mirror of
https://github.com/opsxcq/mirror-textfiles.com.git
synced 2025-09-01 00:51:52 +02:00
1093 lines
56 KiB
Plaintext
1093 lines
56 KiB
Plaintext
350 BC
|
|
|
|
ON INTERPRETATION
|
|
|
|
by Aristotle
|
|
|
|
translated by E. M. Edghill
|
|
|
|
1
|
|
|
|
First we must define the terms 'noun' and 'verb', then the terms
|
|
'denial' and 'affirmation', then 'proposition' and 'sentence.'
|
|
|
|
Spoken words are the symbols of mental experience and written
|
|
words are the symbols of spoken words. Just as all men have not the
|
|
same writing, so all men have not the same speech sounds, but the
|
|
mental experiences, which these directly symbolize, are the same for
|
|
all, as also are those things of which our experiences are the images.
|
|
This matter has, however, been discussed in my treatise about the
|
|
soul, for it belongs to an investigation distinct from that which lies
|
|
before us.
|
|
|
|
As there are in the mind thoughts which do not involve truth or
|
|
falsity, and also those which must be either true or false, so it is
|
|
in speech. For truth and falsity imply combination and separation.
|
|
Nouns and verbs, provided nothing is added, are like thoughts
|
|
without combination or separation; 'man' and 'white', as isolated
|
|
terms, are not yet either true or false. In proof of this, consider
|
|
the word 'goat-stag.' It has significance, but there is no truth or
|
|
falsity about it, unless 'is' or 'is not' is added, either in the
|
|
present or in some other tense.
|
|
|
|
2
|
|
|
|
By a noun we mean a sound significant by convention, which has no
|
|
reference to time, and of which no part is significant apart from
|
|
the rest. In the noun 'Fairsteed,' the part 'steed' has no
|
|
significance in and by itself, as in the phrase 'fair steed.' Yet
|
|
there is a difference between simple and composite nouns; for in the
|
|
former the part is in no way significant, in the latter it contributes
|
|
to the meaning of the whole, although it has not an independent
|
|
meaning. Thus in the word 'pirate-boat' the word 'boat' has no meaning
|
|
except as part of the whole word.
|
|
|
|
The limitation 'by convention' was introduced because nothing is
|
|
by nature a noun or name-it is only so when it becomes a symbol;
|
|
inarticulate sounds, such as those which brutes produce, are
|
|
significant, yet none of these constitutes a noun.
|
|
|
|
The expression 'not-man' is not a noun. There is indeed no
|
|
recognized term by which we may denote such an expression, for it is
|
|
not a sentence or a denial. Let it then be called an indefinite noun.
|
|
|
|
The expressions 'of Philo', 'to Philo', and so on, constitute not
|
|
nouns, but cases of a noun. The definition of these cases of a noun is
|
|
in other respects the same as that of the noun proper, but, when
|
|
coupled with 'is', 'was', or will be', they do not, as they are,
|
|
form a proposition either true or false, and this the noun proper
|
|
always does, under these conditions. Take the words 'of Philo is' or
|
|
'of or 'of Philo is not'; these words do not, as they stand, form
|
|
either a true or a false proposition.
|
|
|
|
3
|
|
|
|
A verb is that which, in addition to its proper meaning, carries
|
|
with it the notion of time. No part of it has any independent meaning,
|
|
and it is a sign of something said of something else.
|
|
|
|
I will explain what I mean by saying that it carries with it the
|
|
notion of time. 'Health' is a noun, but 'is healthy' is a verb; for
|
|
besides its proper meaning it indicates the present existence of the
|
|
state in question.
|
|
|
|
Moreover, a verb is always a sign of something said of something
|
|
else, i.e. of something either predicable of or present in some
|
|
other thing.
|
|
|
|
Such expressions as 'is not-healthy', 'is not, ill', I do not
|
|
describe as verbs; for though they carry the additional note of
|
|
time, and always form a predicate, there is no specified name for this
|
|
variety; but let them be called indefinite verbs, since they apply
|
|
equally well to that which exists and to that which does not.
|
|
|
|
Similarly 'he was healthy', 'he will be healthy', are not verbs, but
|
|
tenses of a verb; the difference lies in the fact that the verb
|
|
indicates present time, while the tenses of the verb indicate those
|
|
times which lie outside the present.
|
|
|
|
Verbs in and by themselves are substantival and have significance,
|
|
for he who uses such expressions arrests the hearer's mind, and
|
|
fixes his attention; but they do not, as they stand, express any
|
|
judgement, either positive or negative. For neither are 'to be' and
|
|
'not to be' the participle 'being' significant of any fact, unless
|
|
something is added; for they do not themselves indicate anything,
|
|
but imply a copulation, of which we cannot form a conception apart
|
|
from the things coupled.
|
|
|
|
4
|
|
|
|
A sentence is a significant portion of speech, some parts of which
|
|
have an independent meaning, that is to say, as an utterance, though
|
|
not as the expression of any positive judgement. Let me explain. The
|
|
word 'human' has meaning, but does not constitute a proposition,
|
|
either positive or negative. It is only when other words are added
|
|
that the whole will form an affirmation or denial. But if we
|
|
separate one syllable of the word 'human' from the other, it has no
|
|
meaning; similarly in the word 'mouse', the part 'ouse' has no meaning
|
|
in itself, but is merely a sound. In composite words, indeed, the
|
|
parts contribute to the meaning of the whole; yet, as has been pointed
|
|
out, they have not an independent meaning.
|
|
|
|
Every sentence has meaning, not as being the natural means by
|
|
which a physical faculty is realized, but, as we have said, by
|
|
convention. Yet every sentence is not a proposition; only such are
|
|
propositions as have in them either truth or falsity. Thus a prayer is
|
|
a sentence, but is neither true nor false.
|
|
|
|
Let us therefore dismiss all other types of sentence but the
|
|
proposition, for this last concerns our present inquiry, whereas the
|
|
investigation of the others belongs rather to the study of rhetoric or
|
|
of poetry.
|
|
|
|
5
|
|
|
|
The first class of simple propositions is the simple affirmation,
|
|
the next, the simple denial; all others are only one by conjunction.
|
|
|
|
Every proposition must contain a verb or the tense of a verb. The
|
|
phrase which defines the species 'man', if no verb in present, past,
|
|
or future time be added, is not a proposition. It may be asked how the
|
|
expression 'a footed animal with two feet' can be called single; for
|
|
it is not the circumstance that the words follow in unbroken
|
|
succession that effects the unity. This inquiry, however, finds its
|
|
place in an investigation foreign to that before us.
|
|
|
|
We call those propositions single which indicate a single fact, or
|
|
the conjunction of the parts of which results in unity: those
|
|
propositions, on the other hand, are separate and many in number,
|
|
which indicate many facts, or whose parts have no conjunction.
