mirror of
https://github.com/opsxcq/mirror-textfiles.com.git
synced 2025-09-01 00:51:52 +02:00
2626 lines
153 KiB
Plaintext
2626 lines
153 KiB
Plaintext
350 BC
|
|
|
|
ON GENERATION AND CORRUPTION
|
|
|
|
by Aristotle
|
|
|
|
translated by H. H. Joachim
|
|
|
|
Book I
|
|
|
|
1
|
|
|
|
OUR next task is to study coming-to-be and passing-away. We are to
|
|
distinguish the causes, and to state the definitions, of these
|
|
processes considered in general-as changes predicable uniformly of all
|
|
the things that come-to-be and pass-away by nature. Further, we are to
|
|
study growth and 'alteration'. We must inquire what each of them is;
|
|
and whether 'alteration' is to be identified with coming-to-be, or
|
|
whether to these different names there correspond two separate
|
|
processes with distinct natures.
|
|
|
|
On this question, indeed, the early philosophers are divided. Some
|
|
of them assert that the so-called 'unqualified coming-to-be' is
|
|
'alteration', while others maintain that 'alteration' and coming-to-be
|
|
are distinct. For those who say that the universe is one something
|
|
(i.e. those who generate all things out of one thing) are bound to
|
|
assert that coming-to-be is 'alteration', and that whatever
|
|
'comes-to-be' in the proper sense of the term is 'being altered':
|
|
but those who make the matter of things more than one must distinguish
|
|
coming-to-be from 'alteration'. To this latter class belong
|
|
Empedocles, Anaxagoras, and Leucippus. And yet Anaxagoras himself
|
|
failed to understand his own utterance. He says, at all events, that
|
|
coming-to-be and passing-away are the same as 'being altered':' yet,
|
|
in common with other thinkers, he affirms that the elements are
|
|
many. Thus Empedocles holds that the corporeal elements are four,
|
|
while all the elements-including those which initiate movement-are six
|
|
in number; whereas Anaxagoras agrees with Leucippus and Democritus
|
|
that the elements are infinite.
|
|
|
|
(Anaxagoras posits as elements the 'homoeomeries', viz. bone, flesh,
|
|
marrow, and everything else which is such that part and whole are
|
|
the same in name and nature; while Democritus and Leucippus say that
|
|
there are indivisible bodies, infinite both in number and in the
|
|
varieties of their shapes, of which everything else is composed-the
|
|
compounds differing one from another according to the shapes,
|
|
'positions', and 'groupings' of their constituents.)
|
|
|
|
For the views of the school of Anaxagoras seem diametrically opposed
|
|
to those of the followers of Empedocles. Empedocles says that Fire,
|
|
Water, Air, and Earth are four elements, and are thus 'simple'
|
|
rather than flesh, bone, and bodies which, like these, are
|
|
'homoeomeries'. But the followers of Anaxagoras regard the
|
|
'homoeomeries' as 'simple' and elements, whilst they affirm that
|
|
Earth, Fire, Water, and Air are composite; for each of these is
|
|
(according to them) a 'common seminary' of all the 'homoeomeries'.
|
|
|
|
Those, then, who construct all things out of a single element,
|
|
must maintain that coming-tobe and passing-away are 'alteration'.
|
|
For they must affirm that the underlying something always remains
|
|
identical and one; and change of such a substratum is what we call
|
|
'altering' Those, on the other hand, who make the ultimate kinds of
|
|
things more than one, must maintain that 'alteration' is distinct from
|
|
coming-to-be: for coming-to-be and passingaway result from the
|
|
consilience and the dissolution of the many kinds. That is why
|
|
Empedocles too uses language to this effect, when he says 'There is no
|
|
coming-to-be of anything, but only a mingling and a divorce of what
|
|
has been mingled'. Thus it is clear (i) that to describe
|
|
coming-to-be and passing-away in these terms is in accordance with
|
|
their fundamental assumption, and (ii) that they do in fact so
|
|
describe them: nevertheless, they too must recognize 'alteration' as a
|
|
fact distinct from coming to-be, though it is impossible for them to
|
|
do so consistently with what they say.
|
|
|
|
That we are right in this criticism is easy to perceive. For
|
|
'alteration' is a fact of observation. While the substance of the
|
|
thing remains unchanged, we see it 'altering' just as we see in it the
|
|
changes of magnitude called 'growth' and 'diminution'. Nevertheless,
|
|
the statements of those who posit more 'original reals' than one
|
|
make 'alteration' impossible. For 'alteration, as we assert, takes
|
|
place in respect to certain qualities: and these qualities (I mean,
|
|
e.g. hot-cold, white-black, dry-moist, soft-hard, and so forth) are,
|
|
all of them, differences characterizing the 'elements'. The actual
|
|
words of Empedocles may be quoted in illustration-
|
|
|
|
The sun everywhere bright to see, and hot,
|
|
|
|
The rain everywhere dark and cold;
|
|
|
|
and he distinctively characterizes his remaining elements in a similar
|
|
manner. Since, therefore, it is not possible for Fire to become Water,
|
|
or Water to become Earth, neither will it be possible for anything
|
|
white to become black, or anything soft to become hard; and the same
|
|
argument applies to all the other qualities. Yet this is what
|
|
'alteration' essentially is.
|
|
|
|
It follows, as an obvious corollary, that a single matter must
|
|
always be assumed as underlying the contrary 'poles' of any change
|
|
whether change of place, or growth and diminution, or 'alteration';
|
|
further, that the being of this matter and the being of 'alteration'
|
|
stand and fall together. For if the change is 'alteration', then the
|
|
substratum is a single element; i.e. all things which admit of
|
|
change into one another have a single matter. And, conversely, if
|
|
the substratum of the changing things is one, there is 'alteration'.
|
|
|
|
Empedocles, indeed, seems to contradict his own statements as well
|
|
as the observed facts. For he denies that any one of his elements
|
|
comes-to-be out of any other, insisting on the contrary that they
|
|
are the things out of which everything else comes-to-be; and yet
|
|
(having brought the entirety of existing things, except Strife,
|
|
together into one) he maintains, simultaneously with this denial, that
|
|
each thing once more comes-to-be out of the One. Hence it was
|
|
clearly out of a One that this came-to-be Water, and that Fire,
|
|
various portions of it being separated off by certain characteristic
|
|
differences or qualities-as indeed he calls the sun 'white and hot',
|
|
and the earth 'heavy and hard'. If, therefore, these characteristic
|
|
differences be taken away (for they can be taken away, since they
|
|
came-to-be), it will clearly be inevitable for Earth to come to-be out
|
|
of Water and Water out of Earth, and for each of the other elements to
|
|
undergo a similar transformation-not only then, but also now-if, and
|
|
because, they change their qualities. And, to judge by what he says,
|
|
the qualities are such that they can be 'attached' to things and can
|
|
again be 'separated' from them, especially since Strife and Love are
|
|
still fighting with one another for the mastery. It was owing to
|
|
this same conflict that the elements were generated from a One at
|
|
the former period. I say 'generated', for presumably Fire, Earth,
|
|
and Water had no distinctive existence at all while merged in one.
|
|
|
|
There is another obscurity in the theory Empedocles. Are we to
|
|
regard the One as his 'original real'? Or is it the Many-i.e. Fire and
|
|
Earth, and the bodies co-ordinate with these? For the One is an
|
|
'element' in so far as it underlies the process as matter-as that
|
|
out of which Earth and Fire come-to-be through a change of qualities
|
|
due to 'the motion'. On the other hand, in so far as the One results
|
|
from composition (by a consilience of the Many), whereas they result
|
|
from disintegration the Many are more 'elementary' than the One, and
|
|
prior to it in their nature.
|
|
|
|
2
|
|
|
|
We have therefore to discuss the whole subject of 'unqualified'
|
|
coming-to-be and passingaway; we have to inquire whether these changes
|
|
do or do not occur and, if they occur, to explain the precise
|
|
conditions of their occurrence. We must also discuss the remaining
|
|
forms of change, viz. growth and 'alteration'. For though, no doubt,
|
|
Plato investigated the conditions under which things come-to-be and
|
|
pass-away, he confined his inquiry to these changes; and he
|
|
discussed not all coming-to-be, but only that of the elements. He
|
|
asked no questions as to how flesh or bones, or any of the other
|
|
similar compound things, come-to-be; nor again did he examine the
|
|
conditions under which 'alteration' or growth are attributable to
|
|
things.
|
|
|
|
A similar criticism applies to all our predecessors with the
|
|
single exception of Democritus. Not one of them penetrated below the
|
|
surface or made a thorough examination of a single one of the
|
|
problems. Democritus, however, does seem not only to have thought
|
|
carefully about all the problems, but also to be distinguished from
|
|
the outset by his method. For, as we are saying, none of the other
|
|
philosophers made any definite statement about growth, except such
|
|
as any amateur might have made. They said that things grow 'by the
|
|
accession of like to like', but they did not proceed to explain the
|
|
manner of this accession. Nor did they give any account of
|
|
'combination': and they neglected almost every single one of the
|
|
remaining problems, offering no explanation, e.g. of 'action' or
|
|
'passion' how in physical actions one thing acts and the other
|
|
undergoes action. Democritus and Leucippus, however, postulate the
|
|
'figures', and make 'alteration' and coming-to-be result from them.
|
|
They explain coming-to-be and passing-away by their 'dissociation' and
|
|
'association', but 'alteration' by their 'grouping' and 'Position'.
|
|
And since they thought that the 'truth lay in the appearance, and
|
|
the appearances are conflicting and infinitely many, they made the
|
|
'figures' infinite in number. Hence-owing to the changes of the
|
|
compound-the same thing seems different and conflicting to different
|
|
people: it is 'transposed' by a small additional ingredient, and
|
|
appears utterly other by the 'transposition' of a single
|
|
constituent. For Tragedy and Comedy are both composed of the same
|
|
letters.
|
|
|
|
Since almost all our predecessors think (i) that coming-to-be is
|
|
distinct from 'alteration', and (ii) that, whereas things 'alter' by
|
|
change of their qualities, it is by 'association' and 'dissociation'
|
|
that they come-to-be and pass-away, we must concentrate our
|
|
attention on these theses. For they lead to many perplexing and
|
|
well-grounded dilemmas. If, on the one hand, coming-to-be is
|
|
'association', many impossible consequences result: and yet there
|
|
are other arguments, not easy to unravel, which force the conclusion
|
|
upon us that coming-to-be cannot possibly be anything else. If, on the
|
|
other hand, coming-to-be is not 'association', either there is no such
|
|
thing as coming-to-be at all or it is 'alteration': or else we must
|
|
endeavour to unravel this dilemma too-and a stubborn one we shall find
|
|
it. The fundamental question, in dealing with all these
|
|
difficulties, is this: 'Do things come-to-be and "alter" and grow, and
|
|
undergo the contrary changes, because the primary "reals" are
|
|
indivisible magnitudes? Or is no magnitude indivisible?' For the
|
|
answer we give to this question makes the greatest difference. And
|
|
again, if the primary 'reals' are indivisible magnitudes, are these
|
|
bodies, as Democritus and Leucippus maintain? Or are they planes, as
|
|
is asserted in the Timaeus?
|
|
|
|
To resolve bodies into planes and no further-this, as we have also
|
|
remarked elsewhere, in itself a paradox. Hence there is more to be
|
|
said for the view that there are indivisible bodies. Yet even these
|
|
involve much of paradox. Still, as we have said, it is possible to
|
|
construct 'alteration' and coming-to-be with them, if one 'transposes'
|
|
the same by 'turning' and 'intercontact', and by 'the varieties of the
|
|
figures', as Democritus does. (His denial of the reality of colour
|
|
is a corollary from this position: for, according to him, things get
|
|
coloured by 'turning' of the 'figures'.) But the possibility of such a
|
|
construction no longer exists for those who divide bodies into planes.
|
|
For nothing except solids results from putting planes together: they
|
|
do not even attempt to generate any quality from them.
|
|
|
|
Lack of experience diminishes our power of taking a comprehensive
|
|
view of the admitted facts. Hence those who dwell in intimate
|
|
association with nature and its phenomena grow more and more able to
|
|
formulate, as the foundations of their theories, principles such as to
|
|
admit of a wide and coherent development: while those whom devotion to
|
|
abstract discussions has rendered unobservant of the facts are too
|
|
ready to dogmatize on the basis of a few observations. The rival
|
|
treatments of the subject now before us will serve to illustrate how
|
|
great is the difference between a 'scientific' and a 'dialectical'
|
|
method of inquiry. For, whereas the Platonists argue that there must
|
|
be atomic magnitudes 'because otherwise "The Triangle" will be more
|
|
than one', Democritus would appear to have been convinced by arguments
|
|
appropriate to the subject, i.e. drawn from the science of nature. Our
|
|
meaning will become clear as we proceed. For to suppose that a body
|
|
(i.e. a magnitude) is divisible through and through, and that this
|
|
division is possible, involves a difficulty. What will there be in the
|
|
body which escapes the division?
|
|
|
|
If it is divisible through and through, and if this division is
|
|
possible, then it might be, at one and the same moment, divided
|
|
through and through, even though the dividings had not been effected
|
|
simultaneously: and the actual occurrence of this result would involve
|
|
no impossibility. Hence the same principle will apply whenever a
|
|
body is by nature divisible through and through, whether by bisection,
|
|
or generally by any method whatever: nothing impossible will have
|
|
resulted if it has actually been divided-not even if it has been
|
|
divided into innumerable parts, themselves divided innumerable
|
|
times. Nothing impossible will have resulted, though perhaps nobody in
|
|
fact could so divide it.
|
|
|
|
Since, therefore, the be dy is divisible through and through, let it
|
|
have been divided. What, then, will remain? A magnitude? No: that is
|
|
impossible, since then there will be something not divided, whereas ex
|
|
hypothesis the body was divisible through and through. But if it be
|
|
admitted that neither a body nor a magnitude will remain, and yet
|
|
division is to take place, the constituents of the body will either be
|
|
points (i.e. without magnitude) or absolutely nothing. If its
|
|
constituents are nothings, then it might both come-to-be out of
|
|
nothings and exist as a composite of nothings: and thus presumably the
|
|
whole body will be nothing but an appearance. But if it consists of
|
|
points, a similar absurdity will result: it will not possess any
|
|
magnitude. For when the points were in contact and coincided to form a
|
|
single magnitude, they did not make the whole any bigger (since,
|
|
when the body was divided into two or more parts, the whole was not
|
|
a bit smaller or bigger than it was before the division): hence,
|
|
even if all the points be put together, they will not make any
|
|
magnitude.
|
|
|
|
But suppose that, as the body is being divided, a minute section-a
|
|
piece of sawdust, as it were-is extracted, and that in this sense-a
|
|
body 'comes away' from the magnitude, evading the division. Even
|
|
then the same argument applies. For in what sense is that section
|
|
divisible? But if what 'came away' was not a body but a separable form
|
|
or quality, and if the magnitude is 'points or contacts thus
|
|
qualified': it is paradoxical that a magnitude should consist of
|
|
elements, which are not magnitudes. Moreover, where will the points
|
|
be? And are they motionless or moving? And every contact is always a
|
|
contact of two somethings, i.e. there is always something besides
|
|
the contact or the division or the point.
|
|
|
|
These, then, are the difficulties resulting from the supposition
|
|
that any and every body, whatever its size, is divisible through and
|
|
through. There is, besides, this further consideration. If, having
|
|
divided a piece of wood or anything else, I put it together, it is
|
|
again equal to what it was, and is one. Clearly this is so, whatever
|
|
the point at which I cut the wood. The wood, therefore, has been
|
|
divided potentially through and through. What, then, is there in the
|
|
wood besides the division? For even if we suppose there is some
|
|
quality, yet how is the wood dissolved into such constituents and
|
|
how does it come-to-be out of them? Or how are such constituents
|
|
separated so as to exist apart from one another? Since, therefore,
|
|
it is impossible for magnitudes to consist of contacts or points,
|
|
there must be indivisible bodies and magnitudes. Yet, if we do
|
|
postulate the latter, we are confronted with equally impossible
|
|
consequences, which we have examined in other works.' But we must
|
|
try to disentangle these perplexities, and must therefore formulate
|
|
the whole problem over again.
|
|
|
|
On the one hand, then, it is in no way paradoxical that every
|
|
perceptible body should be indivisible as well as divisible at any and
|
|
every point. For the second predicate will at. tach to it potentially,
|
|
but the first actually. On the other hand, it would seem to be
|
|
impossible for a body to be, even potentially, divisible at all points
|
|
simultaneously. For if it were possible, then it might actually occur,
|
|
with the result, not that the body would simultaneously be actually
|
|
both (indivisible and divided), but that it would be simultaneously
|
|
divided at any and every point. Consequently, nothing will remain
|
|
and the body will have passed-away into what is incorporeal: and so it
|
|
might come-to-be again either out of points or absolutely out of
|
|
nothing. And how is that possible?
|
|
|
|
But now it is obvious that a body is in fact divided into
|
|
separable magnitudes which are smaller at each division-into
|
|
magnitudes which fall apart from one another and are actually
|
|
separated. Hence (it is urged) the process of dividing a body part
|
|
by part is not a 'breaking up' which could continue ad infinitum;
|
|
nor can a body be simultaneously divided at every point, for that is
|
|
not possible; but there is a limit, beyond which the 'breaking up'
|
|
cannot proceed. The necessary consequence-especially if coming-to-be
|
|
and passing-away are to take place by 'association' and 'dissociation'
|
|
respectively-is that a body must contain atomic magnitudes which are
|
|
invisible. Such is the argument which is believed to establish the
|
|
necessity of atomic magnitudes: we must now show that it conceals a
|
|
faulty inference, and exactly where it conceals it.
|
|
|
|
For, since point is not 'immediately-next' to point, magnitudes
|
|
are 'divisible through and through' in one sense, and yet not in
|
|
another. When, however, it is admitted that a magnitude is
|
|
'divisible through and through', it is thought there is a point not
|
|
only anywhere, but also everywhere, in it: hence it is supposed to
|
|
follow, from the admission, that the magnitude must be divided away
|
|
into nothing. For it is supposed-there is a point everywhere within
|
|
it, so that it consists either of contacts or of points. But it is
|
|
only in one sense that the magnitude is 'divisible through and
|
|
through', viz. in so far as there is one point anywhere within it
|
|
and all its points are everywhere within it if you take them singly
|
|
one by one. But there are not more points than one anywhere within it,
|
|
for the points are not 'consecutive': hence it is not simultaneously
|
|
'divisible through and through'. For if it were, then, if it be
|
|
divisible at its centre, it will be divisible also at a point
|
|
'immediately-next' to its centre. But it is not so divisible: for
|
|
position is not 'immediately-next' to position, nor point to
|
|
point-in other words, division is not 'immediately-next' to
|
|
division, nor composition to composition.
