|
imagination is either (1) calculative or (2) sensitive. In the
|
|
latter an animals, and not only man, partake.
|
|
|
|
11
|
|
|
|
We must consider also in the case of imperfect animals, sc. those
|
|
which have no sense but touch, what it is that in them originates
|
|
movement. Can they have imagination or not? or desire? Clearly they
|
|
have feelings of pleasure and pain, and if they have these they must
|
|
have desire. But how can they have imagination? Must not we say
|
|
that, as their movements are indefinite, they have imagination and
|
|
desire, but indefinitely?
|
|
|
|
Sensitive imagination, as we have said, is found in all animals,
|
|
deliberative imagination only in those that are calculative: for
|
|
whether this or that shall be enacted is already a task requiring
|
|
calculation; and there must be a single standard to measure by, for
|
|
that is pursued which is greater. It follows that what acts in this
|
|
way must be able to make a unity out of several images.
|
|
|
|
This is the reason why imagination is held not to involve opinion,
|
|
in that it does not involve opinion based on inference, though opinion
|
|
involves imagination. Hence appetite contains no deliberative element.
|
|
Sometimes it overpowers wish and sets it in movement: at times wish
|
|
acts thus upon appetite, like one sphere imparting its movement to
|
|
another, or appetite acts thus upon appetite, i.e. in the condition of
|
|
moral weakness (though by nature the higher faculty is always more
|
|
authoritative and gives rise to movement). Thus three modes of
|
|
movement are possible.
|
|
|
|
The faculty of knowing is never moved but remains at rest. Since the
|
|
one premiss or judgement is universal and the other deals with the
|
|
particular (for the first tells us that such and such a kind of man
|
|
should do such and such a kind of act, and the second that this is
|
|
an act of the kind meant, and I a person of the type intended), it
|
|
is the latter opinion that really originates movement, not the
|
|
universal; or rather it is both, but the one does so while it
|
|
remains in a state more like rest, while the other partakes in
|
|
movement.
|
|
|
|
12
|
|
|
|
The nutritive soul then must be possessed by everything that is
|
|
alive, and every such thing is endowed with soul from its birth to its
|
|
death. For what has been born must grow, reach maturity, and decay-all
|
|
of which are impossible without nutrition. Therefore the nutritive
|
|
faculty must be found in everything that grows and decays.
|
|
|
|
But sensation need not be found in all things that live. For it is
|
|
impossible for touch to belong either (1) to those whose body is
|
|
uncompounded or (2) to those which are incapable of taking in the
|
|
forms without their matter.
|
|
|
|
But animals must be endowed with sensation, since Nature does
|
|
nothing in vain. For all things that exist by Nature are means to an
|
|
end, or will be concomitants of means to an end. Every body capable of
|
|
forward movement would, if unendowed with sensation, perish and fail
|
|
to reach its end, which is the aim of Nature; for how could it
|
|
obtain nutriment? Stationary living things, it is true, have as
|
|
their nutriment that from which they have arisen; but it is not
|
|
possible that a body which is not stationary but produced by
|
|
generation should have a soul and a discerning mind without also
|
|
having sensation. (Nor yet even if it were not produced by generation.
|
|
Why should it not have sensation? Because it were better so either for
|
|
the body or for the soul? But clearly it would not be better for
|
|
either: the absence of sensation will not enable the one to think
|
|
better or the other to exist better.) Therefore no body which is not
|
|
stationary has soul without sensation.
|
|
|
|
But if a body has sensation, it must be either simple or compound.
|
|
And simple it cannot be; for then it could not have touch, which is
|
|
indispensable. This is clear from what follows. An animal is a body
|
|
with soul in it: every body is tangible, i.e. perceptible by touch;
|
|
hence necessarily, if an animal is to survive, its body must have
|
|
tactual sensation. All the other senses, e.g. smell, sight, hearing,
|
|
apprehend through media; but where there is immediate contact the
|
|
animal, if it has no sensation, will be unable to avoid some things
|
|
and take others, and so will find it impossible to survive. That is
|
|
why taste also is a sort of touch; it is relative to nutriment,
|
|
which is just tangible body; whereas sound, colour, and odour are
|
|
innutritious, and further neither grow nor decay. Hence it is that
|
|
taste also must be a sort of touch, because it is the sense for what
|
|
is tangible and nutritious.
|
|
|
|
Both these senses, then, are indispensable to the animal, and it
|
|
is clear that without touch it is impossible for an animal to be.