|
|
|
|
Let us, moreover, consent to call a noun or a verb an expression
|
|
only, and not a proposition, since it is not possible for a man to
|
|
speak in this way when he is expressing something, in such a way as to
|
|
make a statement, whether his utterance is an answer to a question
|
|
or an act of his own initiation.
|
|
|
|
To return: of propositions one kind is simple, i.e. that which
|
|
asserts or denies something of something, the other composite, i.e.
|
|
that which is compounded of simple propositions. A simple
|
|
proposition is a statement, with meaning, as to the presence of
|
|
something in a subject or its absence, in the present, past, or
|
|
future, according to the divisions of time.
|
|
|
|
6
|
|
|
|
An affirmation is a positive assertion of something about something,
|
|
a denial a negative assertion.
|
|
|
|
Now it is possible both to affirm and to deny the presence of
|
|
something which is present or of something which is not, and since
|
|
these same affirmations and denials are possible with reference to
|
|
those times which lie outside the present, it would be possible to
|
|
contradict any affirmation or denial. Thus it is plain that every
|
|
affirmation has an opposite denial, and similarly every denial an
|
|
opposite affirmation.
|
|
|
|
We will call such a pair of propositions a pair of
|
|
contradictories. Those positive and negative propositions are said
|
|
to be contradictory which have the same subject and predicate. The
|
|
identity of subject and of predicate must not be 'equivocal'. Indeed
|
|
there are definitive qualifications besides this, which we make to
|
|
meet the casuistries of sophists.
|
|
|
|
7
|
|
|
|
Some things are universal, others individual. By the term
|
|
'universal' I mean that which is of such a nature as to be
|
|
predicated of many subjects, by 'individual' that which is not thus
|
|
predicated. Thus 'man' is a universal, 'Callias' an individual.
|
|
|
|
Our propositions necessarily sometimes concern a universal
|
|
subject, sometimes an individual.
|
|
|
|
If, then, a man states a positive and a negative proposition of
|
|
universal character with regard to a universal, these two propositions
|
|
are 'contrary'. By the expression 'a proposition of universal
|
|
character with regard to a universal', such propositions as 'every man
|
|
is white', 'no man is white' are meant. When, on the other hand, the
|
|
positive and negative propositions, though they have regard to a
|
|
universal, are yet not of universal character, they will not be
|
|
contrary, albeit the meaning intended is sometimes contrary. As
|
|
instances of propositions made with regard to a universal, but not
|
|
of universal character, we may take the 'propositions 'man is
|
|
white', 'man is not white'. 'Man' is a universal, but the
|
|
proposition is not made as of universal character; for the word
|
|
'every' does not make the subject a universal, but rather gives the
|
|
proposition a universal character. If, however, both predicate and
|
|
subject are distributed, the proposition thus constituted is
|
|
contrary to truth; no affirmation will, under such circumstances, be
|
|
true. The proposition 'every man is every animal' is an example of
|
|
this type.
|
|
|
|
An affirmation is opposed to a denial in the sense which I denote by
|
|
the term 'contradictory', when, while the subject remains the same,
|
|
the affirmation is of universal character and the denial is not. The
|
|
affirmation 'every man is white' is the contradictory of the denial
|
|
'not every man is white', or again, the proposition 'no man is
|
|
white' is the contradictory of the proposition 'some men are white'.
|
|
But propositions are opposed as contraries when both the affirmation
|
|
and the denial are universal, as in the sentences 'every man is
|
|
white', 'no man is white', 'every man is just', 'no man is just'.
|
|
|
|
We see that in a pair of this sort both propositions cannot be true,
|
|
but the contradictories of a pair of contraries can sometimes both
|
|
be true with reference to the same subject; for instance 'not every
|
|
man is white' and some men are white' are both true. Of such
|
|
corresponding positive and negative propositions as refer to
|
|
universals and have a universal character, one must be true and the
|
|
other false. This is the case also when the reference is to
|
|
individuals, as in the propositions 'Socrates is white', 'Socrates
|
|
is not white'.
|
|
|
|
When, on the other hand, the reference is to universals, but the
|
|
propositions are not universal, it is not always the case that one
|
|
is true and the other false, for it is possible to state truly that
|
|
man is white and that man is not white and that man is beautiful and
|
|
that man is not beautiful; for if a man is deformed he is the
|
|
reverse of beautiful, also if he is progressing towards beauty he is
|
|
not yet beautiful.
|
|
|
|
This statement might seem at first sight to carry with it a
|
|
contradiction, owing to the fact that the proposition 'man is not
|
|
white' appears to be equivalent to the proposition 'no man is
|
|
white'. This, however, is not the case, nor are they necessarily at
|
|
the same time true or false.
|
|
|
|
It is evident also that the denial corresponding to a single
|
|
affirmation is itself single; for the denial must deny just that which
|
|
the affirmation affirms concerning the same subject, and must
|
|
correspond with the affirmation both in the universal or particular
|
|
character of the subject and in the distributed or undistributed sense
|
|
in which it is understood.
|
|
|
|
For instance, the affirmation 'Socrates is white' has its proper
|
|
denial in the proposition 'Socrates is not white'. If anything else be
|
|
negatively predicated of the subject or if anything else be the
|
|
subject though the predicate remain the same, the denial will not be
|
|
the denial proper to that affirmation, but on that is distinct.
|
|
|
|
The denial proper to the affirmation 'every man is white' is 'not
|
|
every man is white'; that proper to the affirmation 'some men are
|
|
white' is 'no man is white', while that proper to the affirmation 'man
|
|
is white' is 'man is not white'.
|
|
|
|
We have shown further that a single denial is contradictorily
|
|
opposite to a single affirmation and we have explained which these
|
|
are; we have also stated that contrary are distinct from contradictory
|
|
propositions and which the contrary are; also that with regard to a
|
|
pair of opposite propositions it is not always the case that one is
|
|
true and the other false. We have pointed out, moreover, what the
|
|
reason of this is and under what circumstances the truth of the one
|
|
involves the falsity of the other.
|
|
|
|
8
|
|
|
|
An affirmation or denial is single, if it indicates some one fact
|
|
about some one subject; it matters not whether the subject is
|
|
universal and whether the statement has a universal character, or
|
|
whether this is not so. Such single propositions are: 'every man is
|
|
white', 'not every man is white';'man is white','man is not white';
|
|
'no man is white', 'some men are white'; provided the word 'white' has
|
|
one meaning. If, on the other hand, one word has two meanings which do
|
|
not combine to form one, the affirmation is not single. For
|
|
instance, if a man should establish the symbol 'garment' as
|
|
significant both of a horse and of a man, the proposition 'garment
|
|
is white' would not be a single affirmation, nor its opposite a single
|
|
denial. For it is equivalent to the proposition 'horse and man are
|
|
white', which, again, is equivalent to the two propositions 'horse
|
|
is white', 'man is white'. If, then, these two propositions have
|
|
more than a single significance, and do not form a single proposition,
|
|
it is plain that the first proposition either has more than one
|
|
significance or else has none; for a particular man is not a horse.