|
|
|
|
Hence there are both 'association' and 'dissociation', though
|
|
neither (a) into, and out of, atomic magnitudes (for that involves
|
|
many impossibilities), nor (b) so that division takes place through
|
|
and through-for this would have resulted only if point had been
|
|
'immediately-next' to point: but 'dissociation' takes place into small
|
|
(i.e. relatively small) parts, and 'association' takes place out of
|
|
relatively small parts.
|
|
|
|
It is wrong, however, to suppose, as some assert, that
|
|
coming-to-be and passing-away in the unqualified and complete sense
|
|
are distinctively defined by 'association' and 'dissociation', while
|
|
the change that takes place in what is continuous is 'alteration'.
|
|
On the contrary, this is where the whole error lies. For unqualified
|
|
coming-to-be and passing-away are not effected by 'association' and
|
|
'dissociation'. They take place when a thing changes, from this to
|
|
that, as a whole. But the philosophers we are criticizing suppose that
|
|
all such change is 'alteration': whereas in fact there is a
|
|
difference. For in that which underlies the change there is a factor
|
|
corresponding to the definition and there is a material factor.
|
|
When, then, the change is in these constitutive factors, there will be
|
|
coming-to-be or passing-away: but when it is in the thing's qualities,
|
|
i.e. a change of the thing per accidents, there will be 'alteration'.
|
|
|
|
'Dissociation' and 'association' affect the thing's susceptibility
|
|
to passing-away. For if water has first been 'dissociated' into
|
|
smallish drops, air comes-to-be out of it more quickly: while, if
|
|
drops of water have first been 'associated', air comes-to-be more
|
|
slowly. Our doctrine will become clearer in the sequel.' Meantime,
|
|
so much may be taken as established-viz. that coming-to-be cannot be
|
|
'association', at least not the kind of 'association' some
|
|
philosophers assert it to be.
|
|
|
|
3
|
|
|
|
Now that we have established the preceding distinctions, we must
|
|
first consider whether there is anything which comes-to-be and
|
|
passes-away in the unqualified sense: or whether nothing comes-to-be
|
|
in this strict sense, but everything always comes-to-be something
|
|
and out of something-I mean, e.g. comes-to-be-healthy out of being-ill
|
|
and ill out of being-healthy, comes-to-be-small out of being big and
|
|
big out of being-small, and so on in every other instance. For if
|
|
there is to be coming-to-be without qualification, 'something'
|
|
must-without qualification-'come-to-be out of not-being', so that it
|
|
would be true to say that 'not-being is an attribute of some
|
|
things'. For qualified coming-to-be is a process out of qualified
|
|
not-being (e.g. out of not-white or not-beautiful), but unqualified
|
|
coming-to-be is a process out of unqualified not-being.
|
|
|
|
Now 'unqulified' means either (i) the primary predication within
|
|
each Category, or (ii) the universal, i.e. the all-comprehensive,
|
|
predication. Hence, if'unqualified not-being 'means the negation of
|
|
'being' in the sense of the primary term of the Category in
|
|
question, we shall have, in 'unqualified coming-to-be', a coming-to-be
|
|
of a substance out of not-substance. But that which is not a substance
|
|
or a 'this' clearly cannot possess predicates drawn from any of the
|
|
other Categories either-e.g. we cannot attribute to it any quality,
|
|
quantity, or position. Otherwise, properties would admit of
|
|
existence in separation from substances. If, on the other hand,
|
|
'unqualified not-being' means 'what is not in any sense at all', it
|
|
will be a universal negation of all forms of being, so that what
|
|
comes-to-be will have to come-to-be out of nothing.
|
|
|
|
Although we have dealt with these problems at greater length in
|
|
another work,where we have set forth the difficulties and
|
|
established the distinguishing definitions, the following concise
|
|
restatement of our results must here be offered: In one sense things
|
|
come-to-be out of that which has no 'being' without qualification: yet
|
|
in another sense they come-to-be always out of what is'. For
|
|
coming-to-be necessarily implies the pre-existence of something
|
|
which potentially 'is', but actually 'is not'; and this something is
|
|
spoken of both as 'being' and as 'not-being'.
|
|
|
|
These distinctions may be taken as established: but even then it
|
|
is extraordinarily difficult to see how there can be 'unqualified
|
|
coming-to-be' (whether we suppose it to occur out of what
|
|
potentially 'is', or in some other way), and we must recall this
|
|
problem for further examination. For the question might be raised
|
|
whether substance (i.e. the 'this') comes-to-be at all. Is it not
|
|
rather the 'such', the 'so great', or the 'somewhere', which
|
|
comes-to-be? And the same question might be raised about
|
|
'passing-away' also. For if a substantial thing comes-to-be, it is
|
|
clear that there will 'be' (not actually, but potentially) a
|
|
substance, out of which its coming-to-be will proceed and into which
|
|
the thing that is passing-away will necessarily change. Then will
|
|
any predicate belonging to the remaining Categories attach actually to
|
|
this presupposed substance? In other words, will that which is only
|
|
potentially a 'this' (which only potentially is), while without the
|
|
qualification 'potentially' it is not a 'this' (i.e. is not), possess,
|
|
e.g. any determinate size or quality or position? For (i) if it
|
|
possesses none of these determinations actually, but all of them
|
|
only potentially, the result is first that a being, which is not a
|
|
determinate being, is capable of separate existence; and in addition
|
|
that coming-to-be proceeds out of nothing pre-existing-a thesis which,
|
|
more than any other, preoccupied and alarmed the earliest
|
|
philosophers. On the other hand (ii) if, although it is not a 'this
|
|
somewhat' or a substance, it is to possess some of the remaining
|
|
determinations quoted above, then (as we said)' properties will be
|
|
separable from substances.
|
|
|
|
We must therefore concentrate all our powers on the discussion of
|
|
these difficulties and on the solution of a further question-viz. What
|
|
is the cause of the perpetuity of coming-to-be? Why is there always
|
|
unqualified, as well as partial, coming-to-be? Cause' in this
|
|
connexion has two senses. It means (i) the source from which, as we
|
|
say, the process 'originates', and (ii) the matter. It is the material
|
|
cause that we have here to state. For, as to the other cause, we
|
|
have already explained (in our treatise on Motion that it involves (a)
|
|
something immovable through all time and (b) something always being
|
|
moved. And the accurate treatment of the first of these-of the
|
|
immovable 'originative source'-belongs to the province of the other,
|
|
or 'prior', philosophy: while as regards 'that which sets everything
|
|
else in motion by being itself continuously moved', we shall have to
|
|
explain later' which amongst the so-called 'specific' causes
|
|
exhibits this character. But at present we are to state the material
|
|
cause-the cause classed under the head of matter-to which it is due
|
|
that passing-away and coming-to-be never fail to occur in Nature.
|
|
For perhaps, if we succeed in clearing up this question, it will
|
|
simultaneously become clear what account we ought to give of that
|
|
which perplexed us just now, i.e. of unqualified passingaway and
|
|
coming-to-be.
|
|
|
|
Our new question too-viz. 'what is the cause of the unbroken
|
|
continuity of coming-to-be?'-is sufficiently perplexing, if in fact
|
|
what passes-away vanishes into 'what is not' and 'what is not' is
|
|
nothing (since 'what is not' is neither a thing, nor possessed of a
|
|
quality or quantity, nor in any place). If, then, some one of the
|
|
things 'which are' constantly disappearing, why has not the whole of
|
|
'what is' been used up long ago and vanished away assuming of course
|
|
that the material of all the several comings-to-be was finite? For,
|
|
presumably, the unfailing continuity of coming-to-be cannot be
|
|
attributed to the infinity of the material. That is impossible, for
|
|
nothing is actually infinite. A thing is infinite only potentially,
|
|
i.e. the dividing of it can continue indefinitely: so that we should
|
|
have to suppose there is only one kind of coming-to-be in the
|
|
world-viz. one which never fails, because it is such that what
|
|
comes-to-be is on each successive occasion smaller than before. But in
|
|
fact this is not what we see occurring.
|
|
|
|
Why, then, is this form of change necessarily ceaseless? Is it
|
|
because the passing-away of this is a coming-to-be of something
|
|
else, and the coming-to-be of this a passing-away of something else?
|
|
|
|
The cause implied in this solution must no doubt be considered
|
|
adequate to account for coming-to-be and passing-away in their general
|
|
character as they occur in all existing things alike. Yet, if the same
|
|
process is a coming to-be of this but a passing-away of that, and a
|
|
passing-away of this but a coming-to-be of that, why are some things
|
|
said to come-to-be and pass-away without qualification, but others
|
|
only with a qualification?
|
|
|
|
The distinction must be investigated once more, for it demands
|
|
some explanation. (It is applied in a twofold manner.) For (i) we
|
|
say 'it is now passing-away' without qualification, and not merely
|
|
'this is passing-away': and we call this change 'coming-to-be', and
|
|
that 'passing-away', without qualification. And (ii) so-and-so
|
|
'comes-to-be-something', but does not 'come-to-be' without
|
|
qualification; for we say that the student 'comes-to-be-learned',
|
|
not 'comes-to-be' without qualification.
|
|
|
|
(i) Now we often divide terms into those which signify a 'this
|
|
somewhat' and those which do not. And (the first form of) the
|
|
distinction, which we are investigating, results from a similar
|
|
division of terms: for it makes a difference into what the changing
|
|
thing changes. Perhaps, e.g. the passage into Fire is 'coming-to-be'
|
|
unqualified, but 'passingaway-of-something' (e.g. Earth): whilst the
|
|
coming-to-be of Earth is qualified (not unqualified) 'coming-to-be',
|
|
though unqualified 'passing-away' (e.g. of Fire). This would be the
|
|
case on the theory set forth in Parmenides: for he says that the
|
|
things into which change takes place are two, and he asserts that
|
|
these two, viz. what is and what is not, are Fire and Earth. Whether
|
|
we postulate these, or other things of a similar kind, makes no
|
|
difference. For we are trying to discover not what undergoes these
|
|
changes, but what is their characteristic manner. The passage, then,
|
|
into what 'is' not except with a qualification is unqualified
|
|
passing-away, while the passage into what 'is' without qualification
|
|
is unqualified coming-to-be. Hence whatever the contrasted 'poles'
|
|
of the changes may be whether Fire and Earth, or some other couple-the
|
|
one of them will be 'a being' and the other 'a not-being'.
|
|
|
|
We have thus stated one characteristic manner in which unqualified
|
|
will be distinguished from qualified coming-to-be and passing-away:
|
|
but they are also distinguished according to the special nature of the
|
|
material of the changing thing. For a material, whose constitutive
|
|
differences signify more a 'this somewhat', is itself more
|
|
'substantial' or 'real': while a material, whose constitutive
|
|
differences signify privation, is 'not real'. (Suppose, e.g. that 'the
|
|
hot' is a positive predication, i.e. a 'form', whereas 'cold' is a
|
|
privation, and that Earth and Fire differ from one another by these
|
|
constitutive differences.)
|
|
|
|
The opinion, however, which most people are inclined to prefer, is
|
|
that the distinction depends upon the difference between 'the
|
|
perceptible' and 'the imperceptible'. Thus, when there is a change
|
|
into perceptible material, people say there is 'coming-to-be'; but
|
|
when there is a change into invisible material, they call it
|
|
'passing-away'. For they distinguish 'what is' and 'what is not' by
|
|
their perceiving and not-perceiving, just as what is knowable 'is' and
|
|
what is unknowable 'is not'-perception on their view having the
|
|
force of knowledge. Hence, just as they deem themselves to live and to
|
|
'be' in virtue of their perceiving or their capacity to perceive, so
|
|
too they deem the things to 'be' qua perceived or perceptible-and in
|
|
this they are in a sense on the track of the truth, though what they
|
|
actually say is not true.
|
|
|
|
Thus unqualified coming-to-be and passingaway turn out to be
|
|
different according to common opinion from what they are in truth. For
|
|
Wind and Air are in truth more real more a 'this somewhat' or a
|
|
'form'-than Earth. But they are less real to perception which explains
|
|
why things are commonly said to 'pass-away' without qualification when
|
|
they change into Wind and Air, and to 'come-to-be' when they change
|
|
into what is tangible, i.e. into Earth.
|
|
|
|
We have now explained why there is 'unqualified coming-to-be'
|
|
(though it is a passingaway-of-something) and 'unqualified passingaway
|
|
(though it is a coming-to-be-of-something). For this distinction of
|
|
appellation depends upon a difference in the material out of which,
|
|
and into which, the changes are effected. It depends either upon
|
|
whether the material is or is not 'substantial', or upon whether it is
|
|
more or less 'substantial', or upon whether it is more or less
|
|
perceptible.
|
|
|
|
(ii) But why are some things said to 'come to-be' without
|
|
qualification, and others only to 'come-to-be-so-and-so', in cases
|
|
different from the one we have been considering where two things
|
|
come-to-be reciprocally out of one another? For at present we have
|
|
explained no more than this:-why, when two things change
|
|
reciprocally into one another, we do not attribute coming-to-be and
|
|
passing-away uniformly to them both, although every coming-to-be is
|
|
a passing-away of something else and every passing-away some other
|
|
thing's coming-to-be. But the question subsequently formulated
|
|
involves a different problem-viz. why, although the learning thing
|
|
is said to 'come-to-be-learned' but not to 'come-tobe' without
|
|
qualification, yet the growing thing is said to 'come-to-be'.
|
|
|
|
The distinction here turns upon the difference of the Categories.
|
|
For some things signify a this somewhat, others a such, and others a
|
|
so-much. Those things, then, which do not signify substance, are not
|
|
said to 'come-to-be' without qualification, but only to
|
|
'come-to-be-so-and-so'. Nevertheless, in all changing things alike, we
|
|
speak of 'coming-to-be' when the thing comes-to-be something in one of
|
|
the two Columns-e.g. in Substance, if it comes-to-be Fire but not if
|
|
it comes-to-be Earth; and in Quality, if it comes-to-be learned but
|
|
not when it comes-to-be ignorant.
|
|
|
|
We have explained why some things come to-be without
|
|
qualification, but not others both in general, and also when the
|
|
changing things are substances and nothing else; and we have stated
|
|
that the substratum is the material cause of the continuous occurrence
|
|
of coming to-be, because it is such as to change from contrary to
|
|
contrary and because, in substances, the coming-to-be of one thing
|
|
is always a passing-away of another, and the passing-away of one thing
|
|
is always another's coming-to-be. But there is no need even to discuss
|
|
the other question we raised-viz. why coming-to-be continues though
|
|
things are constantly being destroyed. For just as people speak of
|
|
'a passing-away' without qualification when a thing has passed into
|
|
what is imperceptible and what in that sense 'is not', so also they
|
|
speak of 'a coming-to-be out of a not-being' when a thing emerges from
|
|
an imperceptible. Whether, therefore, the substratum is or is not
|
|
something, what comes-tobe emerges out of a 'not-being': so that a
|
|
thing comes-to-be out of a not-being' just as much as it
|
|
'passes-away into what is not'. Hence it is reasonable enough that
|
|
coming-to-be should never fail. For coming-to-be is a passing-away
|
|
of 'what is not' and passing-away is a coming to-be of 'what is not'.
|
|
|
|
But what about that which 'is' not except with a qualification? Is
|
|
it one of the two contrary poles of the chang-e.g. Earth (i.e. the
|
|
heavy) a 'not-being', but Fire (i.e. the light) a 'being'? Or, on
|
|
the contrary, does what is 'include Earth as well as Fire, whereas
|
|
what is not' is matter-the matter of Earth and Fire alike? And
|
|
again, is the matter of each different? Or is it the same, since
|
|
otherwise they would not come-to-be reciprocally out of one another,
|
|
i.e. contraries out of contraries? For these things-Fire, Earth,
|
|
Water, Air-are characterized by 'the contraries'.
|
|
|
|
Perhaps the solution is that their matter is in one sense the
|
|
same, but in another sense different. For that which underlies them,
|
|
whatever its nature may be qua underlying them, is the same: but its
|
|
actual being is not the same. So much, then, on these topics.
|
|
|
|
4
|
|
|
|
Next we must state what the difference is between coming-to-be and
|
|
'alteration'-for we maintain that these changes are distinct from
|
|
one another.
|
|
|
|
Since, then, we must distinguish (a) the substratum, and (b) the
|
|
property whose nature it is to be predicated of the substratum; and
|
|
since change of each of these occurs; there is 'alteration' when the
|
|
substratum is perceptible and persists, but changes in its own
|
|
properties, the properties in question being opposed to one another
|
|
either as contraries or as intermediates. The body, e.g. although
|
|
persisting as the same body, is now healthy and now ill; and the
|
|
bronze is now spherical and at another time angular, and yet remains
|
|
the same bronze. But when nothing perceptible persists in its identity
|
|
as a substratum, and the thing changes as a whole (when e.g. the
|
|
seed as a whole is converted into blood, or water into air, or air
|
|
as a whole into water), such an occurrence is no longer
|
|
'alteration'. It is a coming-to-be of one substance and a passing-away
|
|
of the other-especially if the change proceeds from an imperceptible
|
|
something to something perceptible (either to touch or to all the
|
|
senses), as when water comes-to-be out of, or passes-away into, air:
|
|
for air is pretty well imperceptible. If, however, in such cases,
|
|
any property (being one of a pair of contraries) persists, in the
|
|
thing that has come-to-be, the same as it was in the thing which has
|
|
passedaway-if, e.g. when water comes-to-be out of air, both are
|
|
transparent or cold-the second thing, into which the first changes,
|
|
must not be a property of this persistent identical something.
|
|
Otherwise the change will be 'alteration.' Suppose, e.g. that the
|
|
musical man passed-away and an unmusical man came-tobe, and that the
|
|
man persists as something identical. Now, if 'musicalness and
|
|
unmusicalness' had not been a property essentially inhering in man,
|
|
these changes would have been a coming-to-be of unmusicalness and a
|
|
passing-away of musicalness: but in fact 'musicalness and
|
|
unmusicalness' are a property of the persistent identity, viz. man.
|
|
(Hence, as regards man, these changes are 'modifications'; though,
|
|
as regards musical man and unmusical man, they are a passing-away
|
|
and a coming-to-be.) Consequently such changes are 'alteration.'
|
|
When the change from contrary to contrary is in quantity, it is
|
|
'growth and diminution'; when it is in place, it is 'motion'; when
|
|
it is in property, i.e. in quality, it is 'alteration': but, when
|
|
nothing persists, of which the resultant is a property (or an
|
|
'accident' in any sense of the term), it is 'coming-to-be', and the
|
|
converse change is 'passing-away'.