|
|
All the other senses subserve well-being and for that very reason
|
|
belong not to any and every kind of animal, but only to some, e.g.
|
|
those capable of forward movement must have them; for, if they are
|
|
to survive, they must perceive not only by immediate contact but
|
|
also at a distance from the object. This will be possible if they
|
|
can perceive through a medium, the medium being affected and moved
|
|
by the perceptible object, and the animal by the medium. just as
|
|
that which produces local movement causes a change extending to a
|
|
certain point, and that which gave an impulse causes another to
|
|
produce a new impulse so that the movement traverses a medium the
|
|
first mover impelling without being impelled, the last moved being
|
|
impelled without impelling, while the medium (or media, for there
|
|
are many) is both-so is it also in the case of alteration, except that
|
|
the agent produces produces it without the patient's changing its
|
|
place. Thus if an object is dipped into wax, the movement goes on
|
|
until submersion has taken place, and in stone it goes no distance
|
|
at all, while in water the disturbance goes far beyond the object
|
|
dipped: in air the disturbance is propagated farthest of all, the
|
|
air acting and being acted upon, so long as it maintains an unbroken
|
|
unity. That is why in the case of reflection it is better, instead
|
|
of saying that the sight issues from the eye and is reflected, to
|
|
say that the air, so long as it remains one, is affected by the
|
|
shape and colour. On a smooth surface the air possesses unity; hence
|
|
it is that it in turn sets the sight in motion, just as if the
|
|
impression on the wax were transmitted as far as the wax extends.
|
|
|
|
13
|
|
|
|
It is clear that the body of an animal cannot be simple, i.e.
|
|
consist of one element such as fire or air. For without touch it is
|
|
impossible to have any other sense; for every body that has soul in it
|
|
must, as we have said, be capable of touch. All the other elements
|
|
with the exception of earth can constitute organs of sense, but all of
|
|
them bring about perception only through something else, viz.
|
|
through the media. Touch takes place by direct contact with its
|
|
objects, whence also its name. All the other organs of sense, no
|
|
doubt, perceive by contact, only the contact is mediate: touch alone
|
|
perceives by immediate contact. Consequently no animal body can
|
|
consist of these other elements.
|
|
|
|
Nor can it consist solely of earth. For touch is as it were a mean
|
|
between all tangible qualities, and its organ is capable of
|
|
receiving not only all the specific qualities which characterize
|
|
earth, but also the hot and the cold and all other tangible
|
|
qualities whatsoever. That is why we have no sensation by means of
|
|
bones, hair, &c., because they consist of earth. So too plants,
|
|
because they consist of earth, have no sensation. Without touch
|
|
there can be no other sense, and the organ of touch cannot consist
|
|
of earth or of any other single element.
|
|
|
|
It is evident, therefore, that the loss of this one sense alone must
|
|
bring about the death of an animal. For as on the one hand nothing
|
|
which is not an animal can have this sense, so on the other it is
|
|
the only one which is indispensably necessary to what is an animal.
|
|
This explains, further, the following difference between the other
|
|
senses and touch. In the case of all the others excess of intensity in
|
|
the qualities which they apprehend, i.e. excess of intensity in
|
|
colour, sound, and smell, destroys not the but only the organs of
|
|
the sense (except incidentally, as when the sound is accompanied by an
|
|
impact or shock, or where through the objects of sight or of smell
|
|
certain other things are set in motion, which destroy by contact);
|
|
flavour also destroys only in so far as it is at the same time
|
|
tangible. But excess of intensity in tangible qualities, e.g. heat,
|
|
cold, or hardness, destroys the animal itself. As in the case of every
|
|
sensible quality excess destroys the organ, so here what is tangible
|
|
destroys touch, which is the essential mark of life; for it has been
|
|
shown that without touch it is impossible for an animal to be. That is
|
|
why excess in intensity of tangible qualities destroys not merely
|
|
the organ, but the animal itself, because this is the only sense which
|
|
it must have.
|
|
|
|
All the other senses are necessary to animals, as we have said,
|
|
not for their being, but for their well-being. Such, e.g. is sight,
|
|
which, since it lives in air or water, or generally in what is
|
|
pellucid, it must have in order to see, and taste because of what is
|
|
pleasant or painful to it, in order that it may perceive these
|
|
qualities in its nutriment and so may desire to be set in motion,
|
|
and hearing that it may have communication made to it, and a tongue
|
|
that it may communicate with its fellows.
|
|
|
|
THE END
|
|
.
|