|
|
|
|
This, then, is another instance of those propositions of which
|
|
both the positive and the negative forms may be true or false
|
|
simultaneously.
|
|
|
|
9
|
|
|
|
In the case of that which is or which has taken place, propositions,
|
|
whether positive or negative, must be true or false. Again, in the
|
|
case of a pair of contradictories, either when the subject is
|
|
universal and the propositions are of a universal character, or when
|
|
it is individual, as has been said,' one of the two must be true and
|
|
the other false; whereas when the subject is universal, but the
|
|
propositions are not of a universal character, there is no such
|
|
necessity. We have discussed this type also in a previous chapter.
|
|
|
|
When the subject, however, is individual, and that which is
|
|
predicated of it relates to the future, the case is altered. For if
|
|
all propositions whether positive or negative are either true or
|
|
false, then any given predicate must either belong to the subject or
|
|
not, so that if one man affirms that an event of a given character
|
|
will take place and another denies it, it is plain that the
|
|
statement of the one will correspond with reality and that of the
|
|
other will not. For the predicate cannot both belong and not belong to
|
|
the subject at one and the same time with regard to the future.
|
|
|
|
Thus, if it is true to say that a thing is white, it must
|
|
necessarily be white; if the reverse proposition is true, it will of
|
|
necessity not be white. Again, if it is white, the proposition stating
|
|
that it is white was true; if it is not white, the proposition to
|
|
the opposite effect was true. And if it is not white, the man who
|
|
states that it is making a false statement; and if the man who
|
|
states that it is white is making a false statement, it follows that
|
|
it is not white. It may therefore be argued that it is necessary
|
|
that affirmations or denials must be either true or false.
|
|
|
|
Now if this be so, nothing is or takes place fortuitously, either in
|
|
the present or in the future, and there are no real alternatives;
|
|
everything takes place of necessity and is fixed. For either he that
|
|
affirms that it will take place or he that denies this is in
|
|
correspondence with fact, whereas if things did not take place of
|
|
necessity, an event might just as easily not happen as happen; for the
|
|
meaning of the word 'fortuitous' with regard to present or future
|
|
events is that reality is so constituted that it may issue in either
|
|
of two opposite directions. Again, if a thing is white now, it was
|
|
true before to say that it would be white, so that of anything that
|
|
has taken place it was always true to say 'it is' or 'it will be'. But
|
|
if it was always true to say that a thing is or will be, it is not
|
|
possible that it should not be or not be about to be, and when a thing
|
|
cannot not come to be, it is impossible that it should not come to be,
|
|
and when it is impossible that it should not come to be, it must
|
|
come to be. All, then, that is about to be must of necessity take
|
|
place. It results from this that nothing is uncertain or fortuitous,
|
|
for if it were fortuitous it would not be necessary.
|
|
|
|
Again, to say that neither the affirmation nor the denial is true,
|
|
maintaining, let us say, that an event neither will take place nor
|
|
will not take place, is to take up a position impossible to defend. In
|
|
the first place, though facts should prove the one proposition
|
|
false, the opposite would still be untrue. Secondly, if it was true to
|
|
say that a thing was both white and large, both these qualities must
|
|
necessarily belong to it; and if they will belong to it the next
|
|
day, they must necessarily belong to it the next day. But if an
|
|
event is neither to take place nor not to take place the next day, the
|
|
element of chance will be eliminated. For example, it would be
|
|
necessary that a sea-fight should neither take place nor fail to
|
|
take place on the next day.
|
|
|
|
These awkward results and others of the same kind follow, if it is
|
|
an irrefragable law that of every pair of contradictory
|
|
propositions, whether they have regard to universals and are stated as
|
|
universally applicable, or whether they have regard to individuals,
|
|
one must be true and the other false, and that there are no real
|
|
alternatives, but that all that is or takes place is the outcome of
|
|
necessity. There would be no need to deliberate or to take trouble, on
|
|
the supposition that if we should adopt a certain course, a certain
|
|
result would follow, while, if we did not, the result would not
|
|
follow. For a man may predict an event ten thousand years
|
|
beforehand, and another may predict the reverse; that which was
|
|
truly predicted at the moment in the past will of necessity take place
|
|
in the fullness of time.
|
|
|
|
Further, it makes no difference whether people have or have not
|
|
actually made the contradictory statements. For it is manifest that
|
|
the circumstances are not influenced by the fact of an affirmation
|
|
or denial on the part of anyone. For events will not take place or
|
|
fail to take place because it was stated that they would or would
|
|
not take place, nor is this any more the case if the prediction
|
|
dates back ten thousand years or any other space of time. Wherefore,
|
|
if through all time the nature of things was so constituted that a
|
|
prediction about an event was true, then through all time it was
|
|
necessary that that should find fulfillment; and with regard to all
|
|
events, circumstances have always been such that their occurrence is a
|
|
matter of necessity. For that of which someone has said truly that
|
|
it will be, cannot fail to take place; and of that which takes
|
|
place, it was always true to say that it would be.
|
|
|
|
Yet this view leads to an impossible conclusion; for we see that
|
|
both deliberation and action are causative with regard to the
|
|
future, and that, to speak more generally, in those things which are
|
|
not continuously actual there is potentiality in either direction.
|
|
Such things may either be or not be; events also therefore may
|
|
either take place or not take place. There are many obvious
|
|
instances of this. It is possible that this coat may be cut in half,
|
|
and yet it may not be cut in half, but wear out first. In the same
|
|
way, it is possible that it should not be cut in half; unless this
|
|
were so, it would not be possible that it should wear out first. So it
|
|
is therefore with all other events which possess this kind of
|
|
potentiality. It is therefore plain that it is not of necessity that
|
|
everything is or takes place; but in some instances there are real
|
|
alternatives, in which case the affirmation is no more true and no
|
|
more false than the denial; while some exhibit a predisposition and
|
|
general tendency in one direction or the other, and yet can issue in
|
|
the opposite direction by exception.
|
|
|
|
Now that which is must needs be when it is, and that which is not
|
|
must needs not be when it is not. Yet it cannot be said without
|
|
qualification that all existence and non-existence is the outcome of
|
|
necessity. For there is a difference between saying that that which
|
|
is, when it is, must needs be, and simply saying that all that is must
|
|
needs be, and similarly in the case of that which is not. In the case,
|
|
also, of two contradictory propositions this holds good. Everything
|
|
must either be or not be, whether in the present or in the future, but
|
|
it is not always possible to distinguish and state determinately which
|
|
of these alternatives must necessarily come about.