|
|
|
|
'Matter', in the most proper sense of the term, is to be
|
|
identified with the substratum which is receptive of coming-to-be
|
|
and passingaway: but the substratum of the remaining kinds of change
|
|
is also, in a certain sense, 'matter', because all these substrata are
|
|
receptive of 'contrarieties' of some kind. So much, then, as an answer
|
|
to the questions (i) whether coming-to-be 'is' or 'is not'-i.e. what
|
|
are the precise conditions of its occurrence and (ii) what
|
|
'alteration' is: but we have still to treat of growth.
|
|
|
|
5
|
|
|
|
We must explain (i) wherein growth differs from coming-to-be and
|
|
from 'alteration', and ii) what is the process of growing and the
|
|
sprocess of diminishing in each and all of the things that grow and
|
|
diminish.
|
|
|
|
Hence our first question is this: Do these changes differ from one
|
|
another solely because of a difference in their respective
|
|
'spheres'? In other words, do they differ because, while a change from
|
|
this to that (viz. from potential to actual substance) is
|
|
coming-to-be, a change in the sphere of magnitude is growth and one in
|
|
the sphere of quality is 'alteration'-both growth and 'alteration'
|
|
being changes from what is-potentially to what is-actually magnitude
|
|
and quality respectively? Or is there also a difference in the
|
|
manner of the change, since it is evident that, whereas neither what
|
|
is 'altering' nor what is coming-to-be necessarily changes its
|
|
place, what is growing or diminishing changes its spatial position
|
|
of necessity, though in a different manner from that in which the
|
|
moving thing does so? For that which is being moved changes its
|
|
place as a whole: but the growing thing changes its place like a metal
|
|
that is being beaten, retaining its position as a whole while its
|
|
parts change their places. They change their places, but not in the
|
|
same way as the parts of a revolving globe. For the parts of the globe
|
|
change their places while the whole continues to occupy an equal
|
|
place: but the parts of the rowing thing expand over an
|
|
ever-increasing place and the parts of the diminishing thing
|
|
contract within an ever-diminishing area.
|
|
|
|
It is clear, then, that these changes-the changes of that which is
|
|
coming-to-be, of that which is 'altering', and of that which is
|
|
growing-differ in manner as well as in sphere. But how are we to
|
|
conceive the 'sphere' of the change which is growth and diminution?
|
|
The sphere' of growing and diminishing is believed to be magnitude.
|
|
Are we to suppose that body and magnitude come-to-be out of
|
|
something which, though potentially magnitude and body, is actually
|
|
incorporeal and devoid of magnitude? And since this description may be
|
|
understood in two different ways, in which of these two ways are we to
|
|
apply it to the process of growth? Is the matter, out of which
|
|
growth takes place, (i) 'separate' and existing alone by itself, or
|
|
(ii) 'separate' but contained in another body?
|
|
|
|
Perhaps it is impossible for growth to take place in either of these
|
|
ways. For since the matter is 'separate', either (a) it will occupy no
|
|
place (as if it were a point), or (b) it will be a 'void', i.e. a
|
|
non-perceptible body. But the first of these alternatives is
|
|
impossible. For since what comes-to-be out of this incorporeal and
|
|
sizeless something will always be 'somewhere', it too must be
|
|
'somewhere'-either intrinsically or indirectly. And the second
|
|
alternative necessarily implies that the matter is contained in some
|
|
other body. But if it is to be 'in' another body and yet remains
|
|
'separate' in such a way that it is in no sense a part of that body
|
|
(neither a part of its substantial being nor an 'accident' of it),
|
|
many impossibilities will result. It is as if we were to suppose
|
|
that when, e.g. air comes-to-be out of water the process were due
|
|
not to a change of the but to the matter of the air being 'contained
|
|
in' the water as in a vessel. This is impossible. For (i) there is
|
|
nothing to prevent an indeterminate number of matters being thus
|
|
'contained in' the water, so that they might come-to-be actually an
|
|
indeterminate quantity of air; and (ii) we do not in fact see air
|
|
coming-to-be out of water in this fashion, viz. withdrawing out of
|
|
it and leaving it unchanged.
|
|
|
|
It is therefore better to suppose that in all instances of
|
|
coming-to-be the matter is inseparable, being numerically identical
|
|
and one with the 'containing' body, though isolable from it by
|
|
definition. But the same reasons also forbid us to regard the
|
|
matter, out of which the body comes-to-be, as points or lines. The
|
|
matter is that of which points and lines are limits, and it is
|
|
something that can never exist without quality and without form.
|
|
|
|
Now it is no doubt true, as we have also established elsewhere,'
|
|
that one thing 'comes-tobe' (in the unqualified sense) out of
|
|
another thing: and further it is true that the efficient cause of
|
|
its coming-to-be is either (i) an actual thing (which is the same as
|
|
the effect either generically-or the efficient cause of the
|
|
coming-to-be of a hard thing is not a hard thing or specifically, as
|
|
e.g. fire is the efficient cause of the coming-to-be of fire or one
|
|
man of the birth of another), or (ii) an actuality. Nevertheless,
|
|
since there is also a matter out of which corporeal substance itself
|
|
comes-to-be (corporeal substance, however, already characterized as
|
|
such-and-such a determinate body, for there is no such thing as body
|
|
in general), this same matter is also the matter of magnitude and
|
|
quality-being separable from these matters by definition, but not
|
|
separable in place unless Qualities are, in their turn, separable.
|
|
|
|
It is evident, from the preceding development and discussion of
|
|
difficulties, that growth is not a change out of something which,
|
|
though potentially a magnitude, actually possesses no magnitude.
|
|
For, if it were, the 'void' would exist in separation; but we have
|
|
explained in a former work' that this is impossible. Moreover, a
|
|
change of that kind is not peculiarly distinctive of growth, but
|
|
characterizes coming-to-be as such or in general. For growth is an
|
|
increase, and diminution is a lessening, of the magnitude which is
|
|
there already-that, indeed, is why the growing thing must possess some
|
|
magnitude. Hence growth must not be regarded as a process from a
|
|
matter without magnitude to an actuality of magnitude: for this
|
|
would be a body's coming-to-be rather than its growth.
|
|
|
|
We must therefore come to closer quarters with the subject of our
|
|
inquiry. We must grapple' with it (as it were) from its beginning, and
|
|
determine the precise character of the growing and diminishing whose
|
|
causes we are investigating.
|
|
|
|
It is evident (i) that any and every part of the growing thing has
|
|
increased, and that similarly in diminution every part has become
|
|
smaller: also (ii) that a thing grows by the accession, and diminishes
|
|
by the departure, of something. Hence it must grow by the accession
|
|
either (a) of something incorporeal or (b) of a body. Now, if (a) it
|
|
grows by the accession of something incorporeal, there will exist
|
|
separate a void: but (as we have stated before)' is impossible for a
|
|
matter of magnitude to exist 'separate'. If, on the other hand (b)
|
|
it grows by the accession of a body, there will be two bodies-that
|
|
which grows and that which increases it-in the same place: and this
|
|
too is impossible.
|
|
|
|
But neither is it open to us to say that growth or diminution occurs
|
|
in the way in which e.g. air is generated from water. For, although
|
|
the volume has then become greater, the change will not be growth, but
|
|
a coming to-be of the one-viz. of that into which the change is taking
|
|
place-and a passing-away of the contrasted body. It is not a growth of
|
|
either. Nothing grows in the process; unless indeed there be something
|
|
common to both things (to that which is coming-to-be and to that which
|
|
passed-away), e.g. 'body', and this grows. The water has not grown,
|
|
nor has the air: but the former has passed-away and the latter has
|
|
come-to-be, and-if anything has grown-there has been a growth of
|
|
'body.' Yet this too is impossible. For our account of growth must
|
|
preserve the characteristics of that which is growing and diminishing.
|
|
And these characteristics are three: (i) any and every part of the
|
|
growing magnitude is made bigger (e.g. if flesh grows, every
|
|
particle of the flesh gets bigger), (ii) by the accession of
|
|
something, and (iii) in such a way that the growing thing is preserved
|
|
and persists. For whereas a thing does not persist in the processes of
|
|
unqualified coming-to-be or passing-away, that which grows or 'alters'
|
|
persists in its identity through the 'altering' and through the
|
|
growing or diminishing, though the quality (in 'alteration') and the
|
|
size (in growth) do not remain the same. Now if the generation of
|
|
air from water is to be regarded as growth, a thing might grow without
|
|
the accession (and without the persistence) of anything, and
|
|
diminish without the departure of anything-and that which grows need
|
|
not persist. But this characteristic must be preserved: for the growth
|
|
we are discussing has been assumed to be thus characterized.
|
|
|
|
One might raise a further difficulty. What is 'that which grows'? Is
|
|
it that to which something is added? If, e.g. a man grows in his shin,
|
|
is it the shin which is greater-but not that 'whereby' he grows,
|
|
viz. not the food? Then why have not both 'grown'? For when A is added
|
|
to B, both A and B are greater, as when you mix wine with water; for
|
|
each ingredient is alike increased in volume. Perhaps the
|
|
explanation is that the substance of the one remains unchanged, but
|
|
the substance of the other (viz. of the food) does not. For indeed,
|
|
even in the mixture of wine and water, it is the prevailing ingredient
|
|
which is said to have increased in volume. We say, e.g. that the
|
|
wine has increased, because the whole mixture acts as wine but not
|
|
as water. A similar principle applies also to 'alteration'. Flesh is
|
|
said to have been 'altered' if, while its character and substance
|
|
remain, some one of its essential properties, which was not there
|
|
before, now qualifies it: on the other hand, that 'whereby' it has
|
|
been 'altered' may have undergone no change, though sometimes it too
|
|
has been affected. The altering agent, however, and the originative
|
|
source of the process are in the growing thing and in that which is
|
|
being 'altered': for the efficient cause is in these. No doubt the
|
|
food, which has come in, may sometimes expand as well as the body that
|
|
has consumed it (that is so, e.g. if, after having come in, a food
|
|
is converted into wind), but when it has undergone this change it
|
|
has passedaway: and the efficient cause is not in the food.
|
|
|
|
We have now developed the difficulties sufficiently and must
|
|
therefore try to find a solution of the problem. Our solution must
|
|
preserve intact the three characteristics of growth-that the growing
|
|
thing persists, that it grows by the accession (and diminishes by
|
|
the departure) of something, and further that every perceptible
|
|
particle of it has become either larger or smaller. We must
|
|
recognize also (a) that the growing body is not 'void' and that yet
|
|
there are not two magnitudes in the same place, and (b) that it does
|
|
not grow by the accession of something incorporeal.
|
|
|
|
Two preliminary distinctions will prepare us to grasp the cause of
|
|
growth. We must note (i) that the organic parts grow by the growth
|
|
of the tissues (for every organ is composed of these as its
|
|
constituents); and (ii) that flesh, bone, and every such part-like
|
|
every other thing which has its form immersed in matter-has a
|
|
twofold nature: for the form as well as the matter is called 'flesh'
|
|
or 'bone'.
|
|
|
|
Now, that any and every part of the tissue qua form should
|
|
grow-and grow by the accession of something-is possible, but not
|
|
that any and every part of the tissue qua matter should do so. For
|
|
we must think of the tissue after the image of flowing water that is
|
|
measured by one and the same measure: particle after particle
|
|
comes-to-be, and each successive particle is different. And it is in
|
|
this sense that the matter of the flesh grows, some flowing out and
|
|
some flowing in fresh; not in the sense that fresh matter accedes to
|
|
every particle of it. There is, however, an accession to every part of
|
|
its figure or 'form'.
|
|
|
|
That growth has taken place proportionally, is more manifest in
|
|
the organic parts-e.g. in the hand. For there the fact that the matter
|
|
is distinct from the form is more manifest than in flesh, i.e. than in
|
|
the tissues. That is why there is a greater tendency to suppose that a
|
|
corpse still possesses flesh and bone than that it still has a hand or
|
|
an arm.
|
|
|
|
Hence in one sense it is true that any and every part of the flesh
|
|
has grown; but in another sense it is false. For there has been an
|
|
accession to every part of the flesh in respect to its form, but not
|
|
in respect to its matter. The whole, however, has become larger. And
|
|
this increase is due (a) on the one hand to the accession of
|
|
something, which is called 'food' and is said to be 'contrary' to
|
|
flesh, but (b) on the other hand to the transformation of this food
|
|
into the same form as that of flesh as if, e.g. 'moist' were to accede
|
|
to 'dry' and, having acceded, were to be transformed and to become
|
|
'dry'. For in one sense 'Like grows by Like', but in another sense
|
|
'Unlike grows by Unlike'.
|
|
|
|
One might discuss what must be the character of that 'whereby' a
|
|
thing grows. Clearly it must be potentially that which is
|
|
growing-potentially flesh, e.g. if it is flesh that is growing.
|
|
Actually, therefore, it must be 'other' than the growing thing. This
|
|
'actual other', then, has passed-away and come-to-be flesh. But it has
|
|
not been transformed into flesh alone by itself (for that would have
|
|
been a coming-to-be, not a growth): on the contrary, it is the growing
|
|
thing which has come-to-be flesh (and grown) by the food. In what way,
|
|
then, has the food been modified by the growing thing? Perhaps we
|
|
should say that it has been 'mixed' with it, as if one were to pour
|
|
water into wine and the wine were able to convert the new ingredient
|
|
into wine. And as fire lays hold of the inflammable, so the active
|
|
principle of growth, dwelling in the growing thing that which is
|
|
actually flesh), lays hold of an acceding food which is potentially
|
|
flesh and converts it into actual flesh. The acceding food, therefore,
|
|
must be together with the growing thing: for if it were apart from it,
|
|
the change would be a coming-to-be. For it is possible to produce fire
|
|
by piling logs on to the already burning fire. That is 'growth'. But
|
|
when the logs themselves are set on fire, that is 'coming-to-be'.
|
|
|
|
'Quantum-in-general' does not come-to-be any more than 'animal'
|
|
which is neither man nor any other of the specific forms of animal:
|
|
what 'animal-in-general' is in coming-to-be, that 'quantum-in-general'
|
|
is in growth. But what does come-to-be in growth is flesh or bone-or a
|
|
hand or arm (i.e. the tissues of these organic parts). Such things
|
|
come-to-be, then, by the accession not of quantified-flesh but of a
|
|
quantified-something. In so far as this acceding food is potentially
|
|
the double result e.g. is potentially so-much-flesh-it produces
|
|
growth: for it is bound to become actually both so-much and flesh. But
|
|
in so far as it is potentially flesh only, it nourishes: for it is
|
|
thus that 'nutrition' and 'growth' differ by their definition. That is
|
|
why a body's' nutrition' continues so long as it is kept alive (even
|
|
when it is diminishing), though not its 'growth'; and why nutrition,
|
|
though 'the same' as growth, is yet different from it in its actual
|
|
being. For in so far as that which accedes is potentially 'so
|
|
much-flesh' it tends to increase flesh: whereas, in so far as it is
|
|
potentially 'flesh' only, it is nourishment.
|
|
|
|
The form of which we have spoken is a kind of power immersed in
|
|
matter-a duct, as it were. If, then, a matter accedes-a matter,
|
|
which is potentially a duct and also potentially possesses determinate
|
|
quantity the ducts to which it accedes will become bigger. But if it
|
|
is no longer able to act-if it has been weakened by the continued
|
|
influx of matter, just as water, continually mixed in greater and
|
|
greater quantity with wine, in the end makes the wine watery and
|
|
converts it into water-then it will cause a diminution of the quantum;
|
|
though still the form persists.
|
|
|
|
6
|
|
|
|
(In discussing the causes of coming-tobe) we must first
|
|
investigate the matter, i.e. the so-called 'elements'. We must ask
|
|
whether they really are clements or not, i.e. whether each of them
|
|
is eternal or whether there is a sense in which they come-to-be:
|
|
and, if they do come-to-be, whether all of them come-to-be in the same
|
|
manner reciprocally out of one another, or whether one amongst them is
|
|
something primary. Hence we must begin by explaining certain
|
|
preliminary matters, about which the statements now current are vague.
|
|
|
|
For all (the pluralist philosophers)- those who generate the
|
|
'elements' as well as those who generate the bodies that are
|
|
compounded of the elements- make use of 'dissociation' and
|
|
'association', and of 'action' and 'passion'. Now 'association' is
|
|
'combination'; but the precise meaning of the process we call
|
|
'combining' has not been explained. Again, (all the monists make use
|
|
of 'alteration': but) without an agent and a patient there cannot be
|
|
'altering' any more than there can be 'dissociating' and
|
|
'associating'. For not only those who postulate a plurality of
|
|
elements employ their reciprocal action and passion to generate the
|
|
compounds: those who derive things from a single element are equally
|
|
compelled to introduce 'acting'. And in this respect Diogenes is right
|
|
when he argues that 'unless all things were derived from one,
|
|
reciprocal action and passion could not have occurred'. The hot thing,
|
|
e.g. would not be cooled and the cold thing in turn be warmed: for
|
|
heat and cold do not change reciprocally into one another, but what
|
|
changes (it is clear) is the substratum. Hence, whenever there is
|
|
action and passion between two things, that which underlies them
|
|
must be a single something. No doubt, it is not true to say that all
|
|
things are of this character: but it is true of all things between
|
|
which there is reciprocal action and passion.
|
|
|
|
But if we must investigate 'action-passion' and 'combination', we
|
|
must also investigate 'contact'. For action and passion (in the proper
|
|
sense of the terms) can only occur between things which are such as to
|
|
touch one another; nor can things enter into combination at all unless
|
|
they have come into a certain kind of contact. Hence we must give a
|
|
definite account of these three things- of 'contact', 'combination',
|
|
and 'acting'.
|
|
|
|
Let us start as follows. All things which admit of 'combination'
|
|
must be capable of reciprocal contact: and the same is true of any two
|
|
things, of which one 'acts' and the other 'suffers action' in the
|
|
proper sense of the terms. For this reason we must treat of
|
|
'contact' first. every term which possesses a variety of meaning
|
|
includes those various meanings either owing to a mere coincidence
|
|
of language, or owing to a real order of derivation in the different
|
|
things to which it is applied: but, though this may be taken to hold
|
|
of 'contact' as of all such terms, it is nevertheless true that
|
|
contact' in the proper sense applies only to things which have
|
|
'position'. And 'position' belongs only to those things which also
|
|
have a Place': for in so far as we attribute 'contact' to the
|
|
mathematical things, we must also attribute 'place' to them, whether
|
|
they exist in separation or in some other fashion. Assuming,
|
|
therefore, that 'to touch' is-as we have defined it in a previous
|
|
work'-'to have the extremes together', only those things will touch
|
|
one another which, being separate magnitudes and possessing
|
|
position, have their extremes 'together'. And since position belongs
|
|
only to those things which also have a 'place', while the primary
|
|
differentiation of 'place' is the above' and 'the below' (and the
|
|
similar pairs of opposites), all things which touch one another will
|
|
have 'weight' or 'lightness' either both these qualities or one or the
|
|
other of them. But bodies which are heavy or light are such as to
|
|
'act' and 'suffer action'. Hence it is clear that those things are
|
|
by nature such as to touch one another, which (being separate
|
|
magnitudes) have their extremes 'together' and are able to move, and
|
|
be moved by, one another.