|
|
|
|
Let me illustrate. A sea-fight must either take place to-morrow or
|
|
not, but it is not necessary that it should take place to-morrow,
|
|
neither is it necessary that it should not take place, yet it is
|
|
necessary that it either should or should not take place to-morrow.
|
|
Since propositions correspond with facts, it is evident that when in
|
|
future events there is a real alternative, and a potentiality in
|
|
contrary directions, the corresponding affirmation and denial have the
|
|
same character.
|
|
|
|
This is the case with regard to that which is not always existent or
|
|
not always nonexistent. One of the two propositions in such
|
|
instances must be true and the other false, but we cannot say
|
|
determinately that this or that is false, but must leave the
|
|
alternative undecided. One may indeed be more likely to be true than
|
|
the other, but it cannot be either actually true or actually false. It
|
|
is therefore plain that it is not necessary that of an affirmation and
|
|
a denial one should be true and the other false. For in the case of
|
|
that which exists potentially, but not actually, the rule which
|
|
applies to that which exists actually does not hold good. The case
|
|
is rather as we have indicated.
|
|
|
|
10
|
|
|
|
An affirmation is the statement of a fact with regard to a
|
|
subject, and this subject is either a noun or that which has no
|
|
name; the subject and predicate in an affirmation must each denote a
|
|
single thing. I have already explained' what is meant by a noun and by
|
|
that which has no name; for I stated that the expression 'not-man' was
|
|
not a noun, in the proper sense of the word, but an indefinite noun,
|
|
denoting as it does in a certain sense a single thing. Similarly the
|
|
expression 'does not enjoy health' is not a verb proper, but an
|
|
indefinite verb. Every affirmation, then, and every denial, will
|
|
consist of a noun and a verb, either definite or indefinite.
|
|
|
|
There can be no affirmation or denial without a verb; for the
|
|
expressions 'is', 'will be', 'was', 'is coming to be', and the like
|
|
are verbs according to our definition, since besides their specific
|
|
meaning they convey the notion of time. Thus the primary affirmation
|
|
and denial are 'as follows: 'man is', 'man is not'. Next to these,
|
|
there are the propositions: 'not-man is', 'not-man is not'. Again we
|
|
have the propositions: 'every man is, 'every man is not', 'all that is
|
|
not-man is', 'all that is not-man is not'. The same classification
|
|
holds good with regard to such periods of time as lie outside the
|
|
present.
|
|
|
|
When the verb 'is' is used as a third element in the sentence, there
|
|
can be positive and negative propositions of two sorts. Thus in the
|
|
sentence 'man is just' the verb 'is' is used as a third element,
|
|
call it verb or noun, which you will. Four propositions, therefore,
|
|
instead of two can be formed with these materials. Two of the four, as
|
|
regards their affirmation and denial, correspond in their logical
|
|
sequence with the propositions which deal with a condition of
|
|
privation; the other two do not correspond with these.
|
|
|
|
I mean that the verb 'is' is added either to the term 'just' or to
|
|
the term 'not-just', and two negative propositions are formed in the
|
|
same way. Thus we have the four propositions. Reference to the
|
|
subjoined table will make matters clear:
|
|
|
|
A. Affirmation B. Denial
|
|
|
|
Man is just Man is not just
|
|
|
|
\ /
|
|
|
|
X
|
|
|
|
/ \
|
|
|
|
D. Denial C. Affirmation
|
|
|
|
Man is not not-just Man is not-just
|
|
|
|
Here 'is' and 'is not' are added either to 'just' or to 'not-just'.
|
|
This then is the proper scheme for these propositions, as has been
|
|
said in the Analytics. The same rule holds good, if the subject is
|
|
distributed. Thus we have the table:
|
|
|
|
A'. Affirmation B'. Denial
|
|
|
|
Every man is just Not every man is just
|
|
|
|
\ /
|
|
|
|
X
|
|
|
|
D'. Denial / \ C'. Affirmation
|
|
|
|
Not every man is not-just Every man is not-just
|
|
Yet here it is not possible, in the same way as in the former case,
|
|
that the propositions joined in the table by a diagonal line should
|
|
both be true; though under certain circumstances this is the case.
|
|
|
|
We have thus set out two pairs of opposite propositions; there are
|
|
moreover two other pairs, if a term be conjoined with 'not-man', the
|
|
latter forming a kind of subject. Thus:
|
|
|
|
A." B."
|
|
|
|
Not-man is just Not-man is not just
|
|
|
|
\ /
|
|
- X
|
|
|
|
D." / \ C."
|
|
|
|
Not-man is not not-just Not-man is not-just
|
|
|
|
This is an exhaustive enumeration of all the pairs of opposite
|
|
propositions that can possibly be framed. This last group should
|
|
remain distinct from those which preceded it, since it employs as
|
|
its subject the expression 'not-man'.
|
|
|
|
When the verb 'is' does not fit the structure of the sentence (for
|
|
instance, when the verbs 'walks', 'enjoys health' are used), that
|
|
scheme applies, which applied when the word 'is' was added.
|
|
|
|
Thus we have the propositions: 'every man enjoys health', 'every man
|
|
does-not-enjoy-health', 'all that is not-man enjoys health', 'all that
|
|
is not-man does-not-enjoy-health'. We must not in these propositions
|
|
use the expression 'not every man'. The negative must be attached to
|
|
the word 'man', for the word 'every' does not give to the subject a
|
|
universal significance, but implies that, as a subject, it is
|
|
distributed. This is plain from the following pairs: 'man enjoys
|
|
health', 'man does not enjoy health'; 'not-man enjoys health', 'not
|
|
man does not enjoy health'. These propositions differ from the
|
|
former in being indefinite and not universal in character. Thus the
|
|
adjectives 'every' and no additional significance except that the
|
|
subject, whether in a positive or in a negative sentence, is
|
|
distributed. The rest of the sentence, therefore, will in each case be
|
|
the same.
|
|
|
|
Since the contrary of the proposition 'every animal is just' is
|
|
'no animal is just', it is plain that these two propositions will
|
|
never both be true at the same time or with reference to the same
|
|
subject. Sometimes, however, the contradictories of these contraries
|
|
will both be true, as in the instance before us: the propositions 'not
|
|
every animal is just' and 'some animals are just' are both true.
|
|
|
|
Further, the proposition 'no man is just' follows from the
|
|
proposition 'every man is not just' and the proposition 'not every man
|
|
is not just', which is the opposite of 'every man is not-just',
|
|
follows from the proposition 'some men are just'; for if this be true,
|
|
there must be some just men.
|
|
|
|
It is evident, also, that when the subject is individual, if a
|
|
question is asked and the negative answer is the true one, a certain
|
|
positive proposition is also true. Thus, if the question were asked
|
|
Socrates wise?' and the negative answer were the true one, the
|
|
positive inference 'Then Socrates is unwise' is correct. But no such
|
|
inference is correct in the case of universals, but rather a
|
|
negative proposition. For instance, if to the question 'Is every man
|
|
wise?' the answer is 'no', the inference 'Then every man is unwise' is
|
|
false. But under these circumstances the inference 'Not every man is
|
|
wise' is correct. This last is the contradictory, the former the
|
|
contrary. Negative expressions, which consist of an indefinite noun or
|
|
predicate, such as 'not-man' or 'not-just', may seem to be denials
|
|
containing neither noun nor verb in the proper sense of the words. But
|
|
they are not. For a denial must always be either true or false, and he
|
|
that uses the expression 'not man', if nothing more be added, is not
|
|
nearer but rather further from making a true or a false statement than
|
|
he who uses the expression 'man'.
|
|
|
|
The propositions 'everything that is not man is just', and the
|
|
contradictory of this, are not equivalent to any of the other
|
|
propositions; on the other hand, the proposition 'everything that is
|
|
not man is not just' is equivalent to the proposition 'nothing that is
|
|
not man is just'.
|
|
|
|
The conversion of the position of subject and predicate in a
|
|
sentence involves no difference in its meaning. Thus we say 'man is
|
|
white' and 'white is man'. If these were not equivalent, there would
|
|
be more than one contradictory to the same proposition, whereas it has
|
|
been demonstrated' that each proposition has one proper
|
|
contradictory and one only. For of the proposition 'man is white'
|
|
the appropriate contradictory is 'man is not white', and of the
|
|
proposition 'white is man', if its meaning be different, the
|
|
contradictory will either be 'white is not not-man' or 'white is not
|
|
man'. Now the former of these is the contradictory of the
|
|
proposition 'white is not-man', and the latter of these is the
|
|
contradictory of the proposition 'man is white'; thus there will be
|
|
two contradictories to one proposition.
|
|
|
|
It is evident, therefore, that the inversion of the relative
|
|
position of subject and predicate does not affect the sense of
|
|
affirmations and denials.
|
|
|
|
11
|
|
|
|
There is no unity about an affirmation or denial which, either
|
|
positively or negatively, predicates one thing of many subjects, or
|
|
many things of the same subject, unless that which is indicated by the
|
|
many is really some one thing. do not apply this word 'one' to those
|
|
things which, though they have a single recognized name, yet do not
|
|
combine to form a unity. Thus, man may be an animal, and biped, and
|
|
domesticated, but these three predicates combine to form a unity. On
|
|
the other hand, the predicates 'white', 'man', and 'walking' do not
|
|
thus combine. Neither, therefore, if these three form the subject of
|
|
an affirmation, nor if they form its predicate, is there any unity
|
|
about that affirmation. In both cases the unity is linguistic, but not
|
|
real.
|
|
|
|
If therefore the dialectical question is a request for an answer,
|
|
i.e. either for the admission of a premiss or for the admission of one
|
|
of two contradictories-and the premiss is itself always one of two
|
|
contradictories-the answer to such a question as contains the above
|
|
predicates cannot be a single proposition. For as I have explained
|
|
in the Topics, question is not a single one, even if the answer
|
|
asked for is true.
|
|
|
|
At the same time it is plain that a question of the form 'what is
|
|
it?' is not a dialectical question, for a dialectical questioner
|
|
must by the form of his question give his opponent the chance of
|
|
announcing one of two alternatives, whichever he wishes. He must
|
|
therefore put the question into a more definite form, and inquire,
|
|
e.g.. whether man has such and such a characteristic or not.
|
|
|
|
Some combinations of predicates are such that the separate
|
|
predicates unite to form a single predicate. Let us consider under
|
|
what conditions this is and is not possible. We may either state in
|
|
two separate propositions that man is an animal and that man is a
|
|
biped, or we may combine the two, and state that man is an animal with
|
|
two feet. Similarly we may use 'man' and 'white' as separate
|
|
predicates, or unite them into one. Yet if a man is a shoemaker and is
|
|
also good, we cannot construct a composite proposition and say that he
|
|
is a good shoemaker. For if, whenever two separate predicates truly
|
|
belong to a subject, it follows that the predicate resulting from
|
|
their combination also truly belongs to the subject, many absurd
|
|
results ensue. For instance, a man is man and white. Therefore, if
|
|
predicates may always be combined, he is a white man. Again, if the
|
|
predicate 'white' belongs to him, then the combination of that
|
|
predicate with the former composite predicate will be permissible.
|
|
Thus it will be right to say that he is a white man so on
|
|
indefinitely. Or, again, we may combine the predicates 'musical',
|
|
'white', and 'walking', and these may be combined many times.
|
|
Similarly we may say that Socrates is Socrates and a man, and that
|
|
therefore he is the man Socrates, or that Socrates is a man and a
|
|
biped, and that therefore he is a two-footed man. Thus it is
|
|
manifest that if man states unconditionally that predicates can always
|
|
be combined, many absurd consequences ensue.
|
|
|
|
We will now explain what ought to be laid down.
|
|
|
|
Those predicates, and terms forming the subject of predication,
|
|
which are accidental either to the same subject or to one another,
|
|
do not combine to form a unity. Take the proposition 'man is white
|
|
of complexion and musical'. Whiteness and being musical do not
|
|
coalesce to form a unity, for they belong only accidentally to the
|
|
same subject. Nor yet, if it were true to say that that which is white
|
|
is musical, would the terms 'musical' and 'white' form a unity, for it
|
|
is only incidentally that that which is musical is white; the
|
|
combination of the two will, therefore, not form a unity.
|
|
|
|
Thus, again, whereas, if a man is both good and a shoemaker, we
|
|
cannot combine the two propositions and say simply that he is a good
|
|
shoemaker, we are, at the same time, able to combine the predicates
|
|
'animal' and 'biped' and say that a man is an animal with two feet,
|
|
for these predicates are not accidental.
|
|
|
|
Those predicates, again, cannot form a unity, of which the one is
|
|
implicit in the other: thus we cannot combine the predicate 'white'
|
|
again and again with that which already contains the notion 'white',
|
|
nor is it right to call a man an animal-man or a two-footed man; for
|
|
the notions 'animal' and 'biped' are implicit in the word 'man'. On
|
|
the other hand, it is possible to predicate a term simply of any one
|
|
instance, and to say that some one particular man is a man or that
|
|
some one white man is a white man.
|
|
|
|
Yet this is not always possible: indeed, when in the adjunct there
|
|
is some opposite which involves a contradiction, the predication of
|
|
the simple term is impossible. Thus it is not right to call a dead man
|
|
a man. When, however, this is not the case, it is not impossible.