|
|
|
|
The manner in which the 'mover' moves the moved' not always the
|
|
same: on the contrary, whereas one kind of 'mover' can only impart
|
|
motion by being itself moved, another kind can do so though
|
|
remaining itself unmoved. Clearly therefore we must recognize a
|
|
corresponding variety in speaking of the 'acting' thing too: for the
|
|
'mover' is said to 'act' (in a sense) and the 'acting' thing to
|
|
'impart motion'. Nevertheless there is a difference and we must draw a
|
|
distinction. For not every 'mover' can 'act', if (a) the term
|
|
'agent' is to be used in contrast to 'patient' and (b) 'patient' is to
|
|
be applied only to those things whose motion is a 'qualitative
|
|
affection'-i.e. a quality, like white' or 'hot', in respect to which
|
|
they are moved' only in the sense that they are 'altered': on the
|
|
contrary, to 'impart motion' is a wider term than to 'act'. Still,
|
|
so much, at any rate, is clear: the things which are 'such as to
|
|
impart motion', if that description be interpreted in one sense,
|
|
will touch the things which are 'such as to be moved by them'-while
|
|
they will not touch them, if the description be interpreted in a
|
|
different sense. But the disjunctive definition of 'touching' must
|
|
include and distinguish (a) 'contact in general' as the relation
|
|
between two things which, having position, are such that one is able
|
|
to impart motion and the other to be moved, and (b) 'reciprocal
|
|
contact' as the relation between two things, one able to impart motion
|
|
and the other able to be moved in such a way that 'action and passion'
|
|
are predicable of them.
|
|
|
|
As a rule, no doubt, if A touches B, B touches A. For indeed
|
|
practically all the 'movers' within our ordinary experience impart
|
|
motion by being moved: in their case, what touches inevitably must,
|
|
and also evidently does, touch something which reciprocally touches
|
|
it. Yet, if A moves B, it is possible-as we sometimes express it-for A
|
|
'merely to touch' B, and that which touches need not touch a something
|
|
which touches it. Nevertheless it is commonly supposed that 'touching'
|
|
must be reciprocal. The reason of this belief is that 'movers' which
|
|
belong to the same kind as the 'moved' impart motion by being moved.
|
|
Hence if anything imparts motion without itself being moved, it may
|
|
touch the 'moved' and yet itself be touched by nothing-for we say
|
|
sometimes that the man who grieves us 'touches' us, but not that we
|
|
'touch' him.
|
|
|
|
The account just given may serve to distinguish and define the
|
|
'contact' which occurs in the things of Nature.
|
|
|
|
7
|
|
|
|
Next in order we must discuss 'action' and 'passion'. The
|
|
traditional theories on the subject are conflicting. For (i) most
|
|
thinkers are unanimous in maintaining (a) that 'like' is always
|
|
unaffected by 'like', because (as they argue) neither of two 'likes'
|
|
is more apt than the other either to act or to suffer action, since
|
|
all the properties which belong to the one belong identically and in
|
|
the same degree to the other; and (b) that 'unlikes', i.e.
|
|
'differents', are by nature such as to act and suffer action
|
|
reciprocally. For even when the smaller fire is destroyed by the
|
|
greater, it suffers this effect (they say) owing to its
|
|
'contrariety' since the great is contrary to the small. But (ii)
|
|
Democritus dissented from all the other thinkers and maintained a
|
|
theory peculiar to himself. He asserts that agent and patient are
|
|
identical, i.e. 'like'. It is not possible (he says) that 'others',
|
|
i.e. 'differents', should suffer action from one another: on the
|
|
contrary, even if two things, being 'others', do act in some way on
|
|
one another, this happens to them not qua 'others' but qua
|
|
possessing an identical property.
|
|
|
|
Such, then, are the traditional theories, and it looks as if the
|
|
statements of their advocates were in manifest conflict. But the
|
|
reason of this conflict is that each group is in fact stating a
|
|
part, whereas they ought to have taken a comprehensive view of the
|
|
subject as a whole. For (i) if A and B are 'like'-absolutely and in
|
|
all respects without difference from one another -it is reasonable
|
|
to infer that neither is in any way affected by the other. Why,
|
|
indeed, should either of them tend to act any more than the other?
|
|
Moreover, if 'like' can be affected by 'like', a thing can also be
|
|
affected by itself: and yet if that were so-if 'like' tended in fact
|
|
to act qua 'like'-there would be nothing indestructible or
|
|
immovable, for everything would move itself. And (ii) the same
|
|
consequence follows if A and B are absolutely 'other', i.e. in no
|
|
respect identical. Whiteness could not be affected in any way by
|
|
line nor line by whiseness-except perhaps 'coincidentally', viz. if
|
|
the line happened to be white or black: for unless two things either
|
|
are, or are composed of, 'contraries', neither drives the other out of
|
|
its natural condition. But (iii) since only those things which
|
|
either involve a 'contrariety' or are 'contraries'-and not any
|
|
things selected at random-are such as to suffer action and to act,
|
|
agent and patient must be 'like' (i.e. identical) in kind and yet
|
|
'unlike' (i.e. contrary) in species. (For it is a law of nature that
|
|
body is affected by body, flavour by flavour, colour by colour, and so
|
|
in general what belongs to any kind by a member of the same kind-the
|
|
reason being that 'contraries' are in every case within a single
|
|
identical kind, and it is 'contraries' which reciprocally act and
|
|
suffer action.) Hence agent and patient must be in one sense
|
|
identical, but in another sense other than (i.e. 'unlike') one
|
|
another. And since (a) patient and agent are generically identical
|
|
(i.e. 'like') but specifically 'unlike', while (b) it is
|
|
'contraries' that exhibit this character: it is clear that
|
|
'contraries' and their 'intermediates' are such as to suffer action
|
|
and to act reciprocally-for indeed it is these that constitute the
|
|
entire sphere of passing-away and coming-to-be.
|
|
|
|
We can now understand why fire heats and the cold thing cools, and
|
|
in general why the active thing assimilates to itself the patient. For
|
|
agent and patient are contrary to one another, and coming-to-be is a
|
|
process into the contrary: hence the patient must change into the
|
|
agent, since it is only thus that coming-to be will be a process
|
|
into the contrary. And, again, it is intelligible that the advocates
|
|
of both views, although their theories are not the same, are yet in
|
|
contact with the nature of the facts. For sometimes we speak of the
|
|
substratum as suffering action (e.g. of 'the man' as being healed,
|
|
being warmed and chilled, and similarly in all the other cases), but
|
|
at other times we say 'what is cold is 'being warmed', 'what is sick
|
|
is being healed': and in both these ways of speaking we express the
|
|
truth, since in one sense it is the 'matter', while in another sense
|
|
it is the 'contrary', which suffers action. (We make the same
|
|
distinction in speaking of the agent: for sometimes we say that 'the
|
|
man', but at other times that 'what is hot', produces heat.) Now the
|
|
one group of thinkers supposed that agent and patient must possess
|
|
something identical, because they fastened their attention on the
|
|
substratum: while the other group maintained the opposite because
|
|
their attention was concentrated on the 'contraries'. We must conceive
|
|
the same account to hold of action and passion as that which is true
|
|
of 'being moved' and 'imparting motion'. For the 'mover', like the
|
|
'agent', has two meanings. Both (a) that which contains the
|
|
originative source of the motion is thought to 'impart motion' (for
|
|
the originative source is first amongst the causes), and also (b) that
|
|
which is last, i.e. immediately next to the moved thing and to the
|
|
coming-to-be. A similar distinction holds also of the agent: for we
|
|
speak not only (a) of the doctor, but also (b) of the wine, as
|
|
healing. Now, in motion, there is nothing to prevent the firs; mover
|
|
being unmoved (indeed, as regards some 'first' movers' this is
|
|
actually necessary) although the last mover always imparts motion by
|
|
being itself moved: and, in action, there is nothing to prevent the
|
|
first agent being unaffected, while the last agent only acts by
|
|
suffering action itself. For agent and patient have not the same
|
|
matter, agent acts without being affected: thus the art of healing
|
|
produces health without itself being acted upon in any way by that
|
|
which is being healed. But (b) the food, in acting, is itself in
|
|
some way acted upon: for, in acting, it is simultaneously heated or
|
|
cooled or otherwise affected. Now the art of healing corresponds to an
|
|
'originative source', while the food corresponds to 'the last' (i.e.
|
|
'continuous') mover.
|
|
|
|
Those active powers, then, whose forms are not embodied in matter,
|
|
are unaffected: but those whose forms are in matter are such as to
|
|
be affected in acting. For we maintain that one and the same
|
|
'matter' is equally, so to say, the basis of either of the two opposed
|
|
things-being as it were a 'kind'; and that that which can he hot
|
|
must be made hot, provided the heating agent is there, i.e. comes
|
|
near. Hence (as we have said) some of the active powers are unaffected
|
|
while others are such as to be affected; and what holds of motion is
|
|
true also of the active powers. For as in motion 'the first mover'
|
|
is unmoved, so among the active powers 'the first agent' is
|
|
unaffected.
|
|
|
|
The active power is a 'cause' in the sense of that from which the
|
|
process originates: but the end, for the sake of which it takes place,
|
|
is not 'active'. (That is why health is not 'active', except
|
|
metaphorically.) For when the agent is there, the patient he-comes
|
|
something: but when 'states' are there, the patient no longer
|
|
becomes but already is-and 'forms' (i.e. lends') are a kind of
|
|
'state'. As to the 'matter', it (qua matter) is passive. Now fire
|
|
contains 'the hot' embodied in matter: but a 'hot' separate from
|
|
matter (if such a thing existed) could not suffer any action. Perhaps,
|
|
indeed, it is impossible that 'the hot' should exist in separation
|
|
from matter: but if there are any entities thus separable, what we are
|
|
saying would be true of them.
|
|
|
|
We have thus explained what action and passion are, what things
|
|
exhibit them, why they do so, and in what manner. We must go on to
|
|
discuss how it is possible for action and passion to take place.
|
|
|
|
8
|
|
|
|
Some philosophers think that the 'last' agent-the 'agent' in the
|
|
strictest sense-enters in through certain pores, and so the patient
|
|
suffers action. It is in this way, they assert, that we see and hear
|
|
and exercise all our other senses. Moreover, according to them, things
|
|
are seen through air and water and other transparent bodies, because
|
|
such bodies possess pores, invisible indeed owing to their minuteness,
|
|
but close-set and arranged in rows: and the more transparent the body,
|
|
the more frequent and serial they suppose its pores to be. Such was
|
|
the theory which some philosophers (induding Empedocles) advanced in
|
|
regard to the structure of certain bodies. They do not restrict it
|
|
to the bodies which act and suffer action: but 'combination' too, they
|
|
say, takes place 'only between bodies whose pores are in reciprocal
|
|
symmetry'. The most systematic and consistent theory, however, and one
|
|
that applied to all bodies, was advanced by Leucippus and
|
|
Democritus: and, in maintaining it, they took as their
|
|
starting-point what naturally comes first.
|
|
|
|
For some of the older philosophers thought that 'what is' must of
|
|
necessity be 'one' and immovable. The void, they argue, 'is not':
|
|
but unless there is a void with a separate being of its own, 'what is'
|
|
cannot be moved-nor again can it be 'many', since there is nothing
|
|
to keep things apart. And in this respect, they insist, the view
|
|
that the universe is not 'continuous' but 'discretes-in-contact' is no
|
|
better than the view that there are 'many' (and not 'one') and a void.
|
|
For (suppose that the universe is discretes-in-contact. Then), if it
|
|
is divisible through and through, there is no 'one', and therefore
|
|
no 'many' either, but the Whole is void; while to maintain that it
|
|
is divisible at some points, but not at others, looks like an
|
|
arbitrary fiction. For up to what limit is it divisible? And for
|
|
what reason is part of the Whole indivisible, i.e. a plenum, and
|
|
part divided? Further, they maintain, it is equally necessary to
|
|
deny the existence of motion.
|
|
|
|
Reasoning in this way, therefore, they were led to transcend
|
|
sense-perception, and to disregard it on the ground that 'one ought to
|
|
follow the argument': and so they assert that the universe is 'one'
|
|
and immovable. Some of them add that it is 'infinite', since the limit
|
|
(if it had one) would be a limit against the void.
|
|
|
|
There were, then, certain thinkers who, for the reasons we have
|
|
stated, enunciated views of this kind as their theory of 'The
|
|
Truth'.... Moreover, although these opinions appear to follow
|
|
logically in a dialectical discussion, yet to believe them seems
|
|
next door to madness when one considers the facts. For indeed no
|
|
lunatic seems to be so far out of his senses as to suppose that fire
|
|
and ice are 'one': it is only between what is right and what seems
|
|
right from habit, that some people are mad enough to see no
|
|
difference.
|
|
|
|
Leucippus, however, thought he had a theory which harmonized with
|
|
sense-perception and would not abolish either coming-to-be and
|
|
passing-away or motion and the multiplicity of things. He made these
|
|
concessions to the facts of perception: on the other hand, he conceded
|
|
to the Monists that there could be no motion without a void. The
|
|
result is a theory which he states as follows: 'The void is a "not
|
|
being", and no part of "what is" is a "not-being"; for what "is" in
|
|
the strict sense of the term is an absolute plenum. This plenum,
|
|
however, is not "one": on the contrary, it is a many" infinite in
|
|
number and invisible owing to the minuteness of their bulk. The "many"
|
|
move in the void (for there is a void): and by coming together they
|
|
produce "coming to-be", while by separating they produce
|
|
"passing-away". Moreover, they act and suffer action wherever they
|
|
chance to be in contact (for there they are not "one"), and they
|
|
generate by being put together and becoming intertwined. From the
|
|
genuinely-one, on the other hand, there never could have come-to-be
|
|
a multiplicity, nor from the genuinely-many a "one": that is
|
|
impossible. But' (just as Empedocles and some of the other
|
|
philosophers say that things suffer action through their pores, so)
|
|
'all "alteration" and all "passion" take place in the way that has
|
|
been explained: breaking-up (i.e. passing-away) is effected by means
|
|
of the void, and so too is growth-solids creeping in to fill the
|
|
void places.' Empedocles too is practically bound to adopt the same
|
|
theory as Leucippus. For he must say that there are certain solids
|
|
which, however, are indivisible-unless there are continuous pores
|
|
all through the body. But this last alternative is impossible: for
|
|
then there will be nothing solid in the body (nothing beside the
|
|
pores) but all of it will be void. It is necessary, therefore, for his
|
|
'contiguous discretes' to be indivisible, while the intervals
|
|
between them-which he calls 'pores'-must be void. But this is
|
|
precisely Leucippus' theory of action and passion.
|
|
|
|
Such, approximately, are the current explanations of the manner in
|
|
which some things 'act' while others 'suffer action'. And as regards
|
|
the Atomists, it is not only clear what their explanation is: it is
|
|
also obvious that it follows with tolerable consistency from the
|
|
assumptions they employ. But there is less obvious consistency in
|
|
the explanation offered by the other thinkers. It is not clear, for
|
|
instance, how, on the theory of Empedocles, there is to be
|
|
'passing-away' as well as 'alteration'. For the primary bodies of
|
|
the Atomists-the primary constituents of which bodies are composed,
|
|
and the ultimate elements into which they are dissolved-are
|
|
indivisible, differing from one another only in figure. In the
|
|
philosophy of Empedocles, on the other hand, it is evident that all
|
|
the other bodies down to the 'elements' have their coming-to-be and
|
|
their passingaway: but it is not clear how the 'elements'
|
|
themselves, severally in their aggregated masses, come-to-be and
|
|
pass-away. Nor is it possible for Empedocles to explain how they do
|
|
so, since he does not assert that Fire too (and similarly every one of
|
|
his other 'elements') possesses 'elementary constituents' of itself.
|
|
|
|
Such an assertion would commit him to doctrines like those which
|
|
Plato has set forth in the Timaeus. For although both Plato and
|
|
Leucippus postulate elementary constituents that are indivisible and
|
|
distinctively characterized by figures, there is this great difference
|
|
between the two theories: the 'indivisibles' of Leucippus (i) are
|
|
solids, while those of Plato are planes, and (ii) are characterized by
|
|
an infinite variety of figures, while the characterizing figures
|
|
employed by Plato are limited in number. Thus the 'comings-to-be'
|
|
and the 'dissociations' result from the 'indivisibles' (a) according
|
|
to Leucippus through the void and through contact (for it is at the
|
|
point of contact that each of the composite bodies is divisible),
|
|
but (b) according to Plato in virtue of contact alone, since he denies
|
|
there is a void.
|
|
|
|
Now we have discussed 'indivisible planes' in the preceding
|
|
treatise.' But with regard to the assumption of 'indivisible
|
|
solids', although we must not now enter upon a detailed study of its
|
|
consequences, the following criticisms fall within the compass of a
|
|
short digression: i. The Atomists are committed to the view that every
|
|
'indivisible' is incapable alike of receiving a sensible property (for
|
|
nothing can 'suffer action' except through the void) and of
|
|
producing one-no 'indivisible' can be, e.g. either hard or cold. Yet
|
|
it is surely a paradox that an exception is made of 'the hot'-'the
|
|
hot' being assigned as peculiar to the spherical figure: for, that
|
|
being so, its 'contrary' also ('the cold') is bound to belong to
|
|
another of the figures. If, however, these properties (heat and
|
|
cold) do belong to the 'indivisibles', it is a further paradox that
|
|
they should not possess heaviness and lightness, and hardness and
|
|
softness. And yet Democritus says 'the more any indivisible exceeds,
|
|
the heavier it is'-to which we must clearly add 'and the hotter it
|
|
is'. But if that is their character, it is impossible they should
|
|
not be affected by one another: the 'slightly-hot indivisible', e.g.
|
|
will inevitably suffer action from one which far exceeds it in heat.
|
|
Again, if any 'indivisible' is 'hard', there must also be one which is
|
|
'soft': but 'the soft' derives its very name from the fact that it
|
|
suffers a certain action-for 'soft' is that which yields to pressure.