|
|
|
|
Yet the facts of the case might rather be stated thus: when some
|
|
such opposite elements are present, resolution is never possible,
|
|
but when they are not present, resolution is nevertheless not always
|
|
possible. Take the proposition 'Homer is so-and-so', say 'a poet';
|
|
does it follow that Homer is, or does it not? The verb 'is' is here
|
|
used of Homer only incidentally, the proposition being that Homer is a
|
|
poet, not that he is, in the independent sense of the word.
|
|
|
|
Thus, in the case of those predications which have within them no
|
|
contradiction when the nouns are expanded into definitions, and
|
|
wherein the predicates belong to the subject in their own proper sense
|
|
and not in any indirect way, the individual may be the subject of
|
|
the simple propositions as well as of the composite. But in the case
|
|
of that which is not, it is not true to say that because it is the
|
|
object of opinion, it is; for the opinion held about it is that it
|
|
is not, not that it is.
|
|
|
|
12
|
|
|
|
As these distinctions have been made, we must consider the mutual
|
|
relation of those affirmations and denials which assert or deny
|
|
possibility or contingency, impossibility or necessity: for the
|
|
subject is not without difficulty.
|
|
|
|
We admit that of composite expressions those are contradictory
|
|
each to each which have the verb 'to be' its positive and negative
|
|
form respectively. Thus the contradictory of the proposition 'man
|
|
is' is 'man is not', not 'not-man is', and the contradictory of 'man
|
|
is white' is 'man is not white', not 'man is not-white'. For
|
|
otherwise, since either the positive or the negative proposition is
|
|
true of any subject, it will turn out true to say that a piece of wood
|
|
is a man that is not white.
|
|
|
|
Now if this is the case, in those propositions which do not
|
|
contain the verb 'to be' the verb which takes its place will
|
|
exercise the same function. Thus the contradictory of 'man walks' is
|
|
'man does not walk', not 'not-man walks'; for to say 'man walks'
|
|
merely equivalent to saying 'man is walking'.
|
|
|
|
If then this rule is universal, the contradictory of 'it may be'
|
|
is may not be', not 'it cannot be'.
|
|
|
|
Now it appears that the same thing both may and may not be; for
|
|
instance, everything that may be cut or may walk may also escape
|
|
cutting and refrain from walking; and the reason is that those
|
|
things that have potentiality in this sense are not always actual.
|
|
In such cases, both the positive and the negative propositions will be
|
|
true; for that which is capable of walking or of being seen has also a
|
|
potentiality in the opposite direction.
|
|
|
|
But since it is impossible that contradictory propositions should
|
|
both be true of the same subject, it follows that' it may not be' is
|
|
not the contradictory of 'it may be'. For it is a logical
|
|
consequence of what we have said, either that the same predicate can
|
|
be both applicable and inapplicable to one and the same subject at the
|
|
same time, or that it is not by the addition of the verbs 'be' and
|
|
'not be', respectively, that positive and negative propositions are
|
|
formed. If the former of these alternatives must be rejected, we
|
|
must choose the latter.
|
|
|
|
The contradictory, then, of 'it may be' is 'it cannot be'. The
|
|
same rule applies to the proposition 'it is contingent that it
|
|
should be'; the contradictory of this is 'it is not contingent that it
|
|
should be'. The similar propositions, such as 'it is necessary' and
|
|
'it is impossible', may be dealt with in the same manner. For it comes
|
|
about that just as in the former instances the verbs 'is' and 'is not'
|
|
were added to the subject-matter of the sentence 'white' and 'man', so
|
|
here 'that it should be' and 'that it should not be' are the
|
|
subject-matter and 'is possible', 'is contingent', are added. These
|
|
indicate that a certain thing is or is not possible, just as in the
|
|
former instances 'is' and 'is not' indicated that certain things
|
|
were or were not the case.
|
|
|
|
The contradictory, then, of 'it may not be' is not 'it cannot be',
|
|
but 'it cannot not be', and the contradictory of 'it may be' is not
|
|
'it may not be', but cannot be'. Thus the propositions 'it may be' and
|
|
'it may not be' appear each to imply the other: for, since these two
|
|
propositions are not contradictory, the same thing both may and may
|
|
not be. But the propositions 'it may be' and 'it cannot be' can
|
|
never be true of the same subject at the same time, for they are
|
|
contradictory. Nor can the propositions 'it may not be' and 'it cannot
|
|
not be' be at once true of the same subject.
|
|
|
|
The propositions which have to do with necessity are governed by the
|
|
same principle. The contradictory of 'it is necessary that it should
|
|
be', is not 'it is necessary that it should not be,' but 'it is not
|
|
necessary that it should be', and the contradictory of 'it is
|
|
necessary that it should not be' is 'it is not necessary that it
|
|
should not be'.
|
|
|
|
Again, the contradictory of 'it is impossible that it should be'
|
|
is not 'it is impossible that it should not be' but 'it is not
|
|
impossible that it should be', and the contradictory of 'it is
|
|
impossible that it should not be' is 'it is not impossible that it
|
|
should not be'.
|
|
|
|
To generalize, we must, as has been stated, define the clauses 'that
|
|
it should be' and 'that it should not be' as the subject-matter of the
|
|
propositions, and in making these terms into affirmations and
|
|
denials we must combine them with 'that it should be' and 'that it
|
|
should not be' respectively.
|
|
|
|
We must consider the following pairs as contradictory propositions:
|
|
|
|
It may be. It cannot be.
|
|
|
|
It is contingent. It is not contingent.
|
|
|
|
It is impossible. It is not impossible.
|
|
|
|
It is necessary. It is not necessary.
|
|
|
|
It is true. It is not true.
|
|
|
|
13
|
|
|
|
Logical sequences follow in due course when we have arranged the
|
|
propositions thus. From the proposition 'it may be' it follows that it
|
|
is contingent, and the relation is reciprocal. It follows also that it
|
|
is not impossible and not necessary.
|
|
|
|
From the proposition 'it may not be' or 'it is contingent that
|
|
it should not be' it follows that it is not necessary that it should
|
|
not be and that it is not impossible that it should not be. From the
|
|
proposition 'it cannot be' or 'it is not contingent' it follows that
|
|
it is necessary that it should not be and that it is impossible that
|
|
it should be. From the proposition 'it cannot not be' or 'it is not
|
|
contingent that it should not be' it follows that it is necessary that
|
|
it should be and that it is impossible that it should not be.
|
|
|
|
Let us consider these statements by the help of a table:
|
|
|
|
A. B.
|
|
|
|
It may be. It cannot be.
|
|
|
|
It is contingent. It is not contingent.
|
|
|
|
It is not impossible It is impossible that it
|
|
|
|
that it should be. should be.
|
|
|
|
It is not necessary It is necessary that it
|
|
|
|
that it should be. should not be.
|
|
|
|
C. D.
|
|
|
|
It may not be. It cannot not be.
|
|
|
|
It is contingent that it It is not contingent that
|
|
|
|
should not be. it should not be.
|
|
|
|
It is not impossible It is impossible thatit
|
|
|
|
that it should not be. should not be.
|
|
|
|
It is not necessary that It is necessary that it
|
|
|
|
it should not be. should be.
|
|
|
|
Now the propositions 'it is impossible that it should be' and 'it is
|
|
not impossible that it should be' are consequent upon the propositions
|
|
'it may be', 'it is contingent', and 'it cannot be', 'it is not
|
|
contingent', the contradictories upon the contradictories. But there
|
|
is inversion. The negative of the proposition 'it is impossible' is
|
|
consequent upon the proposition 'it may be' and the corresponding
|
|
positive in the first case upon the negative in the second. For 'it is
|
|
impossible' is a positive proposition and 'it is not impossible' is
|
|
negative.
|
|
|
|
We must investigate the relation subsisting between these
|
|
propositions and those which predicate necessity. That there is a
|
|
distinction is clear. In this case, contrary propositions follow
|
|
respectively from contradictory propositions, and the contradictory
|
|
propositions belong to separate sequences. For the proposition 'it
|
|
is not necessary that it should be' is not the negative of 'it is
|
|
necessary that it should not be', for both these propositions may be
|
|
true of the same subject; for when it is necessary that a thing should
|
|
not be, it is not necessary that it should be. The reason why the
|
|
propositions predicating necessity do not follow in the same kind of
|
|
sequence as the rest, lies in the fact that the proposition 'it is
|
|
impossible' is equivalent, when used with a contrary subject, to the
|
|
proposition 'it is necessary'. For when it is impossible that a
|
|
thing should be, it is necessary, not that it should be, but that it
|
|
should not be, and when it is impossible that a thing should not be,
|
|
it is necessary that it should be. Thus, if the propositions
|
|
predicating impossibility or non-impossibility follow without change
|
|
of subject from those predicating possibility or non-possibility,
|
|
those predicating necessity must follow with the contrary subject; for
|
|
the propositions 'it is impossible' and 'it is necessary' are not
|
|
equivalent, but, as has been said, inversely connected.
|
|
|
|
Yet perhaps it is impossible that the contradictory propositions
|
|
predicating necessity should be thus arranged. For when it is
|
|
necessary that a thing should be, it is possible that it should be.
|
|
(For if not, the opposite follows, since one or the other must follow;
|
|
so, if it is not possible, it is impossible, and it is thus impossible
|
|
that a thing should be, which must necessarily be; which is absurd.)
|
|
|
|
Yet from the proposition 'it may be' it follows that it is not
|
|
impossible, and from that it follows that it is not necessary; it
|
|
comes about therefore that the thing which must necessarily be need
|
|
not be; which is absurd. But again, the proposition 'it is necessary
|
|
that it should be' does not follow from the proposition 'it may be',
|
|
nor does the proposition 'it is necessary that it should not be'.
|
|
For the proposition 'it may be' implies a twofold possibility,
|
|
while, if either of the two former propositions is true, the twofold
|
|
possibility vanishes. For if a thing may be, it may also not be, but
|
|
if it is necessary that it should be or that it should not be, one
|
|
of the two alternatives will be excluded. It remains, therefore,
|
|
that the proposition 'it is not necessary that it should not be'
|
|
follows from the proposition 'it may be'. For this is true also of
|
|
that which must necessarily be.
|
|
|
|
Moreover the proposition 'it is not necessary that it should not be'
|
|
is the contradictory of that which follows from the proposition 'it
|
|
cannot be'; for 'it cannot be' is followed by 'it is impossible that
|
|
it should be' and by 'it is necessary that it should not be', and
|
|
the contradictory of this is the proposition 'it is not necessary that
|
|
it should not be'. Thus in this case also contradictory propositions
|
|
follow contradictory in the way indicated, and no logical
|
|
impossibilities occur when they are thus arranged.
|
|
|
|
It may be questioned whether the proposition 'it may be' follows
|
|
from the proposition 'it is necessary that it should be'. If not,
|
|
the contradictory must follow, namely that it cannot be, or, if a
|
|
man should maintain that this is not the contradictory, then the
|
|
proposition 'it may not be'.
|
|
|
|
Now both of these are false of that which necessarily is. At the
|
|
same time, it is thought that if a thing may be cut it may also not be
|
|
cut, if a thing may be it may also not be, and thus it would follow
|
|
that a thing which must necessarily be may possibly not be; which is
|
|
false. It is evident, then, that it is not always the case that that
|
|
which may be or may walk possesses also a potentiality in the other
|
|
direction. There are exceptions. In the first place we must except
|
|
those things which possess a potentiality not in accordance with a
|
|
rational principle, as fire possesses the potentiality of giving out
|
|
heat, that is, an irrational capacity. Those potentialities which
|
|
involve a rational principle are potentialities of more than one
|
|
result, that is, of contrary results; those that are irrational are
|
|
not always thus constituted. As I have said, fire cannot both heat and
|
|
not heat, neither has anything that is always actual any twofold
|
|
potentiality. Yet some even of those potentialities which are
|
|
irrational admit of opposite results. However, thus much has been said
|
|
to emphasize the truth that it is not every potentiality which
|
|
admits of opposite results, even where the word is used always in
|
|
the same sense.
|
|
|
|
But in some cases the word is used equivocally. For the term
|
|
'possible' is ambiguous, being used in the one case with reference
|
|
to facts, to that which is actualized, as when a man is said to find
|
|
walking possible because he is actually walking, and generally when
|
|
a capacity is predicated because it is actually realized; in the other
|
|
case, with reference to a state in which realization is
|
|
conditionally practicable, as when a man is said to find walking
|
|
possible because under certain conditions he would walk. This last
|
|
sort of potentiality belongs only to that which can be in motion,
|
|
the former can exist also in the case of that which has not this
|
|
power. Both of that which is walking and is actual, and of that
|
|
which has the capacity though not necessarily realized, it is true
|
|
to say that it is not impossible that it should walk (or, in the other
|
|
case, that it should be), but while we cannot predicate this latter
|
|
kind of potentiality of that which is necessary in the unqualified
|
|
sense of the word, we can predicate the former.
|
|
|
|
Our conclusion, then, is this: that since the universal is
|
|
consequent upon the particular, that which is necessary is also
|
|
possible, though not in every sense in which the word may be used.
|
|
|
|
We may perhaps state that necessity and its absence are the
|
|
initial principles of existence and non-existence, and that all else
|
|
must be regarded as posterior to these.