|
|
|
|
II. But further, not only is it paradoxical (i) that no property
|
|
except figure should belong to the 'indivisibles': it is also
|
|
paradoxical (ii) that, if other properties do belong to them, one only
|
|
of these additional properties should attach to each-e.g. that this
|
|
'indivisible' should be cold and that 'indivisible' hot. For, on
|
|
that supposition, their substance would not even be uniform. And it is
|
|
equally impossible (iii) that more than one of these additional
|
|
properties should belong to the single 'indivisible'. For, being
|
|
indivisible, it will possess these properties in the same point-so
|
|
that, if it 'suffers action' by being chilled, it will also, qua
|
|
chilled, 'act' or 'suffer action' in some other way. And the same line
|
|
of argument applies to all the other properties too: for the
|
|
difficulty we have just raised confronts, as a necessary
|
|
consequence, all who advocate 'indivisibles' (whether solids or
|
|
planes), since their 'indivisibles' cannot become either 'rarer' or
|
|
'derser' inasmuch as there is no void in them.
|
|
|
|
III. It is a further paradox that there should be small
|
|
'indivisibles', but not large ones. For it is natural enough, from the
|
|
ordinary point of view, that the larger bodies should be more liable
|
|
to fracture than the small ones, since they (viz. the large bodies)
|
|
are easily broken up because they collide with many other bodies.
|
|
But why should indivisibility as such be the property of small, rather
|
|
than of large, bodies?
|
|
|
|
IV. Again, is the substance of all those solids uniform, or do
|
|
they fall into sets which differ from one another-as if, e.g. some
|
|
of them, in their aggregated bulk, were 'fiery', others earthy'? For
|
|
(i) if all of them are uniform in substance, what is it that separated
|
|
one from another? Or why, when they come into contact, do they not
|
|
coalesce into one, as drops of water run together when drop touches
|
|
drop (for the two cases are precisely parallel)? On the other hand
|
|
(ii) if they fall into differing sets, how are these characterized? It
|
|
is clear, too, that these, rather than the 'figures', ought to be
|
|
postulated as 'original reals', i.e. causes from which the phenomena
|
|
result. Moreover, if they differed in substance, they would both act
|
|
and suffer action on coming into reciprocal contact.
|
|
|
|
V. Again, what is it which sets them moving? For if their 'mover' is
|
|
other than themselves, they are such as to 'suffer action'. If, on the
|
|
other hand, each of them sets itself in motion, either (a) it will
|
|
be divisible ('imparting motion' qua this, 'being moved' qua that), or
|
|
(b) contrary properties will attach to it in the same respect-i.e.
|
|
'matter' will be identical in-potentiality as well as
|
|
numerically-identical.
|
|
|
|
As to the thinkers who explain modification of property through
|
|
the movement facilitated by the pores, if this is supposed to occur
|
|
notwithstanding the fact that the pores are filled, their postulate of
|
|
pores is superfluous. For if the whole body suffers action under these
|
|
conditions, it would suffer action in the same way even if it had no
|
|
pores but were just its own continuous self. Moreover, how can their
|
|
account of 'vision through a medium' be correct? It is impossible
|
|
for (the visual ray) to penetrate the transparent bodies at their
|
|
'contacts'; and impossible for it to pass through their pores if every
|
|
pore be full. For how will that differ from having no pores at all?
|
|
The body will be uniformly 'full' throughout. But, further, even if
|
|
these passages, though they must contain bodies, are 'void', the
|
|
same consequence will follow once more. And if they are 'too minute to
|
|
admit any body', it is absurd to suppose there is a 'minute' void
|
|
and yet to deny the existence of a 'big' one (no matter how small
|
|
the 'big' may be), or to imagine 'the void' means anything else than a
|
|
body's place-whence it clearly follows that to every body there will
|
|
correspond a void of equal cubic capacity.
|
|
|
|
As a general criticism we must urge that to postulate pores is
|
|
superfluous. For if the agent produces no effect by touching the
|
|
patient, neither will it produce any by passing through its pores.
|
|
On the other hand, if it acts by contact, then-even without pores-some
|
|
things will 'suffer action' and others will 'act', provided they are
|
|
by nature adapted for reciprocal action and passion. Our arguments
|
|
have shown that it is either false or futile to advocate pores in
|
|
the sense in which some thinkers conceive them. But since bodies are
|
|
divisible through and through, the postulate of pores is ridiculous:
|
|
for, qua divisible, a body can fall into separate parts.
|
|
|
|
9
|
|
|
|
Let explain the way in which things in fact possess the power of
|
|
generating, and of acting and suffering action: and let us start
|
|
from the principle we have often enunciated. For, assuming the
|
|
distinction between (a) that which is potentially and (b) that which
|
|
is actually such-and-such, it is the nature of the first, precisely in
|
|
so far as it is what it is, to suffer action through and through,
|
|
not merely to be susceptible in some parts while insusceptible in
|
|
others. But its susceptibility varies in degree, according as it is
|
|
more or less; such-and such, and one would be more justified in
|
|
speaking of 'pores' in this connexion: for instance, in the metals
|
|
there are veins of 'the susceptible' stretching continuously through
|
|
the substance.
|
|
|
|
So long, indeed, as any body is naturally coherent and one, it is
|
|
insusceptible. So, too, bodies are insusceptible so long as they are
|
|
not in contact either with one another or with other bodies which
|
|
are by nature such as to act and suffer action. (To illustrate my
|
|
meaning: Fire heats not only when in contact, but also from a
|
|
distance. For the fire heats the air, and the air-being by nature such
|
|
as both to act and suffer action-heats the body.) But the
|
|
supposition that a body is 'susceptible in some parts, but
|
|
insusceptible in others' (is only possible for those who hold an
|
|
erroneous view concerning the divisibility of magnitudes. For us)
|
|
the following account results from the distinctions we established
|
|
at the beginning. For (i) if magnitudes are not divisible through
|
|
and through-if, on the contrary, there are indivisible solids or
|
|
planes-then indeed no body would be susceptible through and through
|
|
:but neither would any be continuous. Since, however, (ii) this is
|
|
false, i.e. since every body is divisible, there is no difference
|
|
between 'having been divided into parts which remain in contact' and
|
|
'being divisible'. For if a body 'can be separated at the contacts'
|
|
(as some thinkers express it), then, even though it has not yet been
|
|
divided, it will be in a state of dividedness-since, as it can be
|
|
divided, nothing inconceivable results. And (iii) the suposition is
|
|
open to this general objection-it is a paradox that 'passion' should
|
|
occur in this manner only, viz. by the bodies being split. For this
|
|
theory abolishes 'alteration': but we see the same body liquid at
|
|
one time and solid at another, without losing its continuity. It has
|
|
suffered this change not by 'division' and composition', nor yet by
|
|
'turning' and 'intercontact' as Democritus asserts; for it has
|
|
passed from the liquid to the solid state without any change of
|
|
'grouping' or 'position' in the constituents of its substance. Nor are
|
|
there contained within it those 'hard' (i.e. congealed) particles
|
|
'indivisible in their bulk': on the contrary, it is liquid-and
|
|
again, solid and congealed-uniformly all through. This theory, it must
|
|
be added, makes growth and diminution impossible also. For if there is
|
|
to be opposition (instead of the growing thing having changed as a
|
|
whole, either by the admixture of something or by its own
|
|
transformation), increase of size will not have resulted in any and
|
|
every part.
|
|
|
|
So much, then, to establish that things generate and are
|
|
generated, act and suffer action, reciprocally; and to distinguish the
|
|
way in which these processes can occur from the (impossible) way in
|
|
which some thinkers say they occur.
|
|
|
|
10
|
|
|
|
But we have still to explain 'combination', for that was the third
|
|
of the subjects we originally proposed to discuss. Our explanation
|
|
will proceed on the same method as before. We must inquire: What is
|
|
'combination', and what is that which can 'combine'? Of what things,
|
|
and under what conditions, is 'combination' a property? And,
|
|
further, does 'combination' exist in fact, or is it false to assert
|
|
its existence?
|
|
|
|
For, according to some thinkers, it is impossible for one thing to
|
|
be combined with another. They argue that (i) if both the 'combined'
|
|
constituents persist unaltered, they are no more 'combined' now than
|
|
they were before, but are in the same condition: while (ii) if one has
|
|
been destroyed, the constituents have not been 'combined'-on the
|
|
contrary, one constituent is and the other is not, whereas
|
|
'combination' demands uniformity of condition in them both: and on the
|
|
same principle (iii) even if both the combining constituents have been
|
|
destroyed as the result of their coalescence, they cannot 'have been
|
|
combined' since they have no being at all.
|
|
|
|
What we have in this argument is, it would seem, a demand for the
|
|
precise distinction of 'combination' from coming-to-be and passingaway
|
|
(for it is obvious that 'combination', if it exists, must differ
|
|
from these processes) and for the precise distinction of the
|
|
'combinable' from that which is such as to come-to-be and pass-away.
|
|
As soon, therefore, as these distinctions are clear, the
|
|
difficulties raised by the argument would be solved.
|
|
|
|
Now (i) we do not speak of the wood as 'combined' with the fire, nor
|
|
of its burning as a 'combining' either of its particles with one
|
|
another or of itself with the fire: what we say is that 'the fire is
|
|
coming-to-be, but the wood is 'passing-away'. Similarly, we speak
|
|
neither (ii) of the food as 'combining' with the body, nor (iii) of
|
|
the shape as 'combining' with the wax and thus fashioning the lump.
|
|
Nor can body 'combine' with white, nor (to generalize) 'properties'
|
|
and 'states' with 'things': for we see them persisting unaltered.
|
|
But again (iv) white and knowledge cannot be 'combined' either, nor
|
|
any other of the 'adjectivals'. (Indeed, this is a blemish in the
|
|
theory of those who assert that 'once upon a time all things were
|
|
together and combined'. For not everything can 'combine' with
|
|
everything. On the contrary, both of the constituents that are
|
|
combined in the compound must originally have existed in separation:
|
|
but no property can have separate existence.)
|
|
|
|
Since, however, some things are-potentially while others
|
|
are-actually, the constituents combined in a compound can 'be' in a
|
|
sense and yet 'not-be'. The compound may he-actually other than the
|
|
constituents from which it has resulted; nevertheless each of them may
|
|
still he-potentially what it was before they were combined, and both
|
|
of them may survive undestroyed. (For this was the difficulty that
|
|
emerged in the previous argument: and it is evident that the combining
|
|
constituents not only coalesce, having formerly existed in separation,
|
|
but also can again be separated out from the compound.) The
|
|
constituents, therefore, neither (a) persist actually, as 'body' and
|
|
'white' persist: nor (b) are they destroyed (either one of them or
|
|
both), for their 'power of action' is preserved. Hence these
|
|
difficulties may be dismissed: but the problem immediately connected
|
|
with them-whether combination is something relative to perception'
|
|
must be set out and discussed.
|
|
|
|
When the combining constituents have been divided into parts so
|
|
small, and have been juxtaposed in such a manner, that perception
|
|
fails to discriminate them one from another, have they then 'been
|
|
combined Or ought we to say 'No, not until any and every part of one
|
|
constituent is juxtaposed to a part of the other'? The term, no doubt,
|
|
is applied in the former sense: we speak, e.g. of wheat having been
|
|
'combined' with barley when each grain of the one is juxtaposed to a
|
|
grain of the other. But every body is divisible and therefore, since
|
|
body 'combined' with body is uniform in texture throughout, any and
|
|
every part of each constituent ought to be juxtaposed to a part of the
|
|
other.
|
|
|
|
No body, however, can be divided into its 'least' parts: and
|
|
'composition' is not identical with 'combination', but other than
|
|
it. From these premises it clearly follows (i) that so long as the
|
|
constituents are preserved in small particles, we must not speak of
|
|
them as 'combined'. (For this will be a 'composition' instead of a
|
|
'blending' or 'combination': nor will every portion of the resultant
|
|
exhibit the same ratio between its constituents as the whole. But we
|
|
maintain that, if 'combination' has taken place, the compound must
|
|
be uniform in texture throughout-any part of such a compound being the
|
|
same as the whole, just as any part of water is water: whereas, if
|
|
'combination' is 'composition of the small particles', nothing of
|
|
the kind will happen. On the contrary, the constituents will only be
|
|
'combined' relatively to perception: and the same thing will be
|
|
'combined' to one percipient, if his sight is not sharp, (but not to
|
|
another,) while to the eye of Lynceus nothing will be 'combined'.)
|
|
It clearly follows (ii) that we must not speak of the constituents
|
|
as 'combined in virtue of a division such that any and every part of
|
|
each is juxtaposed to a part of the other: for it is impossible for
|
|
them to be thus divided. Either, then, there is no 'combination', or
|
|
we have still to explain the manner in which it can take place.
|
|
|
|
Now, as we maintain, some things are such as to act and others
|
|
such as to suffer action from them. Moreover, some things-viz. those
|
|
Which have the same matter-'reciprocate', i.e. are such as to act upon
|
|
one another and to suffer action from one another; while other things,
|
|
viz. agents which have not the same matter as their patients, act
|
|
without themselves suffering action. Such agents cannot 'combine'-that
|
|
is why neither the art of healing nor health produces health by
|
|
'combining' with the bodies of the patients. Amongst those things,
|
|
however, which are reciprocally active and passive, some are
|
|
easily-divisible. Now (i) if a great quantity (or a large bulk) of one
|
|
of these easily-divisible 'reciprocating' materials be brought
|
|
together with a little (or with a small piece) of another, the
|
|
effect produced is not 'combination', but increase of the dominant:
|
|
for the other material is transformed into the dominant. (That is
|
|
why a drop of wine does not 'combine' with ten thousand gallons of
|
|
water: for its form is dissolved, and it is changed so as to merge
|
|
in the total volume of water.) On the other hand (ii) when there is
|
|
a certain equilibrium between their 'powers of action', then each of
|
|
them changes out of its own nature towards the dominant: yet neither
|
|
becomes the other, but both become an intermediate with properties
|
|
common to both.
|
|
|
|
Thus it is clear that only those agents are 'combinable' which
|
|
involve a contrariety-for these are such as to suffer action
|
|
reciprocally. And, further, they combine more freely if small pieces
|
|
of each of them are juxtaposed. For in that condition they change
|
|
one another more easily and more quickly; whereas this effect takes
|
|
a long time when agent and patient are present in bulk.
|
|
|
|
Hence, amongst the divisible susceptible materials, those whose
|
|
shape is readily adaptable have a tendency to combine: for they are
|
|
easily divided into small particles, since that is precisely what
|
|
'being readily adaptable in shape' implies. For instance, liquids
|
|
are the most 'combinable' of all bodies-because, of all divisible
|
|
materials, the liquid is most readily adaptable in shape, unless it be
|
|
viscous. Viscous liquids, it is true, produce no effect except to
|
|
increase the volume and bulk. But when one of the constituents is
|
|
alone susceptible-or superlatively susceptible, the other being
|
|
susceptible in a very slight degree-the compound resulting from
|
|
their combination is either no greater in volume or only a little
|
|
greater. This is what happens when tin is combined with bronze. For
|
|
some things display a hesitating and ambiguous attitude towards one
|
|
another-showing a slight tendency to combine and also an inclination
|
|
to behave as 'receptive matter' and 'form' respectively. The behaviour
|
|
of these metals is a case in point. For the tin almost vanishes,
|
|
behaving as if it were an immaterial property of the bronze: having
|
|
been combined, it disappears, leaving no trace except the colour it
|
|
has imparted to the bronze. The same phenomenon occurs in other
|
|
instances too.
|
|
|
|
It is clear, then, from the foregoing account, that 'combination'
|
|
occurs, what it is, to what it is due, and what kind of thing is
|
|
'combinable'. The phenomenon depends upon the fact that some things
|
|
are such as to be (a) reciprocally susceptible and (b) readily
|
|
adaptable in shape, i.e. easily divisible. For such things can be
|
|
'combined' without its being necessary either that they should have
|
|
been destroyed or that they should survive absolutely unaltered: and
|
|
their 'combination' need not be a 'composition', nor merely
|
|
'relative to perception'. On the contrary: anything is 'combinable'
|
|
which, being readily adaptable in shape, is such as to suffer action
|
|
and to act; and it is 'combinable with' another thing similarly
|
|
characterized (for the 'combinable' is relative to the
|
|
'combinable'); and 'combination' is unification of the
|
|
'combinables', resulting from their 'alteration'.
|
|
|
|
Book II
|
|
|
|
1
|
|
|
|
WE have explained under what conditions 'combination', 'contact',
|
|
and 'action-passion' are attributable to the things which undergo
|
|
natural change. Further, we have discussed 'unqualified'
|
|
coming-to-be and passing-away, and explained under what conditions
|
|
they are predicable, of what subject, and owing to what cause.
|
|
Similarly, we have also discussed 'alteration', and explained what
|
|
'altering' is and how it differs from coming-to-be and passing-away.
|
|
But we have still to investigate the so-called 'elements' of bodies.
|
|
|
|
For the complex substances whose formation and maintenance are due
|
|
to natural processes all presuppose the perceptible bodies as the
|
|
condition of their coming-to-be and passing-away: but philosophers
|
|
disagree in regard to the matter which underlies these perceptible
|
|
bodies. Some maintain it is single, supposing it to be, e.g. Air or
|
|
Fire, or an 'intermediate' between these two (but still a body with
|
|
a separate existence). Others, on the contrary, postulate two or
|
|
more materials-ascribing to their 'association' and 'dissociation', or
|
|
to their 'alteration', the coming-to-be and passing-away of things.
|
|
(Some, for instance, postulate Fire and Earth: some add Air, making
|
|
three: and some, like Empedocles, reckon Water as well, thus
|
|
postulating four.)
|
|
|
|
Now we may agree that the primary materials, whose change (whether
|
|
it be 'association and dissociation' or a process of another kind)
|
|
results in coming-to-be and passingaway, are rightly described as
|
|
'originative sources, i.e. elements'. But (i) those thinkers are in
|
|
error who postulate, beside the bodies we have mentioned, a single
|
|
matter-and that corporeal and separable matter. For this 'body' of
|
|
theirs cannot possibly exist without a 'perceptible contrariety': this
|
|
'Boundless', which some thinkers identify with the 'original real',
|
|
must be either light or heavy, either cold or hot. And (ii) what Plato
|
|
has written in the Timaeus is not based on any precisely-articulated
|
|
conception. For he has not stated clearly whether his
|
|
'Omnirecipient" exists in separation from the 'elements'; nor does
|
|
he make any use of it. He says, indeed, that it is a substratum
|
|
prior to the so-called 'elements'-underlying them, as gold underlies
|
|
the things that are fashioned of gold. (And yet this comparison, if
|
|
thus expressed, is itself open to criticism. Things which come-to-be
|
|
and pass-away cannot be called by the name of the material out of
|
|
which they have come-tobe: it is only the results of 'alteration'
|
|
which retain the name of the substratum whose 'alterations' they
|
|
are. However, he actually says' that the truest account is to affirm
|
|
that each of them is "gold"'.) Nevertheless he carries his analysis of
|
|
the 'elements'-solids though they are-back to 'planes', and it is
|
|
impossible for 'the Nurse' (i.e. the primary matter) to be identical
|
|
with 'the planes'.
|
|
|
|
Our own doctrine is that although there is a matter of the
|
|
perceptible bodies (a matter out of which the so-called 'clements'
|
|
come-to-be), it has no separate existence, but is always bound up with
|
|
a contrariety. A more precise account of these presuppositions has
|
|
been given in another work': we must, however, give a detailed
|
|
explanation of the primary bodies as well, since they too are
|
|
similarly derived from the matter. We must reckon as an 'originative
|
|
source' and as 'primary' the matter which underlies, though it is
|
|
inseparable from, the contrary qualities: for the hot' is not matter
|
|
for 'the cold' nor 'the cold' for 'the hot', but the substratum is
|
|
matter for them both. We therefore have to recognize three
|
|
'originative sources': firstly that which potentially perceptible
|
|
body, secondly the contrarieties (I mean, e.g. heat and cold), and
|
|
thirdly Fire, Water, and the like. Only 'thirdly', however: for
|
|
these bodies change into one another (they are not immutable as
|
|
Empedocles and other thinkers assert, since 'alteration' would then
|
|
have been impossible), whereas the contrarieties do not change.
|
|
|
|
Nevertheless, even so the question remains: What sorts of
|
|
contrarieties, and how many of them, are to be accounted
|
|
'originative sources' of body? For all the other thinkers assume and
|
|
use them without explaining why they are these or why they are just so
|
|
many.
|
|
|
|
2
|
|
|
|
Since, then, we are looking for 'originative sources' of perceptible
|
|
body; and since 'perceptible' is equivalent to 'tangible', and
|
|
'tangible' is that of which the perception is touch; it is clear
|
|
that not all the contrarieties constitute 'forms' and 'originative
|
|
sources' of body, but only those which correspond to touch. For it
|
|
is in accordance with a contrariety-a contrariety, moreover, of
|
|
tangible qualities-that the primary bodies are differentiated. That is
|
|
why neither whiteness (and blackness), nor sweetness (and bitterness),
|
|
nor (similarly) any quality belonging to the other perceptible
|
|
contrarieties either, constitutes an 'element'. And yet vision is
|
|
prior to touch, so that its object also is prior to the object of
|
|
touch. The object of vision, however, is a quality of tangible body
|
|
not qua tangible, but qua something else-qua something which may
|
|
well be naturally prior to the object of touch.
|
|
|
|
Accordingly, we must segregate the tangible differences and
|
|
contrarieties, and distinguish which amongst them are primary.
|
|
Contrarieties correlative to touch are the following: hot-cold,
|
|
dry-moist, heavy-light, hard-soft, viscous-brittle, rough-smooth,
|
|
coarse-fine. Of these (i) heavy and light are neither active nor
|
|
susceptible. Things are not called 'heavy' and 'light' because they
|
|
act upon, or suffer action from, other things. But the 'elements' must
|
|
be reciprocally active and susceptible, since they 'combine' and are
|
|
transformed into one another. On the other hand (ii) hot and cold, and
|
|
dry and moist, are terms, of which the first pair implies power to act
|
|
and the second pair susceptibility. 'Hot' is that which 'associates'
|
|
things of the same kind (for 'dissociating', which people attribute to
|
|
Fire as its function, is 'associating' things of the same class, since
|
|
its effect is to eliminate what is foreign), while 'cold' is that
|
|
which brings together, i.e. 'associates', homogeneous and
|
|
heterogeneous things alike. And moise is that which, being readily
|
|
adaptable in shape, is not determinable by any limit of its own: while
|
|
'dry' is that which is readily determinable by its own limit, but
|
|
not readily adaptable in shape.
|
|
|
|
From moist and dry are derived (iii) the fine and coarse, viscous
|
|
and brittle, hard and soft, and the remaining tangible differences.
|
|
For (a) since the moist has no determinate shape, but is readily
|
|
adaptable and follows the outline of that which is in contact with it,
|
|
it is characteristic of it to be 'such as to fill up'. Now 'the
|
|
fine' is 'such as to fill up'. For the fine' consists of subtle
|
|
particles; but that which consists of small particles is 'such as to
|
|
fill up', inasmuch as it is in contact whole with whole-and 'the fine'
|
|
exhibits this character in a superlative degree. Hence it is evident
|
|
that the fine derives from the moist, while the coarse derives from
|
|
the dry. Again (b) the viscous' derives from the moist: for 'the
|
|
viscous' (e.g. oil) is a 'moist' modified in a certain way. 'The
|
|
brittle', on the other hand, derives from the dry: for 'brittle' is
|
|
that which is completely dry-so completely, that its solidification
|
|
has actually been due to failure of moisture. Further (c) 'the soft'
|
|
derives from the moist. For 'soft' is that which yields to pressure by
|
|
retiring into itself, though it does not yield by total displacement
|
|
as the moist does-which explains why the moist is not 'soft', although
|
|
'the soft' derives from the moist. 'The hard', on the other hand,
|
|
derives from the dry: for 'hard' is that which is solidified, and
|
|
the solidified is dry.
|
|
|
|
The terms 'dry' and 'moist' have more senses than one. For 'the
|
|
damp', as well as the moist, is opposed to the dry: and again 'the
|
|
solidified', as well as the dry, is opposed to the moist. But all
|
|
these qualities derive from the dry and moist we mentioned first.' For
|
|
(i) the dry is opposed to the damp: i.e. 'damp' is that which has
|
|
foreign moisture on its surface ('sodden' being that which is
|
|
penetrated to its core), while 'dry' is that which has lost foreign
|
|
moisture. Hence it is evident that the damp will derive from the
|
|
moist, and 'the dry' which is opposed to it will derive from the
|
|
primary dry. Again (ii) the 'moist' and the solidified derive in the
|
|
same way from the primary pair. For 'moist' is that which contains
|
|
moisture of its-own deep within it ('sodden' being that which is
|
|
deeply penetrated by foreign mosture), whereas 'solidigied' is that
|
|
which has lost this inner moisture. Hence these too derive from the
|
|
primary pair, the 'solidified' from the dry and the 'solidified'
|
|
from the dry the 'liquefiable' from the moist.
|
|
|
|
It is clear, then, that all the other differences reduce to the
|
|
first four, but that these admit of no further reduction. For the
|
|
hot is not essentially moist or dry, nor the moist essentially hot
|
|
or cold: nor are the cold and the dry derivative forms, either of
|
|
one another or of the hot and the moist. Hence these must be four.
|
|
|
|
3
|
|
|
|
The elementary qualities are four, and any four terms can be
|
|
combined in six couples. Contraries, however, refuse to be coupled:
|
|
for it is impossible for the same thing to be hot and cold, or moist
|
|
and dry. Hence it is evident that the 'couplings' of the elementary
|
|
qualities will be four: hot with dry and moist with hot, and again
|
|
cold with dry and cold with moist. And these four couples have
|
|
attached themselves to the apparently 'simple' bodies (Fire, Air,
|
|
Water, and Earth) in a manner consonant with theory. For Fire is hot
|
|
and dry, whereas Air is hot and moist (Air being a sort of aqueous
|
|
vapour); and Water is cold and moist, while Earth is cold and dry.
|
|
Thus the differences are reasonably distributed among the primary
|
|
bodies, and the number of the latter is consonant with theory. For all
|
|
who make the simple bodies 'elements' postulate either one, or two, or
|
|
three, or four. Now (i) those who assert there is one only, and then
|
|
generate everything else by condensation and rarefaction, are in
|
|
effect making their 'originative sources' two, viz. the rare and the
|
|
dense, or rather the hot and the cold: for it is these which are the
|
|
moulding forces, while the 'one' underlies them as a 'matter'. But
|
|
(ii) those who postulate two from the start-as Parmenides postulated
|
|
Fire and Earth-make the intermediates (e.g. Air and Water) blends of
|
|
these. The same course is followed (iii) by those who advocate
|
|
three. (We may compare what Plato does in Me Divisions': for he
|
|
makes 'the middle' a blend.) Indeed, there is practically no
|
|
difference between those who postulate two and those who postulate
|
|
three, except that the former split the middle 'element' into two,
|
|
while the latter treat it as only one. But (iv) some advocate four
|
|
from the start, e.g. Empedocles: yet he too draws them together so
|
|
as to reduce them to the two, for he opposes all the others to Fire.
|
|
|
|
In fact, however, fire and air, and each of the bodies we have
|
|
mentioned, are not simple, but blended. The 'simple' bodies are indeed
|
|
similar in nature to them, but not identical with them. Thus the
|
|
'simple' body corresponding to fire is 'such-as-fire, not fire: that
|
|
which corresponds to air is 'such-as-air': and so on with the rest
|
|
of them. But fire is an excess of heat, just as ice is an excess of
|
|
cold. For freezing and boiling are excesses of heat and cold
|
|
respectively. Assuming, therefore, that ice is a freezing of moist and
|
|
cold, fire analogously will be a boiling of dry and hot: a fact, by
|
|
the way, which explains why nothing comes-to-be either out of ice or
|
|
out of fire.
|
|
|
|
The 'simple' bodies, since they are four, fall into two pairs
|
|
which belong to the two regions, each to each: for Fire and Air are
|
|
forms of the body moving towards the 'limit', while Earth and Water
|
|
are forms of the body which moves towards the 'centre'. Fire and
|
|
Earth, moreover, are extremes and purest: Water and Air, on the
|
|
contrary are intermediates and more like blends. And, further, the
|
|
members of either pair are contrary to those of the other, Water being
|
|
contrary to Fire and Earth to Air; for the qualities constituting
|
|
Water and Earth are contrary to those that constitute Fire and Air.
|
|
Nevertheless, since they are four, each of them is characterized par
|
|
excellence a single quality: Earth by dry rather than by cold, Water
|
|
by cold rather than by moist, Air by moist rather than by hot, and
|
|
Fire by hot rather than by dry.
|
|
|
|
4
|
|
|
|
It has been established before' that the coming-to-be of the
|
|
'simple' bodies is reciprocal. At the same time, it is manifest,
|
|
even on the evidence of perception, that they do come-to-be: for
|
|
otherwise there would not have been 'alteration, since 'alteration' is
|
|
change in respect to the qualities of the objects of touch.
|
|
Consequently, we must explain (i) what is the manner of their
|
|
reciprocal transformation, and (ii) whether every one of them can come
|
|
to-be out of every one-or whether some can do so, but not others.
|
|
|
|
Now it is evident that all of them are by nature such as to change
|
|
into one another: for coming-to-be is a change into contraries and out
|
|
of contraries, and the 'elements' all involve a contrariety in their
|
|
mutual relations because their distinctive qualities are contrary. For
|
|
in some of them both qualities are contrary-e.g. in Fire and Water,
|
|
the first of these being dry and hot, and the second moist and cold:
|
|
while in others one of the qualities (though only one) is
|
|
contrary-e.g. in Air and Water, the first being moist and hot, and the
|
|
second moist and cold. It is evident, therefore, if we consider them
|
|
in general, that every one is by nature such as to come-to-be out of
|
|
every one: and when we come to consider them severally, it is not
|
|
difficult to see the manner in which their transformation is effected.
|
|
For, though all will result from all, both the speed and the
|
|
facility of their conversion will differ in degree.
|
|
|
|
Thus (i) the process of conversion will be quick between those which
|
|
have interchangeable 'complementary factors', but slow between those
|
|
which have none. The reason is that it is easier for a single thing to
|
|
change than for many. Air, e.g. will result from Fire if a single
|
|
quality changes: for Fire, as we saw, is hot and dry while Air is
|
|
hot and moist, so that there will be Air if the dry be overcome by the
|
|
moist. Again, Water will result from Air if the hot be overcome by the
|
|
cold: for Air, as we saw, is hot and moist while Water is cold and
|
|
moist, so that, if the hot changes, there will be Water. So too, in
|
|
the same manner, Earth will result from Water and Fire from Earth,
|
|
since the two 'elements' in both these couples have interchangeable
|
|
'complementary factors'. For Water is moist and cold while Earth is
|
|
cold and dry-so that, if the moist be overcome, there will be Earth:
|
|
and again, since Fire is dry and hot while Earth is cold and dry, Fire
|
|
will result from Earth if the cold pass-away.
|
|
|
|
It is evident, therefore, that the coming-to-be of the 'simple'
|
|
bodies will be cyclical; and that this cyclical method of
|
|
transformation is the easiest, because the consecutive 'clements'
|
|
contain interchangeable 'complementary factors'. On the other hand
|
|
(ii) the transformation of Fire into Water and of Air into Earth,
|
|
and again of Water and Earth into Fire and Air respectively, though
|
|
possible, is more difficult because it involves the change of more
|
|
qualities. For if Fire is to result from Water, both the cold and
|
|
the moist must pass-away: and again, both the cold and the dry must
|
|
pass-away if Air is to result from Earth. So' too, if Water and
|
|
Earth are to result from Fire and Air respectively-both qualities must
|
|
change.
|
|
|
|
This second method of coming-to-be, then, takes a longer time. But
|
|
(iii) if one quality in each of two 'elements' pass-away, the
|
|
transformation, though easier, is not reciprocal. Still, from Fire
|
|
plus Water there will result Earth and Air, and from Air plus Earth
|
|
Fire and Water. For there will be Air, when the cold of the Water
|
|
and the dry of the Fire have passed-away (since the hot of the
|
|
latter and the moist of the former are left): whereas, when the hot of
|
|
the Fire and the moist of the Water have passed-away, there will be
|
|
Earth, owing to the survival of the dry of the Fire and the cold of
|
|
the Water. So, too, in the same Way, Fire and Water will result from
|
|
Air plus Earth. For there will be Water, when the hot of the Air and
|
|
the dry of the Earth have passed-away (since the moist of the former
|
|
and the cold of the latter are left): whereas, when the moist of the
|
|
Air and the cold of the Earth have passed-away, there will be Fire,
|
|
owing to the survival of the hot of the Air and the dry of the
|
|
Earth-qualities essentially constitutive of Fire. Moreover, this
|
|
mode of Fire's coming-to-be is confirmed by perception. For flame is
|
|
par excellence Fire: but flame is burning smoke, and smoke consists of
|
|
Air and Earth.
|
|
|
|
No transformation, however, into any of the 'simple' bodies can
|
|
result from the passingaway of one elementary quality in each of two
|
|
'elements' when they are taken in their consecutive order, because
|
|
either identical or contrary qualities are left in the pair: but no
|
|
'simple' body can be formed either out of identical, or out of
|
|
contrary, qualities. Thus no 'simple' body would result, if the dry of
|
|
Fire and the moist of Air were to pass-away: for the hot is left in
|
|
both. On the other hand, if the hot pass-away out both, the
|
|
contraries-dry and moist-are left. A similar result will occur in
|
|
all the others too: for all the consecutive 'elements' contain one
|
|
identical, and one contrary, quality. Hence, too, it clearly follows
|
|
that, when one of the consecutive 'elements' is transformed into
|
|
one, the coming-to-be is effected by the passing-away of a single
|
|
quality: whereas, when two of them are transformed into a third,
|
|
more than one quality must have passedaway.
|
|
|
|
We have stated that all the 'elements' come-to-be out of any one
|
|
of them; and we have explained the manner in which their mutual
|
|
conversion takes place. Let us nevertheless supplement our theory by
|
|
the following speculations concerning them.
|
|
|
|
5
|
|
|
|
If Water, Air, and the like are a 'matter' of which the natural
|
|
bodies consist, as some thinkers in fact believe, these 'clements'
|
|
must be either one, or two, or more. Now they cannot all of them be
|
|
one-they cannot, e.g. all be Air or Water or Fire or Earth-because
|
|
'Change is into contraries'. For if they all were Air, then
|
|
(assuming Air to persist) there will be 'alteration' instead of
|
|
coming-to-be. Besides, nobody supposes a single 'element' to
|
|
persist, as the basis of all, in such a way that it is Water as well
|
|
as Air (or any other 'element') at the same time. So there will be a
|
|
certain contrariety, i.e. a differentiating quality: and the other
|
|
member of this contrariety, e.g. heat, will belong to some other
|
|
'element', e.g. to Fire. But Fire will certainly not be 'hot Air'. For
|
|
a change of that kind (a) is 'alteration', and (b) is not what is
|
|
observed. Moreover (c) if Air is again to result out of the Fire, it
|
|
will do so by the conversion of the hot into its contrary: this
|
|
contrary, therefore, will belong to Air, and Air will be a cold
|
|
something: hence it is impossible for Fire to be 'hot Air', since in
|
|
that case the same thing will be simultaneously hot and cold. Both
|
|
Fire and Air, therefore, will be something else which is the same;
|
|
i.e. there will be some 'matter', other than either, common to both.
|
|
|
|
The same argument applies to all the 'elements', proving that
|
|
there is no single one of them out of which they all originate. But
|
|
neither is there, beside these four, some other body from which they
|
|
originate-a something intermediate, e.g. between Air and Water
|
|
(coarser than Air, but finer than Water), or between Air and Fire
|
|
(coarser than Fire, but finer than Air). For the supposed
|
|
'intermediate' will be Air and Fire when a pair of contrasted
|
|
qualities is added to it: but, since one of every two contrary
|
|
qualities is a 'privation', the 'intermediate' never can exist-as some
|
|
thinkers assert the 'Boundless' or the 'Environing' exists-in
|
|
isolation. It is, therefore, equally and indifferently any one of
|
|
the 'elements', or else it is nothing.
|
|
|
|
Since, then, there is nothing-at least, nothing perceptible-prior to
|
|
these, they must be all. That being so, either they must always
|
|
persist and not be transformable into one another: or they must
|
|
undergo transformation-either all of them, or some only (as Plato
|
|
wrote in the Timacus).' Now it has been proved before that they must
|
|
undergo reciprocal transformation. It has also been proved that the
|
|
speed with which they come-to-be, one out of another, is not
|
|
uniform-since the process of reciprocal transformation is relatively
|
|
quick between the 'elements' with a 'complementary factor', but
|
|
relatively slow between those which possess no such factor.
|
|
Assuming, then, that the contrariety, in respect to which they are
|
|
transformed, is one, the elements' will inevitably be two: for it is
|
|
'matter' that is the 'mean' between the two contraries, and matter
|
|
is imperceptible and inseparable from them. Since, however, the
|
|
'elements' are seen to be more than two, the contrarieties must at the
|
|
least be two. But the contrarieties being two, the 'elements' must
|
|
be four (as they evidently are) and cannot be three: for the
|
|
couplings' are four, since, though six are possible, the two in
|
|
which the qualities are contrary to one another cannot occur.
|
|
|
|
These subjects have been discussed before:' but the following
|
|
arguments will make it clear that, since the 'elements' are
|
|
transformed into one another, it is impossible for any one of
|
|
them-whether it be at the end or in the middle-to be an 'originative
|
|
source' of the rest. There can be no such 'originative element' at the
|
|
ends: for all of them would then be Fire or Earth, and this theory
|
|
amounts to the assertion that all things are made of Fire or Earth.