|
|
|
|
It is plain from what has been said that that which is of
|
|
necessity is actual. Thus, if that which is eternal is prior,
|
|
actuality also is prior to potentiality. Some things are actualities
|
|
without potentiality, namely, the primary substances; a second class
|
|
consists of those things which are actual but also potential, whose
|
|
actuality is in nature prior to their potentiality, though posterior
|
|
in time; a third class comprises those things which are never
|
|
actualized, but are pure potentialities.
|
|
|
|
14
|
|
|
|
The question arises whether an affirmation finds its contrary in a
|
|
denial or in another affirmation; whether the proposition 'every man
|
|
is just' finds its contrary in the proposition 'no man is just', or in
|
|
the proposition 'every man is unjust'. Take the propositions
|
|
'Callias is just', 'Callias is not just', 'Callias is unjust'; we have
|
|
to discover which of these form contraries.
|
|
|
|
Now if the spoken word corresponds with the judgement of the mind,
|
|
and if, in thought, that judgement is the contrary of another, which
|
|
pronounces a contrary fact, in the way, for instance, in which the
|
|
judgement 'every man is just' pronounces a contrary to that pronounced
|
|
by the judgement 'every man is unjust', the same must needs hold
|
|
good with regard to spoken affirmations.
|
|
|
|
But if, in thought, it is not the judgement which pronounces a
|
|
contrary fact that is the contrary of another, then one affirmation
|
|
will not find its contrary in another, but rather in the corresponding
|
|
denial. We must therefore consider which true judgement is the
|
|
contrary of the false, that which forms the denial of the false
|
|
judgement or that which affirms the contrary fact.
|
|
|
|
Let me illustrate. There is a true judgement concerning that which
|
|
is good, that it is good; another, a false judgement, that it is not
|
|
good; and a third, which is distinct, that it is bad. Which of these
|
|
two is contrary to the true? And if they are one and the same, which
|
|
mode of expression forms the contrary?
|
|
|
|
It is an error to suppose that judgements are to be defined as
|
|
contrary in virtue of the fact that they have contrary subjects; for
|
|
the judgement concerning a good thing, that it is good, and that
|
|
concerning a bad thing, that it is bad, may be one and the same, and
|
|
whether they are so or not, they both represent the truth. Yet the
|
|
subjects here are contrary. But judgements are not contrary because
|
|
they have contrary subjects, but because they are to the contrary
|
|
effect.
|
|
|
|
Now if we take the judgement that that which is good is good, and
|
|
another that it is not good, and if there are at the same time other
|
|
attributes, which do not and cannot belong to the good, we must
|
|
nevertheless refuse to treat as the contraries of the true judgement
|
|
those which opine that some other attribute subsists which does not
|
|
subsist, as also those that opine that some other attribute does not
|
|
subsist which does subsist, for both these classes of judgement are of
|
|
unlimited content.
|
|
|
|
Those judgements must rather be termed contrary to the true
|
|
judgements, in which error is present. Now these judgements are
|
|
those which are concerned with the starting points of generation,
|
|
and generation is the passing from one extreme to its opposite;
|
|
therefore error is a like transition.
|
|
|
|
Now that which is good is both good and not bad. The first quality
|
|
is part of its essence, the second accidental; for it is by accident
|
|
that it is not bad. But if that true judgement is most really true,
|
|
which concerns the subject's intrinsic nature, then that false
|
|
judgement likewise is most really false, which concerns its
|
|
intrinsic nature. Now the judgement that that is good is not good is a
|
|
false judgement concerning its intrinsic nature, the judgement that it
|
|
is bad is one concerning that which is accidental. Thus the
|
|
judgement which denies the true judgement is more really false than
|
|
that which positively asserts the presence of the contrary quality.
|
|
But it is the man who forms that judgement which is contrary to the
|
|
true who is most thoroughly deceived, for contraries are among the
|
|
things which differ most widely within the same class. If then of
|
|
the two judgements one is contrary to the true judgement, but that
|
|
which is contradictory is the more truly contrary, then the latter, it
|
|
seems, is the real contrary. The judgement that that which is good
|
|
is bad is composite. For presumably the man who forms that judgement
|
|
must at the same time understand that that which is good is not good.
|
|
|
|
Further, the contradictory is either always the contrary or never;
|
|
therefore, if it must necessarily be so in all other cases, our
|
|
conclusion in the case just dealt with would seem to be correct. Now
|
|
where terms have no contrary, that judgement is false, which forms the
|
|
negative of the true; for instance, he who thinks a man is not a man
|
|
forms a false judgement. If then in these cases the negative is the
|
|
contrary, then the principle is universal in its application.
|
|
|
|
Again, the judgement that that which is not good is not good is
|
|
parallel with the judgement that that which is good is good. Besides
|
|
these there is the judgement that that which is good is not good,
|
|
parallel with the judgement that that that is not good is good. Let us
|
|
consider, therefore, what would form the contrary of the true
|
|
judgement that that which is not good is not good. The judgement
|
|
that it is bad would, of course, fail to meet the case, since two true
|
|
judgements are never contrary and this judgement might be true at
|
|
the same time as that with which it is connected. For since some
|
|
things which are not good are bad, both judgements may be true. Nor is
|
|
the judgement that it is not bad the contrary, for this too might be
|
|
true, since both qualities might be predicated of the same subject. It
|
|
remains, therefore, that of the judgement concerning that which is not
|
|
good, that it is not good, the contrary judgement is that it is
|
|
good; for this is false. In the same way, moreover, the judgement
|
|
concerning that which is good, that it is not good, is the contrary of
|
|
the judgement that it is good.
|
|
|
|
It is evident that it will make no difference if we universalize the
|
|
positive judgement, for the universal negative judgement will form the
|
|
contrary. For instance, the contrary of the judgement that
|
|
everything that is good is good is that nothing that is good is
|
|
good. For the judgement that that which is good is good, if the
|
|
subject be understood in a universal sense, is equivalent to the
|
|
judgement that whatever is good is good, and this is identical with
|
|
the judgement that everything that is good is good. We may deal
|
|
similarly with judgements concerning that which is not good.
|
|
|
|
If therefore this is the rule with judgements, and if spoken
|
|
affirmations and denials are judgements expressed in words, it is
|
|
plain that the universal denial is the contrary of the affirmation
|
|
about the same subject. Thus the propositions 'everything good is
|
|
good', 'every man is good', have for their contraries the propositions
|
|
'nothing good is good', 'no man is good'. The contradictory
|
|
propositions, on the other hand, are 'not everything good is good',
|
|
'not every man is good'.
|
|
|
|
It is evident, also, that neither true judgements nor true
|
|
propositions can be contrary the one to the other. For whereas, when
|
|
two propositions are true, a man may state both at the same time
|
|
without inconsistency, contrary propositions are those which state
|
|
contrary conditions, and contrary conditions cannot subsist at one and
|
|
the same time in the same subject.
|
|
|
|
THE END
|
|
.
|