|
|
Nor can a 'middle-element' be such an originative source'-as some
|
|
thinkers suppose that Air is transformed both into Fire and into
|
|
Water, and Water both into Air and into Earth, while the
|
|
'end-elements' are not further transformed into one another. For the
|
|
process must come to a stop, and cannot continue ad infinitum in a
|
|
straight line in either direction, since otherwise an infinite
|
|
number of contrarieties would attach to the single 'element'. Let E
|
|
stand for Earth, W for Water, A for Air, and F for Fire. Then (i)
|
|
since A is transformed into F and W, there will be a contrariety
|
|
belonging to A F. Let these contraries be whiteness and blackness.
|
|
Again (ii) since A is transformed into W, there will be another
|
|
contrariety: for W is not the same as F. Let this second contrariety
|
|
be dryness and moistness, D being dryness and M moistness. Now if,
|
|
when A is transformed into W, the 'white' persists, Water will be
|
|
moist and white: but if it does not persist, Water will be black since
|
|
change is into contraries. Water, therefore, must be either white or
|
|
black. Let it then be the first. On similar grounds, therefore, D
|
|
(dryness) will also belong to F. Consequently F (Fire) as well as
|
|
Air will be able to be transformed into Water: for it has qualities
|
|
contrary to those of Water, since Fire was first taken to be black and
|
|
then to be dry, while Water was moist and then showed itself white.
|
|
Thus it is evident that all the 'elements' will be able to be
|
|
transformed out of one another; and that, in the instances we have
|
|
taken, E (Earth) also will contain the remaining two 'complementary
|
|
factors', viz. the black and the moist (for these have not yet been
|
|
coupled).
|
|
|
|
We have dealt with this last topic before the thesis we set out to
|
|
prove. That thesis-viz. that the process cannot continue ad
|
|
infinitum-will be clear from the following considerations. If Fire
|
|
(which is represented by F) is not to revert, but is to be transformed
|
|
in turn into some other 'element' (e.g. into Q), a new contrariety,
|
|
other than those mentioned, will belong to Fire and Q: for it has been
|
|
assumed that Q is not the same as any of the four, E W A and F. Let K,
|
|
then, belong to F and Y to Q. Then K will belong to all four, E W A
|
|
and F: for they are transformed into one another. This last point,
|
|
however, we may admit, has not yet been proved: but at any rate it
|
|
is clear that if Q is to be transformed in turn into yet another
|
|
'element', yet another contrariety will belong not only to Q but
|
|
also to F (Fire). And, similarly, every addition of a new 'element'
|
|
will carry with it the attachment of a new contrariety to the
|
|
preceding elements'. Consequently, if the 'elements' are infinitely
|
|
many, there will also belong to the single 'element' an infinite
|
|
number of contrarieties. But if that be so, it will be impossible to
|
|
define any 'element': impossible also for any to come-to-be. For if
|
|
one is to result from another, it will have to pass through such a
|
|
vast number of contrarieties-and indeed even more than any determinate
|
|
number. Consequently (i) into some 'elements' transformation will
|
|
never be effected-viz. if the intermediates are infinite in number, as
|
|
they must be if the 'elements' are infinitely many: further (ii) there
|
|
will not even be a transformation of Air into Fire, if the
|
|
contrarieties are infinitely many: moreover (iii) all the 'elements'
|
|
become one. For all the contrarieties of the 'elements' above F must
|
|
belong to those below F, and vice versa: hence they will all be one.
|
|
|
|
6
|
|
|
|
As for those who agree with Empedocles that the 'elements' of body
|
|
are more than one, so that they are not transformed into one
|
|
another-one may well wonder in what sense it is open to them to
|
|
maintain that the 'elements' are comparable. Yet Empedocles says
|
|
'For these are all not only equal...'
|
|
|
|
If it is meant that they are comparable in their amount, all the
|
|
'comparables' must possess an identical something whereby they are
|
|
measured. If, e.g. one pint of Water yields ten of Air, both are
|
|
measured by the same unit; and therefore both were from the first an
|
|
identical something. On the other hand, suppose (ii) they are not
|
|
'comparable in their amount' in the sense that so-much of the one
|
|
yields so much of the other, but comparable in 'power of action (a
|
|
pint of Water, e.g. having a power of cooling equal to that of ten
|
|
pints of Air); even so, they are 'comparable in their amount',
|
|
though not qua 'amount' but qua Iso-much power'. There is also (iii) a
|
|
third possibility. Instead of comparing their powers by the measure of
|
|
their amount, they might be compared as terms in a 'correspondence':
|
|
e.g. 'as x is hot, so correspondingly y is white'. But
|
|
'correspondence', though it means equality in the quantum, means
|
|
similarity in a quale. Thus it is manifestly absurd that the
|
|
'simple' bodies, though they are not transformable, are comparable not
|
|
merely as 'corresponding', but by a measure of their powers; i.e. that
|
|
so-much Fire is comparable with many times-that-amount of Air, as
|
|
being 'equally' or 'similarly' hot. For the same thing, if it be
|
|
greater in amount, will, since it belongs to the same kind, have its
|
|
ratio correspondingly increased.
|
|
|
|
A further objection to the theory of Empedocles is that it makes
|
|
even growth impossible, unless it be increase by addition. For his
|
|
Fire increases by Fire: 'And Earth increases its own frame and Ether
|
|
increases Ether." These, however, are cases of addition: but it is not
|
|
by addition that growing things are believed to increase. And it is
|
|
far more difficult for him to account for the coming-to-be which
|
|
occurs in nature. For the things which come-to-be by natural process
|
|
all exhibit, in their coming-to-be, a uniformity either absolute or
|
|
highly regular: while any exceptions any results which are in
|
|
accordance neither with the invariable nor with the general rule are
|
|
products of chance and luck. Then what is the cause determining that
|
|
man comes-to-be from man, that wheat (instead of an olive) comes-to-be
|
|
from wheat, either invariably or generally? Are we to say 'Bone
|
|
comes-to-be if the "elements" be put together in such-and such a
|
|
manner'? For, according to his own estatements, nothing comes-to-be
|
|
from their 'fortuitous consilience', but only from their 'consilience'
|
|
in a certain proportion. What, then, is the cause of this proportional
|
|
consilience? Presumably not Fire or Earth. But neither is it Love
|
|
and Strife: for the former is a cause of 'association' only, and the
|
|
latter only of 'dissociation'. No: the cause in question is the
|
|
essential nature of each thing-not merely to quote his words) 'a
|
|
mingling and a divorce of what has been mingled'. And chance, not
|
|
proportion, 'is the name given to these occurrences': for things can
|
|
be 'mingled' fortuitously.
|
|
|
|
The cause, therefore, of the coming-to-be of the things which owe
|
|
their existence to nature is that they are in such-and-such a
|
|
determinate condition: and it is this which constitutes, the
|
|
'nature' of each thing-a 'nature' about which he says nothing. What he
|
|
says, therefore, is no explanation of 'nature'. Moreover, it is this
|
|
which is both 'the excellence' of each thing and its 'good': whereas
|
|
he assigns the whole credit to the 'mingling'. (And yet the 'elements'
|
|
at all events are 'dissociated' not by Strife, but by Love: since
|
|
the 'elements' are by nature prior to the Deity, and they too are
|
|
Deities.)
|
|
|
|
Again, his account of motion is vague. For it is not an adequate
|
|
explanation to say that 'Love and Strife set things moving, unless the
|
|
very nature of Love is a movement of this kind and the very nature
|
|
of Strife a movement of that kind. He ought, then, either to have
|
|
defined or to have postulated these characteristic movements, or to
|
|
have demonstrated them-whether strictly or laxly or in some other
|
|
fashion. Moreover, since (a) the 'simple' bodies appear to move
|
|
'naturally' as well as by compulsion, i.e. in a manner contrary to
|
|
nature (fire, e.g. appears to move upwards without compulsion,
|
|
though it appears to move by compulsion downwards); and since (b) what
|
|
is 'natural' is contrary to that which is due to compulsion, and
|
|
movement by compulsion actually occurs; it follows that 'natural
|
|
movement' can also occur in fact. Is this, then, the movement that
|
|
Love sets going? No: for, on the contrary, the 'natural movement'
|
|
moves Earth downwards and resembles 'dissociation', and Strife
|
|
rather than Love is its cause-so that in general, too, Love rather
|
|
than Strife would seem to be contrary to nature. And unless Love or
|
|
Strife is actually setting them in motion, the 'simple' bodies
|
|
themselves have absolutely no movement or rest. But this is
|
|
paradoxical: and what is more, they do in fact obviously move. For
|
|
though Strife 'dissociated', it was not by Strife that the 'Ether' was
|
|
borne upwards. On the contrary, sometimes he attributes its movement
|
|
to something like chance ('For thus, as it ran, it happened to meet
|
|
them then, though often otherwise"), while at other times he says it
|
|
is the nature of Fire to be borne upwards, but 'the Ether' (to quote
|
|
his words) 'sank down upon the Earth with long roots'. With such
|
|
statements, too, he combines the assertion that the Order of the World
|
|
is the same now, in the reign of Strife, as it was formerly in the
|
|
reign of Love. What, then, is the 'first mover' of the 'elements'?
|
|
What causes their motion? Presumably not Love and Strife: on the
|
|
contrary, these are causes of a particular motion, if at least we
|
|
assume that 'first mover' to be an originative source'.
|
|
|
|
An additional paradox is that the soul should consist of the
|
|
'elements', or that it should be one of them. How are the soul's
|
|
'alterations' to take Place? How, e.g. is the change from being
|
|
musical to being unmusical, or how is memory or forgetting, to
|
|
occur? For clearly, if the soul be Fire, only such modifications
|
|
will happen to it as characterize Fire qua Fire: while if it be
|
|
compounded out of the elements', only the corporeal modifications will
|
|
occur in it. But the changes we have mentioned are none of them
|
|
corporeal.
|
|
|
|
7
|
|
|
|
The discussion of these difficulties, however, is a task appropriate
|
|
to a different investigation:' let us return to the 'elements' of
|
|
which bodies are composed. The theories that 'there is something
|
|
common to all the "elements"', and that they are reciprocally
|
|
transformed', are so related that those who accept either are bound to
|
|
accept the other as well. Those, on the other hand, who do not make
|
|
their coming-to-be reciprocal-who refuse to suppose that any one of
|
|
the 'elements' comes-to-be out of any other taken singly, except in
|
|
the sense in which bricks come-to-be out of a wall-are faced with a
|
|
paradox. How, on their theory, are flesh and bones or any of the other
|
|
compounds to result from the 'elements' taken together?
|
|
|
|
Indeed, the point we have raised constitutes a problem even for
|
|
those who generate the 'elements' out of one another. In what manner
|
|
does anything other than, and beside, the 'elements' come-to-be out of
|
|
them? Let me illustrate my meaning. Water can come-to-be out of Fire
|
|
and Fire out of Water; for their substralum is something common to
|
|
them both. But flesh too, presumably, and marrow come-to-be out of
|
|
them. How, then, do such things come to-be? For (a) how is the
|
|
manner of their coming-to-be to be conceived by those who maintain a
|
|
theory like that of Empedocles? They must conceive it as
|
|
composition-just as a wall comes-to-be out of bricks and stones: and
|
|
the 'Mixture', of which they speak, will be composed of the
|
|
'elements', these being preserved in it unaltered but with their small
|
|
particles juxtaposed each to each. That will be the manner,
|
|
presumably, in which flesh and every other compound results from the
|
|
'elements'. Consequently, it follows that Fire and Water do not
|
|
come-to-be 'out of any and every part of flesh'. For instance,
|
|
although a sphere might come-to-be out of this part of a lump of wax
|
|
and a pyramid out of some other part, it was nevertheless possible for
|
|
either figure to have come-to-be out of either part indifferently:
|
|
that is the manner of coming-to-be when 'both Fire and Water
|
|
come-to-be out of any and every part of flesh'. Those, however, who
|
|
maintain the theory in question, are not at liberty to conceive that
|
|
'both come-to-be out of flesh' in that manner, but only as a stone and
|
|
a brick 'both come-to-be out of a wall'-viz. each out of a different
|
|
place or part. Similarly (b) even for those who postulate a single
|
|
matter of their 'elements' there is a certain difficulty in explaining
|
|
how anything is to result from two of them taken together-e.g. from
|
|
'cold' and hot', or from Fire and Earth. For if flesh consists of both
|
|
and is neither of them, nor again is a 'composition' of them in
|
|
which they are preserved unaltered, what alternative is left except to
|
|
identify the resultant of the two 'elements' with their matter? For
|
|
the passingaway of either 'element' produces either the other or the
|
|
matter.
|
|
|
|
Perhaps we may suggest the following solution. (i) There are
|
|
differences of degree in hot and cold. Although, therefore, when
|
|
either is fully real without qualification, the other will exist
|
|
potentially; yet, when neither exists in the full completeness of
|
|
its being, but both by combining destroy one another's excesses so
|
|
that there exist instead a hot which (for a 'hot') is cold and a
|
|
cold which (for a 'cold') is hot; then what results from these two
|
|
contraries will be neither their matter, nor either of them existing
|
|
in its full reality without qualification. There will result instead
|
|
an 'intermediate': and this 'intermediate', according as it is
|
|
potentially more hot than cold or vice versa, will possess a
|
|
power-of-heating that is double or triple its power-of-cooling, or
|
|
otherwise related thereto in some similar ratio. Thus all the other
|
|
bodies will result from the contraries, or rather from the 'elements',
|
|
in so far as these have been 'combined': while the elements' will
|
|
result from the contraries, in so far as these 'exist potentially'
|
|
in a special sense-not as matter 'exists potentially', but in the
|
|
sense explained above. And when a thing comes-to-be in this manner,
|
|
the process is cobination'; whereas what comes-to-be in the other
|
|
manner is matter. Moreover (ii) contraries also 'suffer action', in
|
|
accordance with the disjunctively-articulated definition established
|
|
in the early part of this work.' For the actually-hot is
|
|
potentially-cold and the actually cold potentially-hot; so that hot
|
|
and cold, unless they are equally balanced, are transformed into one
|
|
another (and all the other contraries behave in a similar way). It
|
|
is thus, then, that in the first place the 'elements' are transformed;
|
|
and that (in the second place) out of the 'elements' there
|
|
come-to-be flesh and bones and the like-the hot becoming cold and
|
|
the cold becoming hot when they have been brought to the 'mean'. For
|
|
at the 'mean' is neither hot nor cold. The 'mean', however, is of
|
|
considerable extent and not indivisible. Similarly, it is qua
|
|
reduced to a 'mean' condition that the dry and the moist, as well as
|
|
the contraries we have used as examples, produce flesh and bone and
|
|
the remaining compounds.
|
|
|
|
8
|
|
|
|
All the compound bodies-all of which exist in the region belonging
|
|
to the central body-are composed of all the 'simple' bodies. For
|
|
they all contain Earth because every 'simple' body is to be found
|
|
specially and most abundantly in its own place. And they all contain
|
|
Water because (a) the compound must possess a definite outline and
|
|
Water, alone of the 'simple' bodies, is readily adaptable in shape:
|
|
moreover (b) Earth has no power of cohesion without the moist. On
|
|
the contrary, the moist is what holds it together; for it would fall
|
|
to pieces if the moist were eliminated from it completely.
|
|
|
|
They contain Earth and Water, then, for the reasons we have given:
|
|
and they contain Air and Fire, because these are contrary to Earth and
|
|
Water (Earth being contrary to Air and Water to Fire, in so far as one
|
|
Substance can be 'contrary' to another). Now all compounds
|
|
presuppose in their coming-to-be constituents which are contrary to
|
|
one another: and in all compounds there is contained one set of the
|
|
contrasted extremes. Hence the other set must be contained in them
|
|
also, so that every compound will include all the 'simple' bodies.
|
|
|
|
Additional evidence seems to be furnished by the food each
|
|
compound takes. For all of them are fed by substances which are the
|
|
same as their constituents, and all of them are fed by more substances
|
|
than one. Indeed, even the plants, though it might be thought they are
|
|
fed by one substance only, viz. by Water, are fed by more than one:
|
|
for Earth has been mixed with the Water. That is why farmers too
|
|
endeavour to mix before watering. Although food is akin to the matter,
|
|
that which is fed is the 'figure'-i.e. the 'form' taken along with the
|
|
matter. This fact enables us to understand why, whereas all the
|
|
'simple' bodies come-to-be out of one another, Fire is the only one of
|
|
them which (as our predecessors also assert) 'is fed'. For Fire
|
|
alone-or more than all the rest-is akin to the 'form' because it tends
|
|
by nature to be borne towards the limit. Now each of them naturally
|
|
tends to be borne towards its own place; but the 'figure'-i.e. the
|
|
'form'-Of them all is at the limits.
|
|
|
|
Thus we have explained that all the compound bodies are composed
|
|
of all the 'simple' bodies.
|
|
|
|
9
|
|
|
|
Since some things are such as to come-to-be and pass-away, and since
|
|
coming-to-be in fact occurs in the region about the centre, we must
|
|
explain the number and the nature of the 'originative sources' of
|
|
all coming-to-be alike: for a grasp of the true theory of any
|
|
universal facilitates the understanding of its specific forms.
|
|
|
|
The 'originative sources', then, of the things which come-to-be
|
|
are equal in number to, and identical in kind with, those in the
|
|
sphere of the eternal and primary things. For there is one in the
|
|
sense of 'matter', and a second in the sense of 'form': and, in
|
|
addition, the third 'originative source' must be present as well.
|
|
For the two first are not sufficient to bring things into being, any
|
|
more than they are adequate to account for the primary things.
|
|
|
|
Now cause, in the sense of material origin, for the things which
|
|
are such as to come-to-be is 'that which can be-and-not-be': and
|
|
this is identical with'that which can come-to-be-and-pass-away', since
|
|
the latter, while it is at one time, at another time is not. (For
|
|
whereas some things are of necessity, viz. the eternal things,
|
|
others of necessity are not. And of these two sets of things, since
|
|
they cannot diverge from the necessity of their nature, it is
|
|
impossible for the first not to he and impossible for the second to
|
|
he. Other things, however, can both be and not he.) Hence coming-to-be
|
|
and passing-away must occur within the field of 'that which can be-and
|
|
not-be'. This, therefore, is cause in the sense of material origin for
|
|
the things which are such as to come-to-be; while cause, in the
|
|
sense of their 'end', is their 'figure' or 'form'-and that is the
|
|
formula expressing the essential nature of each of them.
|
|
|
|
But the third 'originative source' must be present as well-the cause
|
|
vaguely dreamed of by all our predecessors, definitely stated by
|
|
none of them. On the contrary (a) some amongst them thought the nature
|
|
of 'the Forms' was adequate to account for coming-to-be. Thus Socrates
|
|
in the Phaedo first blames everybody else for having given no
|
|
explanation; and then lays it down; that 'some things are Forms,
|
|
others Participants in the Forms', and that 'while a thing is said
|
|
to "be" in virtue of the Form, it is said to "come-to-be" qua
|
|
sharing in," to "pass-away" qua "losing," the 'Form'. Hence he
|
|
thinks that 'assuming the truth of these theses, the Forms must be
|
|
causes both of coming-to-be and of passing-away'. On the other hand
|
|
(b) there were others who thought 'the matter' was adequate by
|
|
itself to account for coming-to-be, since 'the movement originates
|
|
from the matter'.
|
|
|
|
Neither of these theories, however, is sound. For (a) if the Forms
|
|
are causes, why is their generating activity intermittent instead of
|
|
perpetual and continuous-since there always are Participants as well
|
|
as Forms? Besides, in some instances we see that the cause is other
|
|
than the Form. For it is the doctor who implants health and the man of
|
|
science who implants science, although 'Health itself' and 'Science
|
|
itself' are as well as the Participants: and the same principle
|
|
applies to everything else that is produced in accordance with an art.
|
|
On the other hand (b) to say that 'matter generates owing to its
|
|
movement' would be, no doubt, more scientific than to make such
|
|
statements as are made by the thinkers we have been criticizing. For
|
|
what 'alters' and transfigures plays a greater part in bringing,
|
|
things into being; and we are everywhere accustomed, in the products
|
|
of nature and of art alike, to look upon that which can initiate
|
|
movement as the producing cause. Nevertheless this second theory is
|
|
not right either.
|
|
|
|
For, to begin with, it is characteristic of matter to suffer action,
|
|
i.e. to be moved: but to move, i.e. to act, belongs to a different
|
|
'power'. This is obvious both in the things that come-to-be by art and
|
|
in those that come to-be by nature. Water does not of itself produce
|
|
out of itself an animal: and it is the art, not the wood, that makes a
|
|
bed. Nor is this their only error. They make a second mistake in
|
|
omitting the more controlling cause: for they eliminate the
|
|
essential nature, i.e. the 'form'. And what is more, since they remove
|
|
the formal cause, they invest the forces they assign to the 'simple'
|
|
bodies-the forces which enable these bodies to bring things into
|
|
being-with too instrumental a character. For 'since' (as they say) 'it
|
|
is the nature of the hot to dissociate, of the cold to bring together,
|
|
and of each remaining contrary either to act or to suffer action',
|
|
it is out of such materials and by their agency (so they maintain)
|
|
that everything else comes-to-be and passes-away. Yet (a) it is
|
|
evident that even Fire is itself moved, i.e. suffers action.
|
|
Moreover (b) their procedure is virtually the same as if one were to
|
|
treat the saw (and the various instruments of carpentry) as 'the
|
|
cause' of the things that come-to-be: for the wood must be divided
|
|
if a man saws, must become smooth if he planes, and so on with the
|
|
remaining tools. Hence, however true it may be that Fire is active,
|
|
i.e. sets things moving, there is a further point they fail to
|
|
observe-viz. that Fire is inferior to the tools or instruments in
|
|
the manner in which it sets things moving.
|
|
|
|
10
|
|
|
|
As to our own theory-we have given a general account of the causes
|
|
in an earlier work,' we have now explained and distinguished the
|
|
'matter' and the 'form'. Further, since the change which is motion has
|
|
been proved' to be eternal, the continuity of the occurrence of
|
|
coming-to-be follows necessarily from what we have established: for
|
|
the eternal motion, by causing 'the generator' to approach and retire,
|
|
will produce coming-to-be uninterruptedly. At the same time it is
|
|
clear that we were right when, in an earlier work,' we called motion
|
|
(not coming-to-be) 'the primary form of change'. For it is far more
|
|
reasonable that what is should cause the coming-to-be of what is
|
|
not, than that what is not should cause the being of what is. Now that
|
|
which is being moved is, but that which is coming-to-be is not: hence,
|
|
also, motion is prior to coming-to-be.
|
|
|
|
We have assumed, and have proved, that coming-to-be and passing-away
|
|
happen to things continuously; and we assert that motion causes
|
|
coming-to-be. That being so, it is evident that, if the motion be
|
|
single, both processes cannot occur since they are contrary to one
|
|
another: for it is a law of nature that the same cause, provided it
|
|
remain in the same condition, always produces the same effect, so
|
|
that, from a single motion, either coming-to-be or passing-away will
|
|
always result. The movements must, on the contrary, be more than
|
|
one, and they must be contrasted with one another either by the
|
|
sense of their motion or by its irregularity: for contrary effects
|
|
demand contraries as their causes.
|
|
|
|
This explains why it is not the primary motion that causes
|
|
coming-to-be and passingaway, but the motion along the inclined
|
|
circle: for this motion not only possesses the necessary continuity,
|
|
but includes a duality of movements as well. For if coming-to-be and
|
|
passing-away are always to be continuous, there must be some body
|
|
always being moved (in order that these changes may not fail) and
|
|
moved with a duality of movements (in order that both changes, not one
|
|
only, may result). Now the continuity of this movement is caused by
|
|
the motion of the whole: but the approaching and retreating of the
|
|
moving body are caused by the inclination. For the consequence of
|
|
the inclination is that the body becomes alternately remote and
|
|
near; and since its distance is thus unequal, its movement will be
|
|
irregular. Therefore, if it generates by approaching and by its
|
|
proximity, it-this very same body-destroys by retreating and
|
|
becoming remote: and if it generates by many successive approaches, it
|
|
also destroys by many successive retirements. For contrary effects
|
|
demand contraries as their causes; and the natural processes of
|
|
passing-away and coming-to-be occupy equal periods of time. Hence,
|
|
too, the times-i.e. the lives-of the several kinds of living things
|
|
have a number by which they are distinguished: for there is an Order
|
|
controlling all things, and every time (i.e. every life) is measured
|
|
by a period. Not all of them, however, are measured by the same
|
|
period, but some by a smaller and others by a greater one: for to some
|
|
of them the period, which is their measure, is a year, while to some
|
|
it is longer and to others shorter.
|
|
|
|
And there are facts of observation in manifest agreement with our
|
|
theories. Thus we see that coming-to-be occurs as the sun approaches
|
|
and decay as it retreats; and we see that the two processes occupy
|
|
equal times. For the durations of the natural processes of
|
|
passing-away and coming-to-be are equal. Nevertheless it Often happens
|
|
that things pass-away in too short a time. This is due to the
|
|
'intermingling' by which the things that come-to-be and pass-away
|
|
are implicated with one another. For their matter is 'irregular', i.e.
|
|
is not everywhere the same: hence the processes by which they
|
|
come-to-be must be 'irregular' too, i.e. some too quick and others too
|
|
slow. Consequently the phenomenon in question occurs, because the
|
|
'irregular' coming-to-be of these things is the passing-away of
|
|
other things.
|
|
|
|
Coming-to-be and passing-away will, as we have said, always be
|
|
continuous, and will never fail owing to the cause we stated. And this
|
|
continuity has a sufficient reason on our theory. For in all things,
|
|
as we affirm, Nature always strives after 'the better'. Now 'being'
|
|
(we have explained elsewhere the exact variety of meanings we
|
|
recognize in this term) is better than 'not-being': but not all things
|
|
can possess 'being', since they are too far removed from the
|
|
'originative source. 'God therefore adopted the remaining alternative,
|
|
and fulfilled the perfection of the universe by making coming-to-be
|
|
uninterrupted: for the greatest possible coherence would thus be
|
|
secured to existence, because that 'coming-to-be should itself
|
|
come-to-be perpetually' is the closest approximation to eternal being.
|
|
|
|
The cause of this perpetuity of coming-to-be, as we have often said,
|
|
is circular motion: for that is the only motion which is continuous.
|
|
That, too, is why all the other things-the things, I mean, which are
|
|
reciprocally transformed in virtue of their 'passions' and their
|
|
'powers of action' e.g. the 'simple' bodiesimitate circular motion.
|
|
For when Water is transformed into Air, Air into Fire, and the Fire
|
|
back into Water, we say the coming-to-be 'has completed the circle',
|
|
because it reverts again to the beginning. Hence it is by imitating
|
|
circular motion that rectilinear motion too is continuous.
|
|
|
|
These considerations serve at the same time to explain what is to
|
|
some people a baffling problem-viz. why the 'simple' bodies, since
|
|
each them is travelling towards its own place, have not become
|
|
dissevered from one another in the infinite lapse of time. The
|
|
reason is their reciprocal transformation. For, had each of them
|
|
persisted in its own place instead of being transformed by its
|
|
neighbour, they would have got dissevered long ago. They are
|
|
transformed, however, owing to the motion with its dual character: and
|
|
because they are transformed, none of them is able to persist in any
|
|
place allotted to it by the Order.
|
|
|
|
It is clear from what has been said (i) that coming-to-be and
|
|
passing-away actually occur, (ii) what causes them, and (iii) what
|
|
subject undergoes them. But (a) if there is to be movement (as we have
|
|
explained elsewhere, in an earlier work') there must be something
|
|
which initiates it; if there is to be movement always, there must
|
|
always be something which initiates it; if the movement is to be
|
|
continuous, what initiates it must be single, unmoved, ungenerated,
|
|
and incapable of 'alteration'; and if the circular movements are
|
|
more than one, their initiating causes must all of them, in spite of
|
|
their plurality, be in some way subordinated to a single
|
|
'originative source'. Further (b) since time is continuous, movement
|
|
must be continuous, inasmuch as there can be no time without movement.
|
|
Time, therefore, is a 'number' of some continuous movement-a 'number',
|
|
therefore, of the circular movement, as was established in the
|
|
discussions at the beginning. But (c) is movement continuous because
|
|
of the continuity of that which is moved, or because that in which the
|
|
movement occurs (I mean, e.g. the place or the quality) is continuous?
|
|
The answer must clearly be 'because that which is moved is
|
|
continuous'. (For how can the quality be continuous except in virtue
|
|
of the continuity of the thing to which it belongs? But if the
|
|
continuity of 'that in which' contributes to make the movement
|
|
continuous, this is true only of 'the place in which'; for that has
|
|
'magnitude' in a sense.) But (d) amongst continuous bodies which are
|
|
moved, only that which is moved in a circle is 'continuous' in such
|
|
a way that it preserves its continuity with itself throughout the
|
|
movement. The conclusion therefore is that this is what produces
|
|
continuous movement, viz. the body which is being moved in a circle;
|
|
and its movement makes time continuous.
|
|
|
|
11
|
|
|
|
Wherever there is continuity in any process (coming-to-be or
|
|
'alteration' or any kind of change whatever) we observe
|
|
consecutiveness', i.e. this coming-to-be after that without any
|
|
interval. Hence we must investigate whether, amongst the consecutive
|
|
members, there is any whose future being is necessary; or whether,
|
|
on the contrary, every one of them may fail to come-to-be. For that
|
|
some of them may fail to occur, is clear. (a) We need only appeal to
|
|
the distinction between the statements 'x will be' and 'x is about
|
|
to which depends upon this fact. For if it be true to say of x that it
|
|
'will be', it must at some time be true to say of it that 'it is':
|
|
whereas, though it be true to say of x now that 'it is about to
|
|
occur', it is quite possible for it not to come-to-be-thus a man might
|
|
not walk, though he is now 'about to' walk. And (b) since (to appeal
|
|
to a general principle) amongst the things which 'are' some are
|
|
capable also of 'not-being', it is clear that the same ambiguous
|
|
character will attach to them no less when they are coming-to-be: in
|
|
other words, their coming-to-be will not be necessary.
|
|
|
|
Then are all the things that come-to-be of this contingent
|
|
character? Or, on the contrary, is it absolutely necessary for some of
|
|
them to come-to-be? Is there, in fact, a distinction in the field of
|
|
'coming-to-be' corresponding to the distinction, within the field of
|
|
'being', between things that cannot possibly 'not-be' and things
|
|
that can 'not-be'? For instance, is it necessary that solstices
|
|
shall come-to-be, i.e. impossible that they should fail to be able
|
|
to occur?
|
|
|
|
Assuming that the antecedent must have come-to-be if the
|
|
consequent is to be (e.g. that foundations must have come-to-be if
|
|
there is to be a house: clay, if there are to be foundations), is
|
|
the converse also true? If foundations have come-to-be, must a house
|
|
come-to-be? The answer seems to be that the necessary nexus no
|
|
longer holds, unless it is 'necessary' for the consequent (as well
|
|
as for the antecedent) to come-to-be-'necessary' absolutely. If that
|
|
be the case, however, 'a house must come to-be if foundations have
|
|
come-to-be', as well as vice versa. For the antecedent was assumed
|
|
to be so related to the consequent that, if the latter is to be, the
|
|
antecedent must have come-tobe before it. If, therefore, it is
|
|
necessary that the consequent should come-to-be, the antecedent also
|
|
must have come-to-be: and if the antecedent has come-to-be, then the
|
|
consequent also must come-to-be-not, however, because of the
|
|
antecedent, but because the future being of the consequent was assumed
|
|
as necessary. Hence, in any sequence, when the being of the consequent
|
|
is necessary, the nexus is reciprocal-in other words, when the
|
|
antecedent has come-to-be the consequent must always come-to-be too.
|
|
|
|
Now (i) if the sequence of occurrences is to proceed ad infinitum
|
|
'downwards', the coming to-be of any determinate 'this' amongst the
|
|
later members of the sequence will not be absolutely, but only
|
|
conditionally, necessary. For it will always be necessary that some
|
|
other member shall have come-to-be before 'this' as the presupposed
|
|
condition of the necessity that 'this' should come-to-be:
|
|
consequently, since what is 'infinite' has no 'originative source',
|
|
neither will there be in the infinite sequence any 'primary' member
|
|
which will make it 'necessary' for the remaining members to
|
|
come-to-be.
|
|
|
|
Nor again (ii) will it be possible to say with truth, even in regard
|
|
to the members of a limited sequence, that it is 'absolutely
|
|
necessary' for any one of them to come-to-be. We cannot truly say,
|
|
e.g. that 'it is absolutely necessary for a house to come-to-be when
|
|
foundations have been laid': for (unless it is always necessary for
|
|
a house to be coming-to-be) we should be faced with the consequence
|
|
that, when foundations have been laid, a thing, which need not
|
|
always be, must always be. No: if its coming-to-be is to be
|
|
'necessary', it must be 'always' in its coming-to-be. For what is
|
|
'of necessity' coincides with what is 'always', since that which 'must
|
|
be' cannot possibly 'not-be'. Hence a thing is eternal if its
|
|
'being' is necessary: and if it is eternal, its 'being' is
|
|
necessary. And if, therefore, the 'coming-to-be' of a thing is
|
|
necessary, its 'coming-to-be' is eternal; and if eternal, necessary.
|
|
|
|
It follows that the coming-to-be of anything, if it is absolutely
|
|
necessary, must be cyclical-i.e. must return upon itself. For coming
|
|
to-be must either be limited or not limited: and if not limited, it
|
|
must be either rectilinear or cyclical. But the first of these last
|
|
two alternatives is impossible if coming-to-be is to be eternal,
|
|
because there could not be any 'originative source' whatever in an
|
|
infinite rectilinear sequence, whether its members be taken
|
|
'downwards' (as future events) or 'upwards' (as past events). Yet
|
|
coming-to-be must have an 'originative source' (if it is to be
|
|
necessary and therefore eternal), nor can it be eternal if it is
|
|
limited. Consequently it must be cyclical. Hence the nexus must be
|
|
reciprocal. By this I mean that the necessary occurrence of 'this'
|
|
involves the necessary occurrence of its antecedent: and conversely
|
|
that, given the antecedent, it is also necessary for the consequent to
|
|
come-to-be. And this reciprocal nexus will hold continuously
|
|
throughout the sequence: for it makes no difference whether the
|
|
reciprocal nexus, of which we are speaking, is mediated by two, or
|
|
by many, members.
|
|
|
|
It is in circular movement, therefore, and in cyclical
|
|
coming-to-be that the 'absolutely necessary' is to be found. In
|
|
other words, if the coming-to-be of any things is cyclical, it is
|
|
'necessary' that each of them is coming-to-be and has come-to-be:
|
|
and if the coming-to-be of any things is 'necessary', their
|
|
coming-to-be is cyclical.
|
|
|
|
The result we have reached is logically concordant with the eternity
|
|
of circular motion, i.e. the eternity of the revolution of the heavens
|
|
(a fact which approved itself on other and independent evidence),'
|
|
since precisely those movements which belong to, and depend upon, this
|
|
eternal revolution 'come-to-be' of necessity, and of necessity 'will
|
|
be'. For since the revolving body is always setting something else
|
|
in motion, the movement of the things it moves must also be
|
|
circular. Thus, from the being of the 'upper revolution' it follows
|
|
that the sun revolves in this determinate manner; and since the sun
|
|
revolves thus, the seasons in consequence come-to-be in a cycle,
|
|
i.e. return upon themselves; and since they come-to-be cyclically,
|
|
so in their turn do the things whose coming-to-be the seasons
|
|
initiate.
|
|
|
|
Then why do some things manifestly come to-be in this cyclical
|
|
fashion (as, e.g. showers and air, so that it must rain if there is to
|
|
be a cloud and, conversely, there must be a cloud if it is to rain),
|
|
while men and animals do not 'return upon themselves' so that the same
|
|
individual comes-to-be a second time (for though your coming-to-be
|
|
presupposes your father's, his coming-to-be does not presuppose
|
|
yours)? Why, on the contrary, does this coming-to-be seem to
|
|
constitute a rectilinear sequence?
|
|
|
|
In discussing this new problem, we must begin by inquiring whether
|
|
all things 'return upon themselves' in a uniform manner; or whether,
|
|
on the contrary, though in some sequences what recurs is numerically
|
|
the same, in other sequences it is the same only in species. In
|
|
consequence of this distinction, it is evident that those things,
|
|
whose 'substance'-that which is undergoing the process-is
|
|
imperishable, will be numerically, as well as specifically, the same
|
|
in their recurrence: for the character of the process is determined by
|
|
the character of that which undergoes it. Those things, on the other
|
|
hand, whose 'substance' is perish, able (not imperishable) must
|
|
'return upon themselves' in the sense that what recurs, though
|
|
specifically the same, is not the same numerically. That why, when
|
|
Water comes-to-be from Air and Air from Water, the Air is the same
|
|
'specifically', not 'numerically': and if these too recur
|
|
numerically the same, at any rate this does not happen with things
|
|
whose 'substance' comes-to-be-whose 'substance' is such that it is
|
|
essentially capable of not-being.
|
|
|
|
-THE END-
|
|
.